
In
logic
Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
and
mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, the logical biconditional, also known as material biconditional or equivalence or bidirectional implication or biimplication or bientailment, is the
logical connective used to conjoin two statements
and
to form the statement "
if and only if
In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either bo ...
" (often abbreviated as "
iff
"
), where
is known as the ''
antecedent'', and
the ''
consequent''.
Nowadays, notations to represent equivalence include
.
is logically equivalent to both
and
, and the
XNOR (exclusive NOR)
Boolean operator, which means "both or neither".
Semantically, the only case where a logical biconditional is different from a
material conditional
The material conditional (also known as material implication) is a binary operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol \to is interpreted as material implication, a formula P \to Q is true unless P is true and Q is false.
M ...
is the case where the hypothesis (antecedent) is false but the conclusion (consequent) is true. In this case, the result is true for the conditional, but false for the biconditional.
In the conceptual interpretation, means "All 's are 's and all 's are 's". In other words, the sets and coincide: they are identical. However, this does not mean that and need to have the same meaning (e.g., could be "equiangular trilateral" and could be "equilateral triangle"). When phrased as a sentence, the antecedent is the ''subject'' and the consequent is the ''predicate'' of a
universal affirmative proposition (e.g., in the phrase "all men are mortal", "men" is the subject and "mortal" is the predicate).
In the propositional interpretation,
means that implies and implies ; in other words, the propositions are
logically equivalent, in the sense that both are either jointly true or jointly false. Again, this does not mean that they need to have the same meaning, as could be "the triangle ABC has two equal sides" and could be "the triangle ABC has two equal angles". In general, the antecedent is the ''premise'', or the ''cause'', and the consequent is the ''consequence''. When an implication is translated by a ''hypothetical'' (or ''conditional'') judgment, the antecedent is called the ''hypothesis'' (or the ''condition'') and the consequent is called the ''thesis''.
A common way of demonstrating a biconditional of the form
is to demonstrate that
and
separately (due to its equivalence to the conjunction of the two converse
conditionals
). Yet another way of demonstrating the same biconditional is by demonstrating that
and
.
When both members of the biconditional are propositions, it can be separated into two conditionals, of which one is called a ''theorem'' and the other its ''reciprocal''. Thus whenever a theorem and its reciprocal are true, we have a biconditional. A simple theorem gives rise to an implication, whose antecedent is the ''hypothesis'' and whose consequent is the ''thesis'' of the theorem.
It is often said that the hypothesis is the ''
sufficient condition'' of the thesis, and that the thesis is the ''
necessary condition'' of the hypothesis. That is, it is sufficient that the hypothesis be true for the thesis to be true, while it is necessary that the thesis be true if the hypothesis were true. When a theorem and its reciprocal are true, its hypothesis is said to be the
necessary and sufficient condition of the thesis. That is, the hypothesis is both the cause and the consequence of the thesis at the same time.
Notations
Notations to represent equivalence used in history include:
*
in
George Boole
George Boole ( ; 2 November 1815 – 8 December 1864) was a largely self-taught English mathematician, philosopher and logician, most of whose short career was spent as the first professor of mathematics at Queen's College, Cork in Ireland. H ...
in 1847.
Although Boole used
mainly on classes, he also considered the case that
are propositions in
, and at the time
is equivalence.
*
in
Frege in 1879;
*
in
Bernays in 1918;
*
in
Hilbert
David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician and philosophy of mathematics, philosopher of mathematics and one of the most influential mathematicians of his time.
Hilbert discovered and developed a broad ...
in 1927 (while he used
as the main symbol in the article);
*
in
Hilbert
David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician and philosophy of mathematics, philosopher of mathematics and one of the most influential mathematicians of his time.
Hilbert discovered and developed a broad ...
and
Ackermann in 1928
(they also introduced
while they use
as the main symbol in the whole book;
is adopted by many followers such as Becker in 1933
);
*
(prefix) in
Łukasiewicz in 1929
and
(prefix) in
Łukasiewicz in 1951;
*
in
Heyting in 1930;
*
in
Bourbaki in 1954;
*
in Chazal in 1996;
and so on. Somebody else also use
or
occasionally.
Definition
Logical equality (also known as biconditional) is an
operation on two
logical values, typically the values of two
proposition
A proposition is a statement that can be either true or false. It is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields. Propositions are the object s denoted by declarative sentences; for example, "The sky ...
s, that produces a value of ''true'' if and only if both operands are false or both operands are true.
Truth table
The following is a truth table for
:
When more than two statements are involved, combining them with
might be ambiguous. For example, the statement
:
may be interpreted as
:
,
or may be interpreted as saying that all are ''jointly true or jointly false'':
:
As it turns out, these two statements are only the same when zero or two arguments are involved. In fact, the following truth tables only show the same bit pattern in the line with no argument and in the lines with two arguments:

The left Venn diagram below, and the lines ''(AB )'' in these matrices represent the same operation.
Venn diagrams
Red areas stand for true (as in for ''
and'').
Properties
Commutativity: Yes
Associativity: Yes
Distributivity: Biconditional doesn't distribute over any binary function (not even itself), but
logical disjunction distributes over biconditional.
Idempotency: No
Monotonicity: No
Truth-preserving: Yes
When all inputs are true, the output is true.
Falsehood-preserving: No
When all inputs are false, the output is not false.
Walsh spectrum: (2,0,0,2)
Non
linearity
In mathematics, the term ''linear'' is used in two distinct senses for two different properties:
* linearity of a '' function'' (or '' mapping'');
* linearity of a '' polynomial''.
An example of a linear function is the function defined by f(x) ...
: 0 (the function is linear)
Rules of inference
Like all connectives in first-order logic, the biconditional has rules of inference that govern its use in formal proofs.
Biconditional introduction
Biconditional introduction allows one to infer that if B follows from A and A follows from B, then A
if and only if
In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either bo ...
B.
For example, from the statements "if I'm breathing, then I'm alive" and "if I'm alive, then I'm breathing", it can be inferred that "I'm breathing if and only if I'm alive" or equivalently, "I'm alive if and only if I'm breathing." Or more schematically:
B → A
A → B
∴ A ↔ B
B → A
A → B
∴ B ↔ A
Biconditional elimination
Biconditional elimination allows one to infer a
conditional from a biconditional: if A
↔ B is true, then one may infer either A
→ B, or B
→ A.
For example, if it is true that I'm breathing
if and only if
In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either bo ...
I'm alive, then it's true that ''if'' I'm breathing, then I'm alive; likewise, it's true that ''if'' I'm alive, then I'm breathing. Or more schematically:
A ↔ B
∴ A → B
A ↔ B
∴ B → A
Colloquial usage
One unambiguous way of stating a biconditional in plain English is to adopt the form "''b'' if ''a'' and ''a'' if ''b''"—if the standard form "''a'' if and only if ''b''" is not used. Slightly more formally, one could also say that "''b'' implies ''a'' and ''a'' implies ''b''", or "''a'' is necessary and sufficient for ''b''". The plain English "if'" may sometimes be used as a biconditional (especially in the context of a mathematical definition
[In fact, such is the style adopted by Wikipedia's manual of style in mathematics.]). In which case, one must take into consideration the surrounding context when interpreting these words.
For example, the statement "I'll buy you a new wallet if you need one" may be interpreted as a biconditional, since the speaker doesn't intend a valid outcome to be buying the wallet whether or not the wallet is needed (as in a conditional). However, "it is cloudy if it is raining" is generally not meant as a biconditional, since it can still be cloudy even if it is not raining.
See also
*
If and only if
In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either bo ...
*
Logical equivalence
In logic and mathematics, statements p and q are said to be logically equivalent if they have the same truth value in every model. The logical equivalence of p and q is sometimes expressed as p \equiv q, p :: q, \textsfpq, or p \iff q, depending ...
*
Logical equality
*
XNOR gate
*
Biconditional elimination
*
Biconditional introduction
References
External links
*
{{DEFAULTSORT:Logical Biconditional
Biconditional
Equivalence (mathematics)