HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, the axiom of dependent choice, denoted by \mathsf , is a weak form of the axiom of choice ( \mathsf ) that is still sufficient to develop much of real analysis. It was introduced by Paul Bernays in a 1942 article in reverse mathematics that explores which set-theoretic axioms are needed to develop analysis."The foundation of analysis does not require the full generality of set theory but can be accomplished within a more restricted frame." The axiom of dependent choice is stated on p. 86.


Formal statement

A homogeneous relation R on X is called a total relation if for every a \in X, there exists some b \in X such that a\,R~b is true. The axiom of dependent choice can be stated as follows: For every nonempty set X and every total relation R on X, there exists a sequence (x_n)_ in X such that :x_n\, R~x_ for all n \in \N. In fact, ''x''0 may be taken to be any desired element of ''X''. (To see this, apply the axiom as stated above to the set of finite sequences that start with ''x''0 and in which subsequent terms are in relation R, together with the total relation on this set of the second sequence being obtained from the first by appending a single term.) If the set X above is restricted to be the set of all real numbers, then the resulting axiom is denoted by \mathsf_.


Use

Even without such an axiom, for any n, one can use ordinary mathematical induction to form the first n terms of such a sequence. The axiom of dependent choice says that we can form a whole ( countably infinite) sequence this way. The axiom \mathsf is the fragment of \mathsf that is required to show the existence of a sequence constructed by transfinite recursion of countable length, if it is necessary to make a choice at each step and if some of those choices cannot be made independently of previous choices.


Equivalent statements

Over \mathsf ( Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice), \mathsf is equivalent to the Baire category theorem for complete metric spaces. It is also equivalent over \mathsf to the downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem.Moore states that "Principle of Dependent Choices \Rightarrow Löwenheim–Skolem theorem" — that is, \mathsf implies the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem. ''See'' table \mathsf is also equivalent over \mathsf to the statement that every pruned tree with \omega levels has a branch (''proof below''). Furthermore, \mathsf is equivalent to a weakened form of Zorn's lemma; specifically \mathsf is equivalent to the statement that any partial order such that every well-ordered chain is finite and bounded, must have a maximal element.


Relation with other axioms

Unlike full \mathsf , \mathsf is insufficient to prove (given \mathsf ) that there is a non-measurable set of real numbers, or that there is a set of real numbers without the property of Baire or without the perfect set property. This follows because the Solovay model satisfies \mathsf + \mathsf , and every set of real numbers in this model is Lebesgue measurable, has the Baire property and has the perfect set property. The axiom of dependent choice implies the axiom of countable choice and is strictly stronger.For a proof that the Axiom of Countable Choice does not imply the Axiom of Dependent Choice ''see'' It is possible to generalize the axiom to produce transfinite sequences. If these are allowed to be arbitrarily long, then it becomes equivalent to the full axiom of choice.


Notes


References

* {{Set theory Axiom of choice