Causality conditions are classifications of
Lorentzian manifolds according to the types of
causal structures they admit.
In the study of
spacetime
In physics, spacetime, also called the space-time continuum, is a mathematical model that fuses the three dimensions of space and the one dimension of time into a single four-dimensional continuum. Spacetime diagrams are useful in visualiz ...
s, there exists a hierarchy of causality conditions which are important in proving mathematical theorems about the global structure of such manifolds.
These conditions were collected during the late 1970s.
[E. Minguzzi and M. Sanchez, ''The causal hierarchy of spacetimes'' in H. Baum and D. Alekseevsky (eds.), vol. Recent developments in pseudo-Riemannian geometry, ESI Lect. Math. Phys., (Eur. Math. Soc. Publ. House, Zurich, 2008), pp. 299–358, , arXiv:gr-qc/0609119]
The weaker the causality condition on a spacetime, the more ''unphysical'' the spacetime is. Spacetimes with
closed timelike curves, for example, present severe interpretational difficulties. See the
grandfather paradox.
It is reasonable to believe that any physical spacetime will satisfy the strongest causality condition:
global hyperbolicity. For such spacetimes the equations in
general relativity
General relativity, also known as the general theory of relativity, and as Einstein's theory of gravity, is the differential geometry, geometric theory of gravitation published by Albert Einstein in 1915 and is the current description of grav ...
can be posed as an
initial value problem on a
Cauchy surface.
The hierarchy
There is a hierarchy of causality conditions, each one of which is strictly stronger than the previous. This is sometimes called the causal ladder. The conditions, from weakest to strongest, are:
* Non-totally vicious
* Chronological
* Causal
* Distinguishing
* Strongly causal
* Stably causal
* Causally continuous
* Causally simple
* Globally hyperbolic
Given are the definitions of these causality conditions for a Lorentzian manifold
. Where two or more are given they are equivalent.
Notation:
*
denotes the
chronological relation.
*
denotes the
causal relation.
(See
causal structure for definitions of
,
and
,
.)
Non-totally vicious
* For some points
we have
.
Chronological
* There are no closed chronological (timelike) curves.
* The
chronological relation is
irreflexive:
for all
.
Causal
* There are no closed causal (non-spacelike) curves.
* If both
and
then
Distinguishing
Past-distinguishing
* Two points
which share the same chronological past are the same point:
::
* Equivalently, for any neighborhood
of
there exists a neighborhood
such that no past-directed non-spacelike curve from
intersects
more than once.
Future-distinguishing
* Two points
which share the same chronological future are the same point:
::
* Equivalently, for any neighborhood
of
there exists a neighborhood
such that no future-directed non-spacelike curve from
intersects
more than once.
Strongly causal
* For every neighborhood
of
there exists a neighborhood
through which no timelike curve passes more than once.
* For every neighborhood
of
there exists a neighborhood
that is causally convex in
(and thus in
).
* The
Alexandrov topology
In general topology, an Alexandrov topology is a topology in which the intersection of an ''arbitrary'' family of open sets is open (while the definition of a topology only requires this for a ''finite'' family). Equivalently, an Alexandrov top ...
agrees with the manifold topology.
Stably causal
For each of the weaker causality conditions defined above, there are some manifolds satisfying the condition which can be made to violate it by arbitrarily small
perturbations of the metric. A spacetime is stably causal if it cannot be made to contain closed
causal curves by any perturbation smaller than some arbitrary finite magnitude.
Stephen Hawking showed
[S.W. Hawking]
''The existence of cosmic time functions''
Proc. R. Soc. Lond. (1969), A308, 433 that this is equivalent to:
* There exists a ''global time function'' on
. This is a
scalar field
on
whose
gradient is everywhere timelike and future-directed. This ''global time function'' gives us a stable way to distinguish between future and past for each point of the spacetime (and so we have no causal violations).
Globally hyperbolic
*
is
strongly causal and every set
(for points
) is
compact.
Robert Geroch showed
[R. Geroch]
''Domain of Dependence''
J. Math. Phys. (1970) 11, 437–449 that a spacetime is globally hyperbolic
if and only if
In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either bo ...
there exists a Cauchy surface for
. This means that:
*
is topologically equivalent to
for some
Cauchy surface (Here
denotes the
real line
A number line is a graphical representation of a straight line that serves as spatial representation of numbers, usually graduated like a ruler with a particular origin (geometry), origin point representing the number zero and evenly spaced mark ...
).
See also
*
Spacetime
In physics, spacetime, also called the space-time continuum, is a mathematical model that fuses the three dimensions of space and the one dimension of time into a single four-dimensional continuum. Spacetime diagrams are useful in visualiz ...
*
Lorentzian manifold
*
Causal structure
*
Globally hyperbolic manifold
*
Closed timelike curve
References
*
*
*{{Cite arXiv , eprint=gr-qc/0609119v1 , last1=Minguzzi , first1=E. , last2=Sanchez , first2=M. , title=The causal hierarchy of spacetimes , date=2006
Lorentzian manifolds
Theory of relativity
General relativity
Theoretical physics