HOME
The Info List - Thomas Aquinas


--- Advertisement ---



Catholicism portal Philosophy portal

v t e

Part of a series on

Christianity

Jesus Christ

Jesus
Jesus
in Christianity Son of God Virgin birth Ministry Crucifixion Resurrection

Bible Foundations

Old Testament New Testament Gospel Canon Books Church Creed New Covenant

Theology

God Trinity

Father Son Holy Spirit

Apologetics Baptism Christology History of theology Mission Patriology Pneumatology Salvation

History Tradition

Mary Apostles Peter Paul Fathers Early Christianity Constantine Councils Augustine East–West Schism Crusades Aquinas Luther Reformation Radical Reformation

Related topics

Art Holidays (list) Criticism Culture Ecumenism Liturgy Music Other religions Prayer Sermon Symbolism

Denominations Groups

Western

Adventist Anabaptist Anglican Baptist Calvinist Catholic Charismatic Evangelical Lutheran Methodist Pentecostal Protestant

Eastern

Eastern Orthodox Oriental Orthodox Assyrian

Nontrinitarian

Jehovah's Witness Latter Day Saint Oneness Pentecostal

  Christianity
Christianity
portal

v t e

Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
OP (/əˈkwaɪnəs/; Italian: Tommaso d'Aquino, lit. 'Thomas of Aquino'; 1225 – 7 March 1274) was an Italian[6][7] Dominican friar, Catholic priest, and Doctor of the Church. He was an immensely influential philosopher, theologian, and jurist in the tradition of scholasticism, within which he is also known as the Doctor Angelicus and the Doctor Communis.[8] The name Aquinas identifies his ancestral origins in the county of Aquino in present-day Lazio. He was the foremost classical proponent of natural theology and the father of Thomism; of which he argued that reason is found in God. His influence on Western thought
Western thought
is considerable, and much of modern philosophy developed or opposed his ideas, particularly in the areas of ethics, natural law, metaphysics, and political theory. Unlike many currents in the Church of the time,[9] Thomas embraced several ideas put forward by Aristotle—whom he called "the Philosopher"—and attempted to synthesize Aristotelian philosophy with the principles of Christianity.[10] His best-known works are the Disputed Questions on Truth (1256-59), the Summa contra Gentiles
Summa contra Gentiles
(1259-1265), and the Summa Theologiae (1265-1274). His commentaries on Scripture
Scripture
and on Aristotle also form an important part of his body of work. Furthermore, Thomas is distinguished for his eucharistic hymns, which form a part of the Church's liturgy.[11] The Catholic Church
Catholic Church
honors Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
as a saint and regards him as the model teacher for those studying for the priesthood, and indeed the highest expression of both natural reason and speculative theology. In modern times, under papal directives, the study of his works was long used as a core of the required program of study for those seeking ordination as priests or deacons, as well as for those in religious formation and for other students of the sacred disciplines (philosophy, Catholic theology, church history, liturgy, and canon law).[12] Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
is considered one of the Catholic Church's greatest theologians and philosophers. Pope Benedict XV
Pope Benedict XV
declared: "This (Dominican) Order ... acquired new luster when the Church declared the teaching of Thomas to be her own and that Doctor, honored with the special praises of the Pontiffs, the master and patron of Catholic schools."[13] The English philosopher Anthony Kenny considers Thomas to be "one of the dozen greatest philosophers of the western world".[14]

Contents

1 Biography

1.1 Early life (1225–1244) 1.2 Paris, Cologne, Albert Magnus, and first Paris regency (1245–1259) 1.3 Naples, Orvieto, Rome (1259–1268) 1.4 Quarrelsome second Paris regency (1269–1272) 1.5 Final days and "straw" (1272–1274) 1.6 Claims of levitation 1.7 Condemnation of 1277 1.8 Canonization

2 Philosophy

2.1 Commentaries on Aristotle 2.2 Epistemology 2.3 Ethics 2.4 Political order 2.5 Psychology

3 Theology

3.1 Revelation

3.1.1 Preserving nature within grace

3.2 Creation 3.3 Just war

3.3.1 School of Salamanca

3.4 Nature
Nature
of God 3.5 Nature
Nature
of Sin 3.6 Nature
Nature
of the Trinity 3.7 Prima causa
Prima causa
(first cause) 3.8 Nature
Nature
of Jesus
Jesus
Christ 3.9 Goal of human life 3.10 Treatment of heretics 3.11 Development of a new doctrinal belief in the actual power of witches 3.12 Thoughts on afterlife and resurrection

4 Modern influence 5 Russell's criticism of Thomas as philosopher 6 Works 7 See also

7.1 Thomists

8 Notes 9 References 10 Further reading 11 External links

11.1 Biographies 11.2 On his thought 11.3 By Thomas Aquinas

Biography[edit] Early life (1225–1244)[edit] Thomas was most probably born in the castle of Roccasecca, located in Aquino, old county of the Kingdom of Sicily
Kingdom of Sicily
(present-day Lazio
Lazio
region, Italy), c. 1225,[citation needed] According to some authors,[who?] he was born in the castle of his father, Landulf of Aquino. Though he did not belong to the most powerful branch of the family, Landulf of Aquino was a man of means. As a knight in the service of King Roger II, he held the title miles. Thomas's mother, Theodora, belonged to the Rossi branch of the Neapolitan Caracciolo family.[15] Landulf's brother Sinibald was abbot of the first Benedictine monastery at Monte Cassino. While the rest of the family's sons pursued military careers,[16] the family intended for Thomas to follow his uncle into the abbacy;[17] this would have been a normal career path for a younger son of southern Italian nobility.[18] At the age of five Thomas began his early education at Monte Cassino but after the military conflict between the Emperor Frederick II and Pope Gregory IX
Pope Gregory IX
spilled into the abbey in early 1239, Landulf and Theodora had Thomas enrolled at the studium generale (university) recently established by Frederick in Naples.[19] It was here that Thomas was probably introduced to Aristotle, Averroes
Averroes
and Maimonides, all of whom would influence his theological philosophy.[20] It was also during his study at Naples
Naples
that Thomas came under the influence of John of St. Julian, a Dominican preacher in Naples, who was part of the active effort by the Dominican order to recruit devout followers.[21] There his teacher in arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and music was Petrus de Ibernia.[22]

The Castle of Monte San Giovanni Campano

At the age of nineteen Thomas resolved to join the recently founded Dominican Order. Thomas's change of heart did not please his family.[23] In an attempt to prevent Theodora's interference in Thomas's choice, the Dominicans arranged to move Thomas to Rome, and from Rome, to Paris.[24] However, while on his journey to Rome, per Theodora's instructions, his brothers seized him as he was drinking from a spring and took him back to his parents at the castle of Monte San Giovanni Campano.[24] Thomas was held prisoner for almost one year in the family castles at Monte San Giovanni and Roccasecca
Roccasecca
in an attempt to prevent him from assuming the Dominican habit and to push him into renouncing his new aspiration.[20] Political concerns prevented the Pope
Pope
from ordering Thomas's release, which had the effect of extending Thomas's detention.[25] Thomas passed this time of trial tutoring his sisters and communicating with members of the Dominican Order.[20] Family members became desperate to dissuade Thomas, who remained determined to join the Dominicans. At one point, two of his brothers resorted to the measure of hiring a prostitute to seduce him. According to legend, Thomas drove her away wielding a fire iron. That night two angels appeared to him as he slept and strengthened his determination to remain celibate.[26]

Diego Velázquez, Thomas is girded by angels with a mystical belt of purity after his proof of chastity

By 1244, seeing that all of her attempts to dissuade Thomas had failed, Theodora sought to save the family's dignity, arranging for Thomas to escape at night through his window. In her mind, a secret escape from detention was less damaging than an open surrender to the Dominicans. Thomas was sent first to Naples
Naples
and then to Rome to meet Johannes von Wildeshausen, the Master General of the Dominican Order.[27] Paris, Cologne, Albert Magnus, and first Paris regency (1245–1259)[edit] In 1245 Thomas was sent to study at the Faculty of the Arts at the University of Paris, where he most likely met Dominican scholar Albertus Magnus,[28] then the holder of the Chair of Theology
Theology
at the College of St. James in Paris.[29] When Albertus was sent by his superiors to teach at the new studium generale at Cologne in 1248,[28] Thomas followed him, declining Pope
Pope
Innocent IV's offer to appoint him abbot of Monte Cassino
Monte Cassino
as a Dominican.[17] Albertus then appointed the reluctant Thomas magister studentium.[18] Because Thomas was quiet and didn't speak much, some of his fellow students thought he was slow. But Albertus prophetically exclaimed: "You call him the dumb ox, but in his teaching he will one day produce such a bellowing that it will be heard throughout the world."[17] Thomas taught in Cologne as an apprentice professor (baccalaureus biblicus), instructing students on the books of the Old Testament
Old Testament
and writing Expositio super Isaiam ad litteram (Literal Commentary on Isaiah), Postilla super Ieremiam (Commentary on Jeremiah) and Postilla super Threnos (Commentary on Lamentations).[30] Then in 1252 he returned to Paris to study for the master's degree in theology. He lectured on the Bible
Bible
as an apprentice professor, and upon becoming a baccalaureus Sententiarum (bachelor of the Sentences)[31] devoted his final three years of study to commenting on Peter Lombard's Sentences. In the first of his four theological syntheses, Thomas composed a massive commentary on the Sentences
Sentences
titled Scriptum super libros Sententiarium (Commentary on the Sentences). Aside from his masters writings, he wrote De ente et essentia (On Being and Essence) for his fellow Dominicans in Paris.[17] In the spring of 1256 Thomas was appointed regent master in theology at Paris and one of his first works upon assuming this office was Contra impugnantes Dei cultum et religionem (Against Those Who Assail the Worship of God and Religion), defending the mendicant orders, which had come under attack by William of Saint-Amour.[32] During his tenure from 1256 to 1259, Thomas wrote numerous works, including: Questiones disputatae de veritate (Disputed Questions on Truth), a collection of twenty-nine disputed questions on aspects of faith and the human condition[33] prepared for the public university debates he presided over on Lent
Lent
and Advent;[34] Quaestiones quodlibetales (Quodlibetal Questions), a collection of his responses to questions posed to him by the academic audience;[33] and both Expositio super librum Boethii De trinitate (Commentary on Boethius's De trinitate) and Expositio super librum Boethii De hebdomadibus (Commentary on Boethius's De hebdomadibus), commentaries on the works of 6th-century Roman philosopher Boethius.[35] By the end of his regency, Thomas was working on one of his most famous works, Summa contra Gentiles.[36] Naples, Orvieto, Rome (1259–1268)[edit] In 1259 Thomas completed his first regency at the studium generale and left Paris so that others in his order could gain this teaching experience. He returned to Naples
Naples
where he was appointed as general preacher by the provincial chapter of 29 September 1260. In September 1261 he was called to Orvieto
Orvieto
as conventual lector responsible for the pastoral formation of the friars unable to attend a studium generale. In Orvieto
Orvieto
Thomas completed his Summa contra Gentiles, wrote the Catena aurea (The Golden Chain),[37] and produced works for Pope
Pope
Urban IV such as the liturgy for the newly created feast of Corpus Christi and the Contra errores graecorum (Against the Errors of the Greeks).[36] Some of the hymns that Thomas wrote for the feast of Corpus Christi are still sung today, such as the Pange lingua, Tantum ergo, and Panis angelicus. Modern scholarship has confirmed that Thomas was indeed the author of these texts, a point that some had contested.[38] In February 1265 the newly elected Pope Clement IV
Pope Clement IV
summoned Thomas to Rome to serve as papal theologian. This same year he was ordered by the Dominican Chapter of Agnani[39] to teach at the studium conventuale at the Roman convent of Santa Sabina, founded some years before, in 1222.[40] The studium at Santa Sabina
Santa Sabina
now became an experiment for the Dominicans, the Order's first studium provinciale, an intermediate school between the studium conventuale and the studium generale. Prior to this time the Roman Province had offered no specialized education of any sort, no arts, no philosophy; only simple convent schools, with their basic courses in theology for resident friars, were functioning in Tuscany and the meridionale during the first several decades of the order's life. But the new studium at Santa Sabina
Santa Sabina
was to be a school for the province", a studium provinciale.[41] Tolomeo da Lucca, an associate and early biographer of Thomas, tells us that at the Santa Sabina
Santa Sabina
studium Thomas taught the full range of philosophical subjects, both moral and natural.[42] While at the Santa Sabina
Santa Sabina
studium provinciale Thomas began his most famous work, the Summa theologiae,[37] which he conceived of specifically as suited to beginning students: "Because a doctor of Catholic truth ought not only to teach the proficient, but to him pertains also to instruct beginners. As the Apostle says in 1 Corinthians 3:1–2, as to infants in Christ, I gave you milk to drink, not meat, our proposed intention in this work is to convey those things that pertain to the Christian religion in a way that is fitting to the instruction of beginners."[43] While there he also wrote a variety of other works like his unfinished Compendium Theologiae and Responsio ad fr. Ioannem Vercellensem de articulis 108 sumptis ex opere Petri de Tarentasia (Reply to Brother John of Vercelli Regarding 108 Articles Drawn from the Work of Peter of Tarentaise).[35] In his position as head of the studium Thomas conducted a series of important disputations on the power of God, which he compiled into his De potentia.[44] Nicholas Brunacci [1240–1322] was among Thomas's students at the Santa Sabina
Santa Sabina
studium provinciale and later at the Paris studium generale. In November 1268 he was with Thomas and his associate and secretary Reginald of Piperno, as they left Viterbo on their way to Paris to begin the academic year.[45] Another student of Thomas's at the Santa Sabina studium provinciale was Blessed Tommasello da Perugia.[46] Thomas remained at the studium at Santa Sabina
Santa Sabina
from 1265 until he was called back to Paris in 1268 for a second teaching regency.[44] With his departure for Paris in 1268 and the passage of time the pedagogical activities of the studium provinciale at Santa Sabina
Santa Sabina
were divided between two campuses. A new convent of the Order at the Church of Santa Maria sopra Minerva
Santa Maria sopra Minerva
had a modest beginning in 1255 as a community for women converts, but grew rapidly in size and importance after being given over to the Dominicans friars in 1275.[47] In 1288 the theology component of the provincial curriculum for the education of the friars was relocated from the Santa Sabina
Santa Sabina
studium provinciale to the studium conventuale at Santa Maria sopra Minerva, which was redesignated as a studium particularis theologiae.[48] This studium was transformed in the 16th century into the College of Saint
Saint
Thomas (Latin: Collegium Divi Thomæ). In the 20th century the college was relocated to the convent of Saints Dominic and Sixtus and was transformed into the Pontifical University of Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas, Angelicum. Quarrelsome second Paris regency (1269–1272)[edit]

Triumph of St Thomas Aquinas, "Doctor Communis", between Plato
Plato
and Aristotle, Benozzo Gozzoli,1471. Louvre, Paris

In 1268 the Dominican order assigned Thomas to be regent master at the University of Paris
University of Paris
for a second time, a position he held until the spring of 1272. Part of the reason for this sudden reassignment appears to have arisen from the rise of "Averroism" or "radical Aristotelianism" in the universities. In response to these perceived errors, Thomas wrote two works, one of them being De unitate intellectus, contra Averroistas (On the Unity of Intellect, against the Averroists) in which he reprimands Averroism
Averroism
as incompatible with Christian doctrine.[49] During his second regency, he finished the second part of the Summa and wrote De virtutibus and De aeternitate mundi, contra murmurantes (On the Eternity of the World, against Grumblers),[44] the latter of which dealt with controversial Averroist and Aristotelian beginninglessness of the world.[50] Disputes with some important Franciscans
Franciscans
conspired to make his second regency much more difficult and troubled than the first. A year before Thomas re-assumed the regency at the 1266–67 Paris disputations, Franciscan master William of Baglione accused Thomas of encouraging Averroists, most likely counting him as one of the "blind leaders of the blind". Eleonore Stump says, "It has also been persuasively argued that Aquinas's De aeternitate mundi was directed in particular against his Fransiscan colleague in theology, John Pecham."[50] In reality, Thomas was deeply disturbed by the spread of Averroism
Averroism
and was angered when he discovered Siger of Brabant
Siger of Brabant
teaching Averroistic interpretations of Aristotle
Aristotle
to Parisian students.[51] On 10 December 1270, the Bishop of Paris, Etienne Tempier, issued an edict condemning thirteen Aristotelian and Averroistic propositions as heretical and excommunicating anyone who continued to support them.[52] Many in the ecclesiastical community, the so-called Augustinians, were fearful that this introduction of Aristotelianism
Aristotelianism
and the more extreme Averroism
Averroism
might somehow contaminate the purity of the Christian faith. In what appears to be an attempt to counteract the growing fear of Aristotelian thought, Thomas conducted a series of disputations between 1270 and 1272: De virtutibus in communi (On Virtues in General), De virtutibus cardinalibus (On Cardinal Virtues), De spe (On Hope).[53] Final days and "straw" (1272–1274)[edit]

Icon of the crucifixion speaking to Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
is depicted on this stained glass window in Saint
Saint
Patrick Church (Columbus, Ohio)

In 1272 Thomas took leave from the University of Paris
University of Paris
when the Dominicans from his home province called upon him to establish a studium generale wherever he liked and staff it as he pleased. He chose to establish the institution in Naples, and moved there to take his post as regent master.[44] He took his time at Naples
Naples
to work on the third part of the Summa while giving lectures on various religious topics. He also preached to the people of Naples
Naples
every day in Lent, 1273. These sermons on the commandments, the creed, the Our Father, and Hail Mary were very popular.[54] On one occasion, at 1273 at the Dominican convent of Naples
Naples
in the chapel of Saint
Saint
Nicholas,[55] after Matins, Thomas lingered and was seen by the sacristan Domenic of Caserta to be levitating in prayer with tears before an icon of the crucified Christ. Christ said to Thomas, "You have written well of me, Thomas. What reward would you have for your labor?" Thomas responded, "Nothing but you, Lord."[56][57][58] After this exchange something happened, but Thomas never spoke of it or wrote it down. On 6 December 1273, another mystical experience took place. While he was celebrating Mass, he experienced an unusually long ecstasy.[58] Because of what he saw, he abandoned his routine and refused to dictate to his socius Reginald of Piperno. When Reginald begged him to get back to work, Thomas replied: "Reginald, I cannot, because all that I have written seems like straw to me"[59] (mihi videtur ut palea).[60] As a result, the Summa Theologica
Summa Theologica
would remain uncompleted. What exactly triggered Thomas's change in behavior is believed by Catholics to have been some kind of supernatural experience of God.[61] After taking to his bed, he did recover some strength.[62] In 1054 the Great Schism had occurred between the Latin
Latin
Church following the Pope
Pope
(known as the Roman Catholic Church) in the West, and the Patriarchate of Constantinople
Patriarchate of Constantinople
in the East (known as the Eastern Orthodox Church). Looking to find a way to reunite the Eastern Orthodox Church and the Roman Catholic Church, Pope
Pope
Gregory X convened the Second Council of Lyon
Second Council of Lyon
to be held on 1 May 1274 and summoned Thomas to attend.[63] At the meeting, Thomas's work for Pope
Pope
Urban IV concerning the Greeks, Contra errores graecorum, was to be presented.[64] On his way to the Council, riding on a donkey along the Appian Way,[63] he struck his head on the branch of a fallen tree and became seriously ill again. He was then quickly escorted to Monte Cassino
Monte Cassino
to convalesce.[62] After resting for a while, he set out again, but stopped at the Cistercian
Cistercian
Fossanova Abbey
Fossanova Abbey
after again falling ill.[65] The monks nursed him for several days,[66] and as he received his last rites he prayed: "I have written and taught much about this very holy Body, and about the other sacraments in the faith of Christ, and about the Holy Roman Church, to whose correction I expose and submit everything I have written."[67] He died on 7 March 1274[65] while giving commentary on the Song of Songs.[68] Claims of levitation[edit] See also: Saints and levitation For centuries, there have been recurring claims that Thomas had the ability to levitate. For example, G. K. Chesterton
G. K. Chesterton
wrote that, "His experiences included well-attested cases of levitation in ecstasy; and the Blessed Virgin appeared to him, comforting him with the welcome news that he would never be a Bishop."[69] Condemnation of 1277[edit] See also: Condemnations of 1210–1277 In 1277 Étienne Tempier, the same bishop of Paris who had issued the condemnation of 1270, issued another more extensive condemnation. One aim of this condemnation was to clarify that God's absolute power transcended any principles of logic that Aristotle
Aristotle
or Averroes
Averroes
might place on it.[70] More specifically, it contained a list of 219 propositions that the bishop had determined to violate the omnipotence of God, and included in this list were twenty Thomistic propositions. Their inclusion badly damaged Thomas's reputation for many years.[71] In the Divine Comedy, Dante
Dante
sees the glorified soul of Thomas in the Heaven of the Sun with the other great exemplars of religious wisdom.[72] Dante
Dante
asserts that Thomas died by poisoning, on the order of Charles of Anjou;[73] Villani (ix. 218) cites this belief, and the Anonimo Fiorentino
Anonimo Fiorentino
describes the crime and its motive. But the historian Ludovico Antonio Muratori
Ludovico Antonio Muratori
reproduces the account made by one of Thomas's friends, and this version of the story gives no hint of foul play.[74] Thomas's theology had begun its rise to prestige. Two centuries later, in 1567, Pope
Pope
Pius V
Pius V
proclaimed St. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
a Doctor of the Church and ranked his feast with those of the four great Latin fathers: Ambrose, Augustine of Hippo, Jerome
Jerome
and Gregory.[74] At the Council of Trent, Thomas had the honor of having his Summa theologiae placed on the altar alongside the Bible
Bible
and the Decretals.[71][75] In his encyclical of 4 August 1879, Aeterni Patris, Pope
Pope
Leo XIII stated that Thomas Aquinas's theology was a definitive exposition of Catholic doctrine. Thus, he directed the clergy to take the teachings of Thomas as the basis of their theological positions. Leo XIII also decreed that all Catholic seminaries and universities must teach Thomas's doctrines, and where Thomas did not speak on a topic, the teachers were "urged to teach conclusions that were reconcilable with his thinking." In 1880, Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
was declared patron of all Catholic educational establishments.[74] Canonization[edit]

Triumph of St. Thomas Aquinas, "Doctor Angelicus", with saints and angels, Andrea di Bonaiuto, 1366. Basilica of Santa Maria Novella, fresco

When the devil's advocate at his canonization process objected that there were no miracles, one of the cardinals answered, "Tot miraculis, quot articulis"—"there are as many miracles (in his life) as articles (in his Summa)".[75] Fifty years after Thomas's death, on 18 July 1323, Pope
Pope
John XXII, seated in Avignon, pronounced Thomas a saint.[76] A monastery at Naples, near the cathedral of St. Januarius, shows a cell in which he supposedly lived.[74] His remains were placed in the Church of the Jacobins
Church of the Jacobins
in Toulouse
Toulouse
on 28 January 1369. Between 1789 and 1974, they were held in the Basilique de Saint-Sernin, Toulouse. In 1974, they were returned to the Church of the Jacobins, where they have remained ever since. When he was canonized, his feast day was inserted in the General Roman Calendar for celebration on 7 March, the day of his death. Since this date commonly falls within Lent, the 1969 revision of the calendar moved his memorial to 28 January, the date of the translation of his relics to Church of the Jacobins, Toulouse.[77][78] Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
is honored with a feast day in some churches of the Anglican Communion. Philosophy[edit]

Part of a series on

Thomas Aquinas

Thomism

Scholasticism Apophatic theology Divine simplicity Quinque viae Beatific vision Actus purus Sacraments Correspondence theory Hylomorphism Substance theory (ousia) Substantial form Quiddity (essence / accident nature) Peripatetic axiom Principle
Principle
of double effect Cardinal / Theological / Intellectual virtues Natural law

Determinatio

Just war Just price Concupiscence Analytical Thomism

Works

Summa Theologica

Treatise on Law

Summa contra Gentiles Contra Errores Graecorum Commentaries on Aristotle

People

Aristotle St. Paul Pseudo-Dionysius St. Augustine St. Boethius Avicenna Peter Lombard Averroes Maimonides St. Albertus Magnus Reginald of Piperno

Related topics

Pange Lingua Aristotelianism Dominican Order School of Salamanca Catholic theology Doctor of the Church Empiricism Neo-Thomism Æterni Patris

Catholicism portal Philosophy portal

v t e

Main article: Thomism Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
was a theologian and a Scholastic philosopher.[79] However, he never considered himself a philosopher, and criticized philosophers, whom he saw as pagans, for always "falling short of the true and proper wisdom to be found in Christian revelation."[80] With this in mind, Thomas did have respect for Aristotle, so much so that in the Summa, he often cites Aristotle
Aristotle
simply as "the Philosopher." Much of his work bears upon philosophical topics, and in this sense may be characterized as philosophical. Thomas' philosophical thought has exerted enormous influence on subsequent Christian theology, especially that of the Catholic Church, extending to Western philosophy in general. Thomas stands as a vehicle and modifier of Aristotelianism
Aristotelianism
and Neoplatonism. It is said that Thomas modified both Aristotelianism
Aristotelianism
and Neoplatonism
Neoplatonism
by way of heavy reliance on the Pseudo-Dionysius.[citation needed] Commentaries on Aristotle[edit] Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
wrote several important commentaries on Aristotle's works, including On the Soul, Nicomachean Ethics
Ethics
and Metaphysics. His work is associated with William of Moerbeke's translations of Aristotle
Aristotle
from Greek into Latin. Epistemology[edit] See also: Double truth Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
believed "that for the knowledge of any truth whatsoever man needs divine help, that the intellect may be moved by God to its act."[81] However, he believed that human beings have the natural capacity to know many things without special divine revelation, even though such revelation occurs from time to time, "especially in regard to such (truths) as pertain to faith."[82] But this is the light that is given to man by God according to man's nature: "Now every form bestowed on created things by God has power for a determined act[uality], which it can bring about in proportion to its own proper endowment; and beyond which it is powerless, except by a superadded form, as water can only heat when heated by the fire. And thus the human understanding has a form, viz. intelligible light, which of itself is sufficient for knowing certain intelligible things, viz. those we can come to know through the senses."[82] Ethics[edit] See also: Christian ethics Thomas' ethics are based on the concept of "first principles of action."[83] In his Summa theologiae, he wrote:

Virtue
Virtue
denotes a certain perfection of a power. Now a thing's perfection is considered chiefly in regard to its end. But the end of power is act. Wherefore power is said to be perfect, according as it is determinate to its act.[84]

Thomas emphasized that " Synderesis is said to be the law of our mind, because it is a habit containing the precepts of the natural law, which are the first principles of human actions."[85][86] According to Thomas "…all acts of virtue are prescribed by the natural law: since each one's reason naturally dictates to him to act virtuously. But if we speak of virtuous acts, considered in themselves, i.e., in their proper species, thus not all virtuous acts are prescribed by the natural law: for many things are done virtuously, to which nature does not incline at first; but that, through the inquiry of reason, have been found by men to be conductive to well living." Therefore, we must determine if we are speaking of virtuous acts as under the aspect of virtuous or as an act in its species.[87] Thomas defined the four cardinal virtues as prudence, temperance, justice, and fortitude. The cardinal virtues are natural and revealed in nature, and they are binding on everyone. There are, however, three theological virtues: faith, hope, and charity. Thomas also describes the virtues as imperfect (incomplete) and perfect (complete) virtues. A perfect virtue is any virtue with charity, charity completes a cardinal virtue. A non-Christian can display courage, but it would be courage with temperance. A Christian would display courage with charity. These are somewhat supernatural and are distinct from other virtues in their object, namely, God:

Now the object of the theological virtues is God Himself, Who is the last end of all, as surpassing the knowledge of our reason. On the other hand, the object of the intellectual and moral virtues is something comprehensible to human reason. Wherefore the theological virtues are specifically distinct from the moral and intellectual virtues.[88]

Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
wrote " Greed
Greed
is a sin against God, just as all mortal sins, in as much as man condemns things eternal for the sake of temporal things."[citation needed] Furthermore, Thomas distinguished four kinds of law: eternal, natural, human, and divine. Eternal law is the decree of God that governs all creation. It is, "That Law
Law
which is the Supreme Reason
Reason
cannot be understood to be otherwise than unchangeable and eternal."[89] Natural law is the human "participation" in the eternal law and is discovered by reason.[90] Natural law
Natural law
is based on "first principles":

. . . this is the first precept of the law, that good is to be done and promoted, and evil is to be avoided. All other precepts of the natural law are based on this . . .[91]

Whether the natural law contains several precepts, or one only is explained by Thomas, "All the inclinations of any parts whatsoever of human nature, e.g., of the concupiscible and irascible parts, in so far as they are ruled by reason, belong to the natural law, and are reduced to one first precept, as stated above: so that the precepts of the natural law are many in themselves, but are based on one common foundation."[92] The desires to live and to procreate are counted by Thomas among those basic (natural) human values on which all human values are based. According to Thomas, all human tendencies are geared towards real human goods. In this case, the human nature in question is marriage, the total gift of oneself to another that ensures a family for children and a future for mankind.[93] He defined the dual inclination of the action of love: "towards the good which a man wishes to someone (to himself or to another) and towards that to which he wishes some good".[94] Concerning the Human Law, Thomas concludes, "...that just as, in the speculative reason, from naturally known indemonstrable principles, we draw the conclusions of the various sciences, the knowledge of which is not imparted to us by nature, but acquired by the efforts of reason, so to it is from the precepts of the natural law, as from general and indemonstrable principles, that human reason needs to proceed to the more particular determination of certain matters. These particular determinations, devised by human reason, are called human laws, provided the other essential conditions of law be observed...." Human law is positive law: the natural law applied by governments to societies.[95] Natural and human law is not adequate alone. The need for human behavior to be directed made it necessary to have Divine law. Divine law is the specially revealed law in the scriptures. Thomas quotes, "The Apostle says (Hebrews 7.12): The priesthood being translated, it is necessary that a translation also be made of the law. But the priesthood is twofold, as stated in the same passage, viz, the levitical priesthood, and the priesthood of Christ. Therefore the Divine law is twofold, namely, the Old Law
Law
and the New Law."[96] Thomas also greatly influenced Catholic understandings of mortal and venial sins. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
refers to animals as dumb and that the natural order has declared animals for man's use. Thomas denied that human beings have any duty of charity to animals because they are not persons. Otherwise, it would be unlawful to kill them for food. But humans should still be charitable to them, for "cruel habits might carry over into our treatment of human beings."[97][98] Thomas contributed to economic thought as an aspect of ethics and justice. He dealt with the concept of a just price, normally its market price or a regulated price sufficient to cover seller costs of production. He argued it was immoral for sellers to raise their prices simply because buyers were in pressing need for a product.[99][100] Political order[edit] Thomas's theory of political order became highly influential. He sees man as a social being that lives in a community and interacts with its other members. That leads, among other things, to the division of labour. Thomas made a distinction between a good man and a good citizen, which was important to the development of libertarian theory. That is, the sphere of individual autonomy was one which the state could not interfere with.[101] Thomas thinks that monarchy is the best form of government, because a monarch does not have to form compromises with other persons. Moreover, according to Thomas, oligarchy degenerates more easily into tyranny than monarchy. To prevent a king from becoming a tyrant, his political powers must be curbed. Unless an agreement of all persons involved can be reached, a tyrant must be tolerated, as otherwise the political situation could deteriorate into anarchy, which would be even worse than tyranny. The kings are God's representatives in their territories. But the church, represented by the popes, is above the kings in matters of doctrine and morality. As a consequence, the kings and other worldly rulers are obliged to adapt their laws to the Catholic church's doctrines and ethics. For example, the worldly authorities have to execute persons whom the church has sentenced to death for heresy and they have to fight and subdue groups of heretics such as the Albigenses
Albigenses
and Waldensians
Waldensians
to restore the unity of the church.[citation needed] Following Aristotle's concept of slavery, Thomas justifies this institution on the grounds of natural law.[102] Psychology[edit]

This section needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (September 2011) (Learn how and when to remove this template message)

This section is written like a personal reflection or opinion essay that states a editor's personal feelings about a topic. Please help improve it by rewriting it in an encyclopedic style. (September 2013) (Learn how and when to remove this template message)

This section needs attention from an expert in Philosophy. The specific problem is: statements are not attributed or contextualised. See the talk page for details. WikiProject Philosophy may be able to help recruit an expert. (September 2013)

Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
maintains that a human is a single material substance. He understands the soul as the form of the body, which makes a human being the composite of the two. Thus, only living, form-matter composites can truly be called human; dead bodies are "human" only analogously. One actually existing substance comes from body and soul. A human is a single material substance, but still should be understood as having an immaterial soul, which continues after bodily death. In his Summa theologiae Thomas clearly states his position on the nature of the soul; defining it as "the first principle of life."[103] The soul is not corporeal, or a body; it is the act of a body. Because the intellect is incorporeal, it does not use the bodily organs, as "the operation of anything follows the mode of its being."[104] According to Thomas the soul is not matter, not even incorporeal or spiritual matter. If it were, it would not be able to understand universals, which are immaterial. A receiver receives things according to the receiver's own nature, so for soul (receiver) to understand (receive) universals, it must have the same nature as universals. Yet, any substance that understands universals may not be a matter-form composite. So, humans have rational souls, which are abstract forms independent of the body. But a human being is one existing, single material substance that comes from body and soul: that is what Thomas means when he writes that "something one in nature can be formed from an intellectual substance and a body", and "a thing one in nature does not result from two permanent entities unless one has the character of substantial form and the other of matter."[105] The soul is a "substantial form"; it is a part of a substance, but it is not a substance by itself. Nevertheless, the soul exists separately from the body, and continues, after death, in many of the capacities we think of as human. Substantial form is what makes a thing a member of the species to which it belongs, and substantial form is also the structure or configuration that provides the object with the abilities that make the object what it is. For humans, those abilities are those of the rational animal. These distinctions can be better understood in the light of Thomas's understanding of matter and form, a hylomorphic ("matter/form") theory derived from Aristotle. In any given substance, matter and form are necessarily united, and each is a necessary aspect of that substance. However, they are conceptually separable. Matter represents what is changeable about the substance—what is potentially something else. For example, bronze matter is potentially a statue, or also potentially a cymbal. Matter must be understood as the matter of something. In contrast, form is what determines some particular chunk of matter to be a specific substance and no other. When Thomas says that the human body is only partly composed of matter, he means the material body is only potentially a human being. The soul is what actualizes that potential into an existing human being. Consequently, the fact that a human body is live human tissue entails that a human soul is wholly present in each part of the human. Walter Freeman proposes that Thomism
Thomism
is the philosophical system explaining cognition that is most compatible with neurodynamics, in a 2008 article in the journal Mind and Matter titled "Nonlinear Brain Dynamics and Intention According to Aquinas."[106] Theology[edit] See also: Works by Thomas Aquinas

17th-century sculpture of Thomas Aquinas

Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
viewed theology, or the sacred doctrine, as a science,[61] the raw material data of which consists of written scripture and the tradition of the Catholic Church. These sources of data were produced by the self-revelation of God to individuals and groups of people throughout history. Faith
Faith
and reason, while distinct but related, are the two primary tools for processing the data of theology. Thomas believed both were necessary—or, rather, that the confluence of both was necessary—for one to obtain true knowledge of God. Thomas blended Greek philosophy and Christian doctrine by suggesting that rational thinking and the study of nature, like revelation, were valid ways to understand truths pertaining to God. According to Thomas, God reveals himself through nature, so to study nature is to study God. The ultimate goals of theology, in Thomas's mind, are to use reason to grasp the truth about God and to experience salvation through that truth. The central thought is Gratia non tollit naturam, sed perficit. Grace does not destroy nature, but perfects it. Revelation[edit] Thomas believed that truth is known through reason (natural revelation) and faith (supernatural revelation). Supernatural revelation has its origin in the inspiration of the Holy Spirit
Holy Spirit
and is made available through the teaching of the prophets, summed up in Holy Scripture, and transmitted by the Magisterium, the sum of which is called "Tradition". Natural revelation is the truth available to all people through their human nature and powers of reason. For example, he felt this applied to rational ways to know the existence of God. Though one may deduce the existence of God and his Attributes (Unity, Truth, Goodness, Power, Knowledge) through reason, certain specifics may be known only through the special revelation of God through Jesus Christ. The major theological components of Christianity, such as the Trinity, the Incarnation, and charity are revealed in the teachings of the Church and the Scriptures
Scriptures
and may not otherwise be deduced.[107] Preserving nature within grace[edit] Revealed knowledge does not negate the truth and the completeness of human science as human, it further establishes them. First, it grants that the same things can be treated from two different perspectives without one canceling the other; thus there can be two sciences of God. Second, it provides the basis for the two sciences: one functions through the power of the light of natural reason, the other through the light of divine revelation. Moreover, they can, at least to some extent, keep out of each other's way because they differ "according to genus". Sacred
Sacred
doctrine is a fundamentally different kind of thing from theology, which is part of philosophy (ST I. 1.1 ad 2). Faith
Faith
and reason complement rather than contradict each other, each giving different views of the same truth. Creation[edit]

Super libros de generatione et corruptione

As a Catholic Thomas believed that God is the "maker of heaven and earth, of all that is visible and invisible." Like Aristotle, Thomas posited that life could form from non-living material or plant life, a theory of ongoing abiogenesis known as spontaneous generation:

Since the generation of one thing is the corruption of another, it was not incompatible with the first formation of things, that from the corruption of the less perfect the more perfect should be generated. Hence animals generated from the corruption of inanimate things, or of plants, may have been generated then.[108]

Super Physicam Aristotelis, 1595

Additionally Thomas considered Empedocles's theory that various mutated species emerged at the dawn of Creation. Thomas reasoned that these species were generated through mutations in animal sperm, and argued that they were not unintended by nature; rather, such species were simply not intended for perpetual existence. That discussion is found in his commentary on Aristotle's Physics:

The same thing is true of those substances Empedocles
Empedocles
said were produced at the beginning of the world, such as the 'ox-progeny', i.e., half ox and half man. For if such things were not able to arrive at some end and final state of nature so that they would be preserved in existence, this was not because nature did not intend this [a final state], but because they were not capable of being preserved. For they were not generated according to nature, but by the corruption of some natural principle, as it now also happens that some monstrous offspring are generated because of the corruption of seed.[109]

Just war[edit] See also: Just War Augustine of Hippo
Augustine of Hippo
agreed strongly with the conventional wisdom of his time, that Christians should be pacifists philosophically, but that they should use defense as a means of preserving peace in the long run. For example, he routinely argued that pacifism did not prevent the defence of innocents. In essence, the pursuit of peace might require fighting to preserve it in the long-term.[110] Such a war must not be preemptive, but defensive, to restore peace.[111] Clearly, some special characteristics sets apart "war" from "schism", "brawling", and "sedition." While it would be contradictory to speak of a "just schism", a "just brawling" or a "just sedition" (the three terms denote sin and sin only) "war" alone permits sub classification into good and bad kinds. Curiously, however, Augustine does not work up a terminological contrast between "just" and "unjust" war.[112] Thomas Aquinas, centuries later, used the authority of Augustine's arguments in an attempt to define the conditions under which a war could be just.[113] He laid these out in his historic work, Summa Theologica:

First, war must occur for a good and just purpose rather than the pursuit of wealth or power. Second, just war must be waged by a properly instituted authority such as the state. Third, peace must be a central motive even in the midst of violence.[114]

School of Salamanca[edit] The School of Salamanca
School of Salamanca
expanded Thomas's understanding of natural law and just war. Given that war is one of the worst evils suffered by mankind, the adherents of the School reasoned that it ought to be resorted to only when it was necessary to prevent an even greater evil. A diplomatic agreement is preferable, even for the more powerful party, before a war is started. Examples of "just war" are:[citation needed]

In self-defense, as long as there is a reasonable possibility of success. If failure is a foregone conclusion, then it is just a wasteful spilling of blood. Preventive war against a tyrant who is about to attack. War
War
to punish a guilty enemy.

A war is not legitimate or illegitimate simply based on its original motivation: it must comply with a series of additional requirements:[citation needed]

The response must be commensurate with the evil; more violence than is strictly necessary would be unjust. Governing authorities declare war, but their decision is not sufficient cause to begin a war. If the people oppose a war, then it is illegitimate. The people have a right to depose a government that is waging, or is about to wage, an unjust war. Once war has begun, there remain moral limits to action. For example, one may not attack innocents or kill hostages. The belligerents must exhaust all options for dialogue and negotiation before undertaking a war; war is only legitimate as a last resort.

Under this doctrine, expansionist wars, wars of pillage, wars to convert infidels or pagans, and wars for glory are all inherently unjust. Nature
Nature
of God[edit] Thomas believed that the existence of God is self-evident in itself, but not to us. "Therefore I say that this proposition, "God exists", of itself is self-evident, for the predicate is the same as the subject.... Now because we do not know the essence of God, the proposition is not self-evident to us; but needs to be demonstrated by things that are more known to us, though less known in their nature—namely, by effects."[115] Thomas believed that the existence of God can be demonstrated. Briefly in the Summa theologiae and more extensively in the Summa contra Gentiles, he considered in great detail five arguments for the existence of God, widely known as the quinque viae (Five Ways). For detailed analysis of the five proofs, see Existence of God For the original text of the five proofs, see Quinque viae

Motion: Some things undoubtedly move, though cannot cause their own motion. Since, as Thomas believed, there can be no infinite chain of causes of motion, there must be a First Mover not moved by anything else, and this is what everyone understands by God.

Causation: As in the case of motion, nothing can cause itself, and an infinite chain of causation is impossible, so there must be a First Cause, called God.

Existence of necessary and the unnecessary: Our experience includes things certainly existing but apparently unnecessary. Not everything can be unnecessary, for then once there was nothing and there would still be nothing. Therefore, we are compelled to suppose something that exists necessarily, having this necessity only from itself; in fact itself the cause for other things to exist.

Gradation: If we can notice a gradation in things in the sense that some things are more hot, good, etc., there must be a superlative that is the truest and noblest thing, and so most fully existing. This then, we call God

Ordered tendencies of nature: A direction of actions to an end is noticed in all bodies following natural laws. Anything without awareness tends to a goal under the guidance of one who is aware. This we call God[116]

Concerning the nature of God, Thomas felt the best approach, commonly called the via negativa, is to consider what God is not. This led him to propose five statements about the divine qualities:

God is simple, without composition of parts, such as body and soul, or matter and form.[117] God is perfect, lacking nothing. That is, God is distinguished from other beings on account of God's complete actuality.[118] Thomas defined God as the 'Ipse Actus Essendi subsistens,' subsisting act of being.[119] God is infinite. That is, God is not finite in the ways that created beings are physically, intellectually, and emotionally limited. This infinity is to be distinguished from infinity of size and infinity of number.[120] God is immutable, incapable of change on the levels of God's essence and character.[121] God is one, without diversification within God's self. The unity of God is such that God's essence is the same as God's existence. In Thomas's words, "in itself the proposition 'God exists' is necessarily true, for in it subject and predicate are the same."[122]

Nature
Nature
of Sin[edit] Following St. Augustine of Hippo, Thomas defines sin as "a word, deed, or desire, contrary to the eternal law."[123] It is important to note the analogous nature of law in Thomas's legal philosophy. Natural law is an instance or instantiation of eternal law. Because natural law is what human beings determine according to their own nature (as rational beings), disobeying reason is disobeying natural law and eternal law. Thus eternal law is logically prior to reception of either "natural law" (that determined by reason) or "divine law" (that found in the Old and New Testaments). In other words, God's will extends to both reason and revelation. Sin
Sin
is abrogating either one's own reason, on the one hand, or revelation on the other, and is synonymous with "evil" (privation of good, or privatio boni[124]). Thomas, like all Scholastics, generally argued that the findings of reason and data of revelation cannot conflict, so both are a guide to God's will for human beings. Nature
Nature
of the Trinity[edit] Thomas argued that God, while perfectly united, also is perfectly described by Three Interrelated Persons. These three persons (Father, Son, and Holy Spirit) are constituted by their relations within the essence of God. Thomas wrote that the term "Trinity" "does not mean the relations themselves of the Persons, but rather the number of persons related to each other; and hence it is that the word in itself does not express regard to another."[125] The Father generates the Son (or the Word) by the relation of self-awareness. This eternal generation then produces an eternal Spirit "who enjoys the divine nature as the Love of God, the Love of the Father for the Word." This Trinity
Trinity
exists independently from the world. It transcends the created world, but the Trinity
Trinity
also decided to give grace to human beings. This takes place through the Incarnation
Incarnation
of the Word in the person of Jesus
Jesus
Christ and through the indwelling of the Holy Spirit within those who have experienced salvation by God; according to Aidan Nichols.[126] Prima causa
Prima causa
(first cause)[edit] Thomas's five proofs for the existence of God take some of Aristotle's assertions concerning principles of being. For God as prima causa ("first cause") comes from Aristotle's concept of the unmoved mover and asserts that God is the ultimate cause of all things.[127] Nature
Nature
of Jesus
Jesus
Christ[edit] In the Summa Theologica
Summa Theologica
Thomas begins his discussion of Jesus
Jesus
Christ by recounting the biblical story of Adam and Eve
Adam and Eve
and by describing the negative effects of original sin. The purpose of Christ's Incarnation was to restore human nature by removing the contamination of sin, which humans cannot do by themselves. "Divine Wisdom judged it fitting that God should become man, so that thus one and the same person would be able both to restore man and to offer satisfaction."[128] Thomas argued in favor of the satisfaction view of atonement; that is, that Jesus
Jesus
Christ died "to satisfy for the whole human race, which was sentenced to die on account of sin."[129] Thomas argued against several specific contemporary and historical theologians who held differing views about Christ. In response to Photinus, Thomas stated that Jesus
Jesus
was truly divine and not simply a human being. Against Nestorius, who suggested that Son of God was merely conjoined to the man Christ, Thomas argued that the fullness of God was an integral part of Christ's existence. However, countering Apollinaris's views, Thomas held that Christ had a truly human (rational) soul, as well. This produced a duality of natures in Christ. Thomas argued against Eutyches
Eutyches
that this duality persisted after the Incarnation. Thomas stated that these two natures existed simultaneously yet distinguishably in one real human body, unlike the teachings of Manichaeus
Manichaeus
and Valentinus.[130] With respect to Saint
Saint
Paul's assertion that Christ, "though he was in the form of God... emptied himself" ( Philippians
Philippians
2:6–7) in becoming human, Thomas offered an articulation of divine kenosis that has informed much subsequent Catholic Christology. Following the Council of Nicaea, Saint
Saint
Augustine of Hippo, as well as the assertions of Scripture, Thomas held the doctrine of divine immutability.[131][132][133] Hence, in becoming human, there could be no change in the divine person of Christ. For Thomas, "the mystery of Incarnation
Incarnation
was not completed through God being changed in any way from the state in which He had been from eternity, but through His having united Himself to the creature in a new way, or rather through having united it to Himself."[134] Similarly, Thomas explained that Christ "emptied Himself, not by putting off His divine nature, but by assuming a human nature."[135] For Thomas, "the divine nature is sufficiently full, because every perfection of goodness is there. But human nature and the soul are not full, but capable of fulness, because it was made as a slate not written upon. Therefore, human nature is empty."[135] Thus, when Paul indicates that Christ "emptied himself" this is to be understood in light of his assumption of a human nature. In short "Christ had a real body of the same nature of ours, a true rational soul, and, together with these, perfect Deity." Thus, there is both unity (in his one hypostasis) and composition (in his two natures, human and Divine) in Christ.[136]

I answer that, The Person or hypostasis of Christ may be viewed in two ways. First as it is in itself, and thus it is altogether simple, even as the Nature
Nature
of the Word. Secondly, in the aspect of person or hypostasis to which it belongs to subsist in a nature; and thus the Person of Christ subsists in two natures. Hence though there is one subsisting being in Him, yet there are different aspects of subsistence, and hence He is said to be a composite person, insomuch as one being subsists in two.[137]

Echoing Athanasius of Alexandria, he said that "The only begotten Son of God...assumed our nature, so that he, made man, might make men gods."[138] Goal of human life[edit] Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
identified the goal of human existence as union and eternal fellowship with God. This goal is achieved through the beatific vision, in which a person experiences perfect, unending happiness by seeing the essence of God. The vision occurs after death as a gift from God to those who in life experienced salvation and redemption through Christ. The goal of union with God has implications for the individual's life on earth. Thomas stated that an individual's will must be ordered toward right things, such as charity, peace, and holiness. He saw this orientation as also the way to happiness. Indeed, Thomas ordered his treatment of the moral life around the idea of happiness. The relationship between will and goal is antecedent in nature "because rectitude of the will consists in being duly ordered to the last end [that is, the beatific vision]." Those who truly seek to understand and see God will necessarily love what God loves. Such love requires morality and bears fruit in everyday human choices.[139] Treatment of heretics[edit] Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
belonged to the Dominican Order
Dominican Order
(formally Ordo Praedicatorum, the Order of Preachers) who began as an order dedicated to the conversion of the Albigensians
Albigensians
and other heterodox factions, at first by peaceful means; later the Albigensians
Albigensians
were dealt with by means of the Albigensian Crusade. In the Summa theologiae, he wrote:

With regard to heretics two points must be observed: one, on their own side; the other, on the side of the Church. On their own side there is the sin, whereby they deserve not only to be separated from the Church by excommunication, but also to be severed from the world by death. For it is a much graver matter to corrupt the faith that quickens the soul, than to forge money, which supports temporal life. Wherefore if forgers of money and other evil-doers are forthwith condemned to death by the secular authority, much more reason is there for heretics, as soon as they are convicted of heresy, to be not only excommunicated but even put to death. On the part of the Church, however, there is mercy, which looks to the conversion of the wanderer, wherefore she condemns not at once, but "after the first and second admonition", as the Apostle directs: after that, if he is yet stubborn, the Church no longer hoping for his conversion, looks to the salvation of others, by excommunicating him and separating him from the Church, and furthermore delivers him to the secular tribunal to be exterminated thereby from the world by death.(Summa, II–II, Q.11, art.3.)

Heresy
Heresy
was a capital offense against the secular law of most European countries of the 13th century, which had a limited prison capacity. Kings and emperors, even those at war with the papacy, listed heresy first among the crimes against the state. Kings claimed power from God according to the Christian faith. Often enough, especially in that age of papal claims to universal worldly power, the rulers' power was tangibly and visibly legitimated directly through coronation by the pope. Simple theft, forgery, fraud, and other such crimes were also capital offenses; Thomas's point seems to be that the gravity of this offense, which touches not only the material goods but also the spiritual goods of others, is at least the same as forgery. Thomas's suggestion specifically demands that heretics be handed to a "secular tribunal" rather than magisterial authority. That Thomas specifically says that heretics "deserve... death" is related to his theology, according to which all sinners have no intrinsic right to life ("For the wages of sin is death; but the free gift of God is eternal life in Christ Jesus our Lord"[140]). Nevertheless, his point is clear: heretics should be executed by the state. He elaborates on his opinion regarding heresy in the next article, when he says:

In God's tribunal, those who return are always received, because God is a searcher of hearts, and knows those who return in sincerity. But the Church cannot imitate God in this, for she presumes that those who relapse after being once received, are not sincere in their return; hence she does not debar them from the way of salvation, but neither does she protect them from the sentence of death. (Summa, op. cit., art.4.)

For Jews, Thomas argues for toleration, not only of their persons but also of their public rites.[141] Development of a new doctrinal belief in the actual power of witches[edit] Under the canon Episcopi, church doctrine held that witchcraft was not possible and any practitioners of sorcery were deluded and their acts an illusion. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
was instrumental in developing a new doctrine that included the belief in the real power of witches. This was a departure from the teachings of his master Albertus Magnus
Albertus Magnus
whose doctrine was based in the Episcopi.[142] The famous fifteenth century witch-hunter's manual, the Malleus Maleficarum, also written by a member of the Dominican Order, begins by quoting Aquinas ("Commentary on Pronouncements" Sent.4.34.I.Co.) refuting the Episcopi and goes on to cite Aquinas over a hundred times.[143] Promoters of the witch phobia that followed often quoted Aquinas more than any other source.[144] Thoughts on afterlife and resurrection[edit] A grasp of Thomas's psychology is essential for understanding his beliefs around the afterlife and resurrection. Thomas, following Church doctrine, accepts that the soul continues to exist after the death of the body. Because he accepts that the soul is the form of the body, then he also must believe that the human being, like all material things, is form-matter composite. Substantial form (the human soul) configures prime matter (the physical body) and is the form by which a material composite belongs to that species it does; in the case of human beings, that species is rational animal.[145] So, a human being is a matter-form composite that is organized to be a rational animal. Matter cannot exist without being configured by form, but form can exist without matter—which allows for the separation of soul from body. Thomas says that the soul shares in the material and spiritual worlds, and so has some features of matter and other, immaterial, features (such as access to universals). The human soul is different from other material and spiritual things; it is created by God, but also only comes into existence in the material body. Human beings are material, but the human person can survive the death of the body through continued existence of the soul, which persists. The human soul straddles the spiritual and material worlds, and is both a configured subsistent form as well as a configurer of matter into that of a living, bodily human.[146] Because it is spiritual, the human soul does not depend on matter and may exist separately. Because the human being is a soul-matter composite, the body has a part in what it is to be human. Perfected human nature consists in the human dual nature, embodied and intellecting. Resurrection appears to require dualism, which Thomas rejects. Yet Thomas believes the soul persists after the death and corruption of the body, and is capable of existence, separated from the body between the time of death and the resurrection. Thomas believes in a different sort of dualism, one guided by Christian scripture. Thomas knows that human beings are essentially physical, but physicality has a spirit capable of returning to God after life.[147] For Thomas, the rewards and punishment of the afterlife are not only spiritual. Because of this, resurrection is an important part of his philosophy on the soul. The human is fulfilled and complete in the body, so the hereafter must take place with souls enmattered in resurrected bodies. In addition to spiritual reward, humans can expect to enjoy material and physical blessings. Because Thomas's soul requires a body for its actions, during the afterlife, the soul will also be punished or rewarded in corporeal existence. Thomas states clearly his stance on resurrection, and uses it to back up his philosophy of justice; that is, the promise of resurrection compensates Christians who suffered in this world through a heavenly union with the divine. He says, "If there is no resurrection of the dead, it follows that there is no good for human beings other than in this life."[148] Resurrection provides the impetus for people on earth to give up pleasures in this life. Aquinas believes the human who prepared for the afterlife both morally and intellectually will be rewarded more greatly; however, all reward is through the grace of God. Thomas insists beatitude will be conferred according to merit, and will render the person better able to conceive the divine. Thomas accordingly believes punishment is directly related to earthly, living preparation and activity as well. Thomas's account of the soul focuses on epistemology and metaphysics, and because of this he believes it gives a clear account of the immaterial nature of the soul. Thomas conservatively guards Christian doctrine, and thus maintains physical and spiritual reward and punishment after death. By accepting the essentiality of both body and soul, he allows for a heaven and hell described in scripture and church dogma. Modern influence[edit]

A stained glass window of Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
in St. Joseph's Catholic Church (Central City, Kentucky)

Many modern ethicists both within and outside the Catholic Church (notably Philippa Foot
Philippa Foot
and Alasdair MacIntyre) have recently commented on the possible use of Thomas's virtue ethics as a way of avoiding utilitarianism or Kantian "sense of duty" (called deontology). Through the work of twentieth-century philosophers such as Elizabeth Anscombe (especially in her book Intention), Thomas's principle of double effect specifically and his theory of intentional activity generally have been influential. In recent years the cognitive neuroscientist Walter Freeman proposes that Thomism
Thomism
is the philosophical system explaining cognition that is most compatible with neurodynamics, in a 2008 article in the journal Mind and Matter titled "Nonlinear Brain Dynamics and Intention According to Aquinas." Henry Adams's Mont Saint
Saint
Michel and Chartres ends with a culminating chapter on Thomas, in which Adams calls Thomas an "artist" and constructs an extensive analogy between the design of Thomas's "Church Intellectual" and that of the gothic cathedrals of that period. Erwin Panofsky later would echo these views in Gothic Architecture and Scholasticism
Scholasticism
(1951). Thomas's aesthetic theories, especially the concept of claritas, deeply influenced the literary practice of modernist writer James Joyce, who used to extol Thomas as being second only to Aristotle among Western philosophers. Joyce refers to Thomas's doctrines in Elementa philosophiae ad mentem D. Thomae Aquinatis doctoris angelici (1898) of Girolamo Maria Mancini, professor of theology at the Collegium Divi Thomae de Urbe.[149] For example, Mancini's Elementa is referred to in Joyce's Portrait of the Artist as a Young Man.[150] The influence of Thomas's aesthetics also can be found in the works of the Italian semiotician Umberto Eco, who wrote an essay on aesthetic ideas in Thomas (published in 1956 and republished in 1988 in a revised edition). Russell's criticism of Thomas as philosopher[edit] Twentieth century philosopher Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Russell
criticized Thomas's philosophy stating that,

He does not, like the Platonic Socrates, set out to follow wherever the argument may lead. He is not engaged in an inquiry, the result of which it is impossible to know in advance. Before he begins to philosophize, he already knows the truth; it is declared in the Catholic faith. If he can find apparently rational arguments for some parts of the faith, so much the better; if he cannot, he need only fall back on revelation. The finding of arguments for a conclusion given in advance is not philosophy, but special pleading. I cannot, therefore, feel that he deserves to be put on a level with the best philosophers either of Greece or of modern times.[151]

This critique is illustrated on the following examples: According to Russell, Thomas advocates the indissolubility of marriage "on the ground that the father is useful in the education of the children, (a) because he is more rational than the mother, (b) because, being stronger, he is better able to inflict physical punishment."[152] Even though modern approaches to education do not support these views, "No follower of Saint
Saint
Thomas would, on that account, cease to believe in lifelong monogamy, because the real grounds of belief are not those which are alleged."[152] It may be countered that the treatment of matrimony in the Summa Theologica
Summa Theologica
is in the Supplements volume, which was not written by Thomas.[153] Moreover, as noted above,[154] Thomas's introduction of arguments and concepts from the pagan Aristotle
Aristotle
and Muslim Averroes
Averroes
was controversial within the Catholic Church of his day. Thomas's views of God as first cause, cf. quinque viae, "depend upon the supposed impossibility of a series having no first term. Every mathematician knows that there is no such impossibility; the series of negative integers ending with minus one is an instance to the contrary."[152] Moreover, according to Russell, statements regarding God's essence and existence that are reached within the Aristotelian logic are based on "some kind of syntactical confusion, without which much of the argumentation about God would lose its plausibility."[152] Works[edit] Main article: List of works by Thomas Aquinas The first edition of Thomas's opera omnia, the so-called editio Piana (from Pius V, the Dominican Pope
Pope
who commissioned it), was produced in 1570 at the studium of the Roman convent at Santa Maria sopra Minerva, the forerunner of the Pontifical University of Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas, Angelicum.[155] The critical edition of Thomas's works is the ongoing edition commissioned by Pope
Pope
Leo XIII (1882–1903), the so-called Leonine Edition. Most of his major works have now been edited, the Summa Theologiae in nine volumes during 1888–1906, the Summa contra Gentiles in three volumes during 1918–1930. Abbé Migne
Abbé Migne
published an edition of the Summa Theologiae, in four volumes, as an appendix to his Patrologiae Cursus Completus
Patrologiae Cursus Completus
(English editions: Joseph Rickaby
Joseph Rickaby
1872, J. M. Ashley 1888). Electronic texts of mostly the Leonine Edition are maintained online by the Corpus Thomisticum (corpusthomisticum.org) by Enrique Alarcón, University of Navarra, and at Documenta Catholica Omnia. See also[edit]

Christianity
Christianity
portal Saints portal

Adoro te devote Aquinas Institute Aquinas School in San Juan City, Philippines Aquinas University in Legazpi City, Philippines Bartholomew of Lucca, Aquinas's friend and confessor Christian mysticism High Middle Ages Homo unius libri International Council of Universities of Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas Lauda Sion List of institutions named after Thomas Aquinas Medieval university Omnipotence paradox Pange Lingua Gloriosi Corporis Mysterium Pontifical Academy of St. Thomas Aquinas Pontifical University of St. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
(Angelicum) Sacris solemniis St. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
College School of Salamanca, 16th-century Spanish Thomists Statues of Madonna, Saint
Saint
Dominic and Thomas Aquinas, Charles Bridge St. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
High School (Florida) Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
and the Sacraments Thought of Thomas Aquinas University of Santo Tomas University of St. Thomas (Minnesota) Verbum Supernum Prodiens Gratia non tollit naturam, sed perficit

Thomists[edit]

Alasdair MacIntyre Étienne Gilson G. E. M. Anscombe Brian Davies Jacques Maritain J. Budziszewski James V. Schall Josef Pieper Ralph McInerny Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange

Notes[edit]

^ Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
– CatholicSaints.Info ^ A. C. Brown, Jonathan (2014). Misquoting Muhammad: The Challenge and Choices of Interpreting the Prophet's Legacy. Oneworld Publications. p. 12. ISBN 978-1780744209. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
admitted relying heavily on Averroes
Averroes
to understand Aristotle.  ^ "The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Avicenna
Avicenna
(Ibn Sina) (c. 980–1037)". Iep.utm.edu. 2006-01-06. Retrieved 2010-01-19.  ^ " Anselm of Canterbury
Anselm of Canterbury
(1033–1109)", Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2006, retrieved 10 November 2017  ^ Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
- Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy ^ Conway, John Placid (1911). Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas. London.  ^ Rev. Vaughan, Roger Bede
Bede
(1871). The Life and Labours of St. Thomas of Aquin: Vol.I. London.  ^ See Pius XI, Studiorum Ducem 11 (29 June 1923), AAS, XV ("non modo Angelicum, sed etiam Communem seu Universalem Ecclesiae Doctorem"). The title Doctor Communis dates to the fourteenth century; the title Doctor Angelicus dates to the fifteenth century, see Walz, Xenia Thomistica, III, p. 164 n. 4. Tolomeo da Lucca
Tolomeo da Lucca
writes in Historia Ecclesiastica (1317): "This man is supreme among modern teachers of philosophy and theology, and indeed in every subject. And such is the common view and opinion, so that nowadays in the University of Paris they call him the Doctor Communis because of the outstanding clarity of his teaching." Historia Eccles. xxiii, c. 9. ^ http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aquinas/ ^ "Archived copy". Archived from the original on 13 September 2013. Retrieved 18 December 2013.  ^ http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/31211/Saint-Thomas-Aquinas ^ Code of Canon Law, Can. 252, §3 "Archived copy". Archived from the original on 8 May 2011. Retrieved 22 March 2011.  ^ Benedict XV Encyclical
Encyclical
Fausto appetente die 29 June 1921, AAS 13 (1921), 332; Pius XI
Pius XI
Encyclical
Encyclical
Studiorum Ducem §11, 29 June 1923, AAS 15 (1923), cf. AAS 17 (1925) 574; Paul VI, 7 March 1964 AAS 56 (1964), 302 (Bouscaren, vol. VI, pp. 786–88). ^ Aquinas, Thomas (1993). Selected Philosophical Writings. Oxford University Press. pp. Xi. ISBN 0192835858.  access-date= requires url= (help) ^ Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas: The Person And His Work, CUA press, 2005, p. 3. Google Book ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 14. ^ a b c d Stump, Aquinas, p. 3. ^ a b Schaff, Philip (1953). Thomas Aquinas, pp. 422–23. ^ Davies, Aquinas: An Introduction, pp. 1–2 ^ a b c Davies, Aquinas: An Introduction, p. 2 ^ Hampden, The Life, pp. 21–22. ^ Grabmann, Martin. Virgil Michel, trans. Thomas Aquinas: His Personality and Thought. (Kessinger Publishing, 2006), pp. 2. ^ Collison, Diane, and Kathryn Plant. Fifty Major Philosophers. 2nd ed. New York: Routledge, 2006. ^ a b Hampden, The Life, p. 23. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 24. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 25. ^ Hampden, The Life, pp. 27–28. ^ a b Healy, Theologian, p. 2. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 33. ^ Stump, Aquinas, p. xvi. ^ Davies, The Thought, p. 5. ^ Aquinas, Thomas; Richard J. Regan; Brian Davies (2003). On Evil. Oxford University Press US. p. 5. ISBN 0-19-509183-3.  ^ a b Stump, Aquinas, p. 4. ^ Davies, Aquinas: An Introduction, pp. 3–4. ^ a b Stump, Aquinas, p. xvii. ^ a b Davies, Aquinas: An Introduction, p. 4. ^ a b Healy, Theologian, p. 4. ^ Torrell, " Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas", pp. 129–32. ^ Fr. Thome de Aquino iniungimus in remissionem peccatorum quod teneat studium Rome, et volumus quod fratribus qui stant secum ad studendum provideatur in necessariis vestimentis a conventibus de quorum predicatione traxerunt originem. Si autem illi studentes inventi fuerint negligentes in studio, damus potestatem fr. Thome quod ad conventus suos possit eos remittere (Acta Capitulorum Provincialium, Provinciae Romanae Ordinis Praedicatorum, 1265, n. 12)http://www.corpusthomisticum.org/a65.html ^ Compendium Historiae Ordinis Praedicatorum, A.M. Walz, Herder 1930, 214: "Conventus S. Sabinae de Urbe prae ceteris gloriam singularem ex praesentia fundatoris ordinis et primitivorum fratrum necnon ex residentia Romana magistrorum generalium, si de ea sermo esse potest, habet. In documentis quidem eius nonnisi anno 1222 nomen fit, ait certe iam antea nostris concreditus est. Florebant ibi etiam studia sacra." https://archive.org/stream/MN5081ucmf_3/MN5081ucmf_3_djvu.txt Accessed 4-9-2011. ^ Marian Michèle Mulchahey, "First the bow is bent in study": Dominican education before 1350, 1998, pp. 278–79. [1] Accessed 6-30-2011 ^ "Tenuit studium Rome, quasi totam Philosophiam, sive Moralem, sive Naturalem exposuit." Ptolomaei Lucensis historia ecclesiastica nova, xxii, c. 24, in Ferdinand Gregorovius "History of the City of Rome In the Middle Ages", Vol V, part II, 617, note 2. http://www.third-millennium-library.com/PDF/Authors/Gregorovius/history-of-rome-city_5_2.pdf Accessed 6-5-2011. Archived 5 October 2011 at the Wayback Machine. ^ Summa theologiae, I, 1, prooemium:"Quia Catholicae veritatis doctor non solum provectos debet instruere, sed ad eum pertinet etiam incipientes erudire, secundum illud apostoli I ad Corinth. III, tanquam parvulis in Christo, lac vobis potum dedi, non escam; propositum nostrae intentionis in hoc opere est, ea quae ad Christianam religionem pertinent, eo modo tradere, secundum quod congruit ad eruditionem incipientium." ^ a b c d Davies, Aquinas: An Introduction, p. 5. ^ http://aquinatis.blogspot.com/2008/05/vida-de-santo-toms-de-aquino.html Accessed 22 June 2011: "A mediados de noviembre abandonó Santo Tomás la ciudad de Viterbo en compañía de fray Reginaldo de Piperno y su discípulo fray Nicolás Brunacci." http://www.brunacci.it/s--tommaso.html Accessed 22 June 2011. http://www.brunacci.it/s--tommaso.html Accessed 22 June 2011: "Per l'acutezza del suo ingegno, dopo aver studiato nella sua provincia, ebbe l'alto onore di accompagnare S. Tommaso a Parigi nel novembre del 1268. Rimase in quello studio fino al 1272 e di là passò a Colonia sotto la disciplina di Alberto Magno." ^ http://www.santiebeati.it/dettaglio/92060 Accessed 29 June 2011 ^ Compendium Historiae Ordinis Praedicatorum, A.M. Walz, Herder 1930, 214: Romanus conventus S. Mariae supra Minervam anno 1255 ex conditionibus parvis crevit. Tunc enim paenitentibus feminis in communi regulariter ibi 1252/53 viventibus ad S. Pancratium migratis fratres Praedicatores domum illam relictam a Summo Pontifice habendam petierunt et impetranint. Qua demum feliciter obtenda capellam hospitio circa annum 1255 adiecerunt. Huc evangelizandi causa fratres e conventu S. Sabinae descendebant. https://archive.org/stream/MN5081ucmf_3/MN5081ucmf_3_djvu.txt Accessed 5-17-2011 ^ Marian Michèle Mulchahey, "First the bow is bent in study": Dominican education before 1350, 1998, p. 323. https://books.google.com/books?id=bK9axCYcbFIC&pg=PA323 Accessed 5-26-2011 ^ Stump, Aquinas, pp. 10–11. ^ a b Stump, Aquinas, p. 11-12. ^ Aquinas, Reader, pp. 9–11. ^ McInerney, Against the Averroists, p. 10. ^ Thomas Aquinas, Reader, p. 11. ^ James Weisheipl, OP Friar
Friar
Thomas D'Aquino: His Life, Thought, and Work. (Doubleday, 1974), p. 319. ^ http://www4.desales.edu/~philtheo/loughlin/ATP/Sermons/Nicholas_Essay.pdf ^ Guilelmus de Tocco, Ystoria sancti Thome de Aquino de Guillaume de Tocco (1323), Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1996, p. 162. ^ Catholic Encyclopedia ^ a b "CATHOLIC ENCYCLOPEDIA: St. Thomas Aquinas". www.newadvent.org. Retrieved 2016-08-22.  ^ Davies, The Thought, p. 9. ^ McBride, William Leon (1997). The Development and Meaning of Twentieth-century Existentialism. Taylor and Francis. p. 131. ISBN 0-8153-2491-X.  ^ a b McInerny, Ralph and John O'Callaghan, " Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.) ^ a b Healy, Theologian, p. 7. ^ a b Nichols, Discovering Aquinas, p. 18. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 46. ^ a b Healy, Theologian, p. 8. ^ Aquinas, Reader, p. 12. ^ Torrell, " Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas", p. 292. ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 47. ^ G. K. Chesterton
G. K. Chesterton
wrote an Essay on St. Thomas Aquinas, which appeared in The Spectator
The Spectator
27 Feb. 1932. ^ Grant, Edward (1996). The Foundations of Modern Science in the Middle Ages: Their Religious, Institutional, and Intellectual Contexts. Cambridge University Press. pp. 81–82. ISBN 0-521-56762-9.  ^ a b Hans Küng
Hans Küng
(1994), Christian Thinkers [2], pp. 112–14. ^ "Parad. x. 99". Divinecomedy.org. Archived from the original on 26 July 2011. Retrieved 17 January 2010.  ^ "Purg. xx. 69". Divinecomedy.org. Archived from the original on 26 July 2011. Retrieved 17 January 2010.  ^ a b c d  One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain: Chisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Thomas Aquinas". Encyclopædia Britannica (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 250.  ^ a b Brian Mullady, O.P. (2006). "The Angelic Doctor – Thomas Aquinas". Archived from the original on 7 October 2008. Retrieved 11 June 2011.  ^ Hampden, The Life, p. 54. ^ Calendarium Romanum Libreria Editrice Vaticana 1969, p. 86 ^ Liturgy of the Hours Volume III, Proper of Saints, 28 January. ^ Some would not describe Thomas as a philosopher. See, e.g., Mark D. Jordan, "Philosophy in a Summa of Theology", in Rewritten Theology: Aquinas after his Readers (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006) pp. 154–70. [3] ^ Davies, Brian (2004). Aquinas. Continuum International Publishing Group. p. 14.  ^ "Blog Archive " Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas". Saints.SQPN.com. 22 October 1974. Retrieved 2010-01-17.  ^ a b "Summa, I–II, Q109a1". Ccel.org. Retrieved 2012-03-25.  ^ Geisler, p. 727. ^ "Summa, Q55a1". Ccel.org. Retrieved 2012-02-02.  ^ 3. Aquinas ^ Summa Theologica, First Part of the Second Part, Question 94 Reply Obj. 2 ^ Summa Question 94, A.3 ^ "Summa, Q62a2". Ccel.org. Retrieved 2012-02-02.  ^ Aquinas Summa Theologica
Summa Theologica
q91 a1 ^ Pojman, Louis (1995). Ethics: Discovering Right and Wrong. Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing Company. ISBN 0-534-56138-1.  ^ "Summa, Q94a2". Ccel.org. Retrieved 2012-02-02.  ^ Summa Theologica, Question 94, Second Article Reply Obj.2 ^ Aquinas, Thomas. "IV In Sententiae. d. 27 q. 1 a.1". Commentary. Retrieved 2011-09-21.  ^ "St. Thomas Aquinas, STh I–II, 26, 4, corp. art". Newadvent.org. Retrieved 2010-10-30.  ^ Summa,Q.94, A.3. ^ Summa, Q.94, A.5 ^ Honderich, Ted, ed. (1995). "Animals: Peter Singer". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford. pp. 35–36.  ^ Summa Theologica, second Part of the Second Part, Question 64. Article 1. ^ Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologica. "Of Cheating, Which Is Committed in Buying and Selling." Translated by The Fathers of the English Dominican Province [4] Retrieved 19 June 2012 ^ Barry Gordon (1987). "Aquinas, St Thomas (1225–1274)", v. 1, p. 100 ^ Smith, George S. (2008). "Aquinas, Thomas (c. 1225–1274)". In Hamowy, Ronald. The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE; Cato Institute. p. 18. doi:10.4135/9781412965811.n11. ISBN 978-1-4129-6580-4. LCCN 2008009151. OCLC 750831024. Individuals, therefore, have a private 'sphere of action which is distinct from the whole.'  ^ Heinz-Dietrich Wendland (1962): Sklaverei und Christentum. In: Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart, Third Edition, Tübingen (Germany), Vol. VI, col. 103 ^ Aquinas, Thomas (1920). "Question 75, Article 1". In Literally Translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province. Summa Theologiae of St. Thomas Aquinas. Second and Revised Edition. CS1 maint: Uses editors parameter (link) ^ Aquinas, Thomas (1920). "Question 75, Article 3". In Literally Translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province. Summa Theologiae of St. Thomas Aquinas. Second and Revised Edition. CS1 maint: Uses editors parameter (link) ^ Aquinas, Thomas (1975). "5 volumes.". In Translated by Anton C. Pegis et al. Summa Contra Gentiles. Notre Dame, Ind.: U. of Notre Dame Press. CS1 maint: Uses editors parameter (link) ^ http://philpapers.org/rec/FRENBD ^ Hankey, Wayne (2013). The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion (Second ed.). CSU East Bay: Routledge. pp. 134–35. ISBN 978-0-415-78295-1.  ^ Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, On the Work of the Sixth Day, Reply to Objection 5, Fathers of the English Dominican Province ^ Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas, Physica, Book 2, Lecture 14, Fathers of the English Dominican Province ^ St. Augustine of Hippo
Augustine of Hippo
Archived 28 July 2012 at Archive.is, Crusades-Encyclopedia ^ Saint
Saint
Augustine and the Theory of Just War ^ Reichberg, Gregory (June 2010). " Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
between Just War
Just War
and Pacificism". Journal of Religious Ethics. 38 (2): 219–41. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9795.2010.00427.x.  ^ The Just War ^ Justo L. Gonzalez (1984). The Story of Christianity. HarperSanFrancisco.  ^ http://www.newadvent.org/summa/1002.htm#article1 ^ Summa of Theology
Theology
I, q.2, The Five Ways Philosophers Have Proven God's Existence ^ Kreeft, pp. 74–77. ^ Kreeft, pp. 86–87. ^ See Actus Essendi. See also Online Resources: Actus Essendi Electronic Journal. ^ Kreeft, pp. 97–99. ^ Kreeft, p. 105. ^ Kreeft, pp. 111–12. ^ "Summa, II–I, Q.71, art.6". Newadvent.org. Retrieved 2010-01-17.  ^ Summa, II–I, Q.75, art.1. "For evil is the absence of the good, which is natural and due to a thing." ^ http://www.newadvent.org/summa/1031.htm#article3 ^ Nichols, Aidan (2002). Discovering Aquinas. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Eerdmans Publishing Company. pp. 173–74.  ^ Nichols, Aidan (2002). Discovering Aquinas. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Eerdmans Publishing Company. pp. 80–82.  ^ Thomas Aquinas, pp. 228–29. ^ "Summa, III, Q.50, art.1". Newadvent.org. Retrieved 2010-01-17.  ^ Thomas Aquinas, pp. 231–39. ^ "The Profession of Faith
Faith
of the 318 Fathers," First Council of Nicaea – 325 AD, available at http://www.papalencyclicals.net/Councils/ecum01.htm, §2. ^ Augustine, Sermo VII, 7. ^ For instance, Malachi
Malachi
3:6 and James 1:17 ^ ST III.1.1. ^ a b Commentary on Saint
Saint
Paul's Letter to the Philippians, available at http://dhspriory.org/thomas/english/SSPhilippians.htm, §2-2. ^ Thomas Aquinas, pp. 241, 245–49. Emphasis is the author's. ^ http://www.newadvent.org/summa/4002.htm#article4 ^ Weigel, George (2001). The Truth of Catholicism. New York City: Harper Collins. p. 9. ISBN 0-06-621330-4.  ^ Kreeft, p. 383. ^ "Romans 6:23, ASV". Biblegateway.com. Retrieved 2010-01-17.  ^ Novak, Michael (December 1995), "Aquinas and the Heretics", First Things. ^ GL Burr, Selected Writings ed. LO Gibbons (New York, 1943) p. 173-4.Original essay (1890) available here. ^ Heinrich Kramer, Malleus Maleficarum, trans. Christopher Mackay (Cambridge, 2009) 91-2. ^ Burr(1943)p.174. ^ Stump, Eleanore (2003). Aquinas, (in the series The Arguments of the Philosophers). London and New York: Routledge. p. 194.  ^ Stump, Eleanore (2003). Aquinas, (in the series The Arguments of the Philosophers). London and New York: Routledge. p. 200.  ^ Stump, Eleanore (2003). Aquinas, (in the series The Arguments of the Philosophers). London and New York: Routledge. p. 192.  ^ Stump, Eleanore (2003). Aquinas, (in the series The Arguments of the Philosophers). London and New York: Routledge. pp. 461, 473.  ^ The Irish Ecclesiastical Record, Vol V, Year 32, No. 378, June, 1899, p. 570 Accessed 3-7-2013 ^ A Portrait of the Artist as a Young Man, James Joyce, Wordsworth 1992 edition, Introduction and Notes by Jacqueline Belanger, 2001, p. 136, note 309: "Synopsis Philosophiae ad mentem D. Thomae This appears to be a reference to Elementa Philosophiae ad mentem D. Thomae Aquinatis, a selection of Thomas Thomas's writings edited and published by G. M. Mancini in 1898. (G)" https://books.google.com/books?id=C_rPXanc_HAC&pg=PA221#v=onepage&q&f=false Accessed 3-6-2013 ^ (Russell 1967, p. 463) A History of Western Philosophy, Ch. 34, "St. Thomas Aquinas", Allen & Unwin, London; Simon & Schuster, New York 1946, pp. 484–. ^ a b c d (Russell 1967, p. 462) ^ http://www.newadvent.org/summa/5.htm ^ Thomas Aquinas#Condemnation of 1277 ^ In This Light Which Gives Light: A History of the College of St. Albert the Great, Christopher J. Renzi, p. 42: https://books.google.com/books?id=t8qt63uOg6IC&pg=PA42#v=onepage&q&f=false Accessed 4-24-2011

References[edit]

Aquinas, Thomas (2000). Mary T. Clark, ed. An Aquinas Reader: Selections from the Writings of Thomas Aquinas. Fordham University Press. ISBN 0-8232-2029-X.  ——— (2002). Aquinas's Shorter Summa. Manchester, New Hampshire: Sophia Institute Press. ISBN 1-928832-43-1.  Davies, Brian (1993). The Thought of Thomas Aquinas. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-826753-3.  ——— (2004). Aquinas: An Introduction. Continuum. ISBN 0-8264-7095-5.  Geisler, Norman, ed. (1999). Baker Encyclopedia of Christian Apologetics. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Baker Academic.  Gordon, Barry (2009) [1987], "Aquinas, St Thomas", The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, 1 . Hampden, Renn Dickson (1848). "The Life of Thomas Aquinas: A Dissertation of the Scholastic Philosophy of the Middle Ages". Encyclopædia Metropolitana. London: John J. Griffin & Co.  Healy, Nicholas M. (2003). Thomas Aquinas: Theologian of the Christian Life. Ashgate. ISBN 0-7546-1472-7.  Kreeft, Peter (1990). Summa of the Summa. Ignatius Press. ISBN 0-89870-300-X.  Küng, Hans (1994), Great Christian Thinkers, New York: Continuum Books, ISBN 0-8264-0848-6  McInerny, Ralph M. (1993). Aquinas Against the Averroists: On There Being Only One Intellect. Purdue University Press. ISBN 1-55753-029-7.  Nichols, Aidan (2003). Discovering Aquinas: An Introduction to His Life, Work, and Influence. Wm. B. Eerdmans. ISBN 0-8028-0514-0.  Russell, Bertrand (1967), A History of Western Philosophy, Simon & Schuster, ISBN 0-67120158-1  Schaff, Philip (1953). "Thomas Aquinas". The New Schaff-Herzog Encyclopedia of Religious Knowledge. 126. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Baker Book House. pp. 422–23. Bibcode:1930Natur.126..951G. doi:10.1038/126951c0.  Stump, Eleonore (2003). Aquinas. Routledge. ISBN 0-415-02960-0. 

Further reading[edit]

Copleston, Frederick (1991). Aquinas: An Introduction to the Life and Work of the Great Medieval Thinker. Penguin Books. ISBN 0-14-013674-6.  Faitanin, Paulo (2008). A Sabedoria do Amor: iniciação à filosofia de Santo Tomás de Aquino [Love's philosophy: initiation to Saint Thomas Aquinas's philosophy] (in Portuguese). Instituto Aquinate. ISSN 1982-8845.  ——— (2008). O Ofício do Sábio: o modo de estudar e ensinar segundo Santo Tomás de Aquino [The wise's profession: the way of studying & learning after Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas] (in Portuguese). Instituto Aquinate. ISSN 1982-8845.  Paterson, Craig & Matthew S. Pugh (eds.), Analytical Thomism: Traditions in Dialogue. Ashgate, 2006. Introduction to Thomism Porro, Paquale (2015). Thomas Aquinas: A Historical and Philosophical Profile. Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press. ISBN 978-0-8132-2805-1.  Schmitz, Kenneth (2007). St. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
(audiobook). Narrated by Charlton Heston. Ashland, Oregon; Boulder, Colorado: Knowledge Products; Blackstone Audiobooks; NetLibrary. ISBN 0-7861-6932-X. OCLC 78235338. Archived from the original on 16 December 2011.  Strathern, Paul (1998). Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
in 90 Minutes. Chicago: I.R. Dee. 90 pp. ISBN 1-56663-194-7. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
(1952), edd. Walter Farrell, OP, and Martin J. Healy, My Way of Life: Pocket Edition of St. Thomas – The Summa Simplified for Everyone, Brooklyn: Confraternity of the Precious Blood. Torrell, Jean-Pierre (2005). Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
(Rev. ed.). Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press. ISBN 978-0-8132-1423-8. OCLC 456104266.  Wallace, William A (1970). "Thomas Aquinas, Saint". In Gillispie, Charles. Dictionary of Scientific Biography. 1. New York: Scribner & American Council of Learned Societies. pp. 196–200. ISBN 978-0-684-10114-9.  Weisheipl, James (1974). Friar
Friar
Thomas D'Aquino: his life, thought, and work (1st ed.). Garden City, New York: Doubleday. ISBN 978-0-385-01299-7.  Eugene F. Rogers Jr., Aquinas and the Supreme Court: Biblical Narratives of Jews, Gentiles and Gender [1 ed.], 1118391160, 9781118391167 Wiley-Blackwell 2013

External links[edit]

Wikimedia Commons has media related to Thomas Aquinas.

Catholic Churches named after St. Thomas Aquinas

Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
Cathedral - Reno, Nevada USA

Wikiquote has quotations related to: Thomas Aquinas

Wikisource
Wikisource
has original works written by or about: Thomas Aquinas

Biographies[edit]

St. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
(pdf) biography from Fr. Alban Butler's Lives of the Saints  "St. Thomas Aquinas". Catholic Encyclopedia. 1913.  St. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
article by Daniel Kennedy in Catholic Encyclopedia (1912), at NewAdvent.org St. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
biography by Jacques Maritain St. Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
biography by G. K. Chesterton
G. K. Chesterton
protected by copyright outside Australia Vita D. Thomae Aquinatis, a pictorial life of Aquinas from a manuscript by Otto van Veen
Otto van Veen
(1610) Colonnade Statue St Peter's Square

On his thought[edit]

"Introductory Guide to Reading the Summa Theologica
Summa Theologica
of Thomas Aquinas." Actus Essendi: An Electronic Journal on Aquinas's Doctrine of the Act of Being. Brown, Paterson. "Infinite Causal Regression", Philosophical Review, 1966. Brown, Paterson. "St. Thomas's Doctrine of Necessary Being", Philosophical Review, 1964. Instituto Teológico São Tomás de Aquino (Portuguese) On the legend of St. Albert's automaton Aquinas on Intelligent Extra-Terrestrial Life Poetry of St. Thomas Aquinas Biography and ideas at SWIF/University of Bari/Italy (Italian) Postilla in Job From the Book and Special
Special
Collections Division at the Library of Congress Thomas Aquinas, by R. McInerny and J. O'Callaghan (2014), in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Aquinas' Moral, Political and Legal Philosophy, by J. Finnis (2011), in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy "Thomas Aquinas". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  "Aquinas: Metaphysics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  "Aquinas: Moral Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  "Aquinas: Political Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  "Aquinas: Theology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
at Find a Grave Thomistic Philosophy Inspired by the enduring thought of Saint
Saint
Thomas Aquinas Article on Thomism
Thomism
by the Jacques Maritain
Jacques Maritain
Center of Notre Dame University Thomistica.net news and newsletter devoted to the academic study of Aquinas Aquinas the Scholar from The Thirteenth, the Greatest of Centuries, ch. XVII. by James Joseph Walsh A discussion of Aquinas on BBC Radio 4's In Our Time series 2009

By Thomas Aquinas[edit]

Corpus Thomisticum – his complete works in (in Latin) Corpus Thomisticum (A Searchable Latin
Latin
text for Android devices) De Rationibus Fidei/Reasons for the Faith
Faith
against Muslim Objections... Documenta Catholica Omnia – his complete works in PDF files, in (in Latin), (in Italian), (in English), (in German), (in Spanish), (in French), (in Portuguese) Summa contra Gentiles
Summa contra Gentiles
[dead link] Summa Theologica The Principles of Nature On Being and Essence (De Ente et Essentia) Catena Aurea (partial) Works by Thomas Aquinas
Works by Thomas Aquinas
at Project Gutenberg Works by or about Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
at Internet Archive Works by Thomas Aquinas
Works by Thomas Aquinas
at LibriVox
LibriVox
(public domain audiobooks) Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
at Goodreads Bibliotheca Thomistica IntraText: texts, concordances and frequency lists An Aquinas Bibliography Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
in English De Magistro (On the teacher q. 11, a.1 of de Veritate) Online Galleries, History of Science Collections, University of Oklahoma Libraries High resolution images of works by Thomas Aquinas in .jpg and .tiff format. Summa totius logicae. [s.n.]: [s.l.], 1880. 96 p. - available online at University Library in Bratislava Digital Library

v t e

Christianity

Jesus

Christ Jesus
Jesus
in Christianity Virgin birth Crucifixion Resurrection Son of God

Foundations

Church Creed Gospel New Covenant

Bible

Books Canon Old Testament New Testament

Theology

God Trinity

Father Son Holy Spirit

Apologetics Baptism Christology Ecclesiology History of theology Mission Salvation

History and tradition

Mary Apostles Peter Paul Fathers Early Constantine Ecumenical councils Augustine East–West Schism Crusades Aquinas Reformation Luther

Denomi- nations and traditions (list)

Western

Adventist Anabaptist Anglican Baptist Calvinist Catholic Charismatic Evangelical Holiness Lutheran Methodist Pentecostal Protestant

Eastern

Eastern Orthodox Oriental Orthodox (Miaphysite) Assyrian Church of the East
Assyrian Church of the East
("Nestorian") Eastern Catholic Churches

Nontrinitarian

Jehovah's Witnesses Latter Day Saint
Saint
movement Oneness Pentecostalism

Related topics

Art Criticism Culture Ecumenism Liturgy Music Other religions Prayer Sermon Symbolism

Category Christianity
Christianity
portal

v t e

History of Catholic theology

General history

History of the Catholic Church Early Christianity History of the papacy Ecumenical Councils Timeline of the Catholic Church History of Christianity History of Christian theology

Church beginnings

Paul Clement of Rome First Epistle of Clement Didache Ignatius of Antioch Polycarp Epistle of Barnabas The Shepherd of Hermas Aristides of Athens Justin Martyr Epistle to Diognetus Irenaeus Montanism Tertullian Origen Antipope Novatian Cyprian

Constantine to Pope
Pope
Gregory I

Eusebius Athanasius of Alexandria Arianism Pelagianism Nestorianism Monophysitism Ephrem the Syrian Hilary of Poitiers Cyril of Jerusalem Basil of Caesarea Gregory of Nazianzus Gregory of Nyssa Ambrose John Chrysostom Jerome Augustine of Hippo John Cassian Orosius Cyril of Alexandria Peter Chrysologus Pope
Pope
Leo I Boethius Pseudo-Dionysius
Pseudo-Dionysius
the Areopagite Pope
Pope
Gregory I

Early Middle Ages

Isidore of Seville John Climacus Maximus the Confessor Monothelitism Ecthesis Bede John of Damascus Iconoclasm Transubstantiation
Transubstantiation
dispute Predestination
Predestination
disputes Paulinus II of Aquileia Alcuin Benedict of Aniane Rabanus Maurus Paschasius Radbertus John Scotus Eriugena

High Middle Ages

Roscellinus Gregory of Narek Berengar of Tours Peter Damian Anselm of Canterbury Joachim of Fiore Peter Abelard Decretum Gratiani Bernard of Clairvaux Peter Lombard Anselm of Laon Hildegard of Bingen Hugh of Saint
Saint
Victor Dominic de Guzmán Robert Grosseteste Francis of Assisi Anthony of Padua Beatrice of Nazareth Bonaventure Albertus Magnus Boetius of Dacia Henry of Ghent Thomas Aquinas Siger of Brabant Thomism Roger Bacon

Mysticism
Mysticism
and reforms

Ramon Llull Duns Scotus Dante
Dante
Alighieri William of Ockham Richard Rolle John of Ruusbroec Catherine of Siena Brigit of Sweden Meister Eckhart Johannes Tauler Walter Hilton The Cloud of Unknowing Heinrich Seuse Geert Groote Devotio Moderna Julian of Norwich Thomas à Kempis Nicholas of Cusa Marsilio Ficino Girolamo Savonarola Giovanni Pico della Mirandola

Reformation Counter-Reformation

Erasmus Thomas Cajetan Thomas More John Fisher Johann Eck Francisco de Vitoria Thomas of Villanova Ignatius of Loyola Francisco de Osuna John of Ávila Francis Xavier Teresa of Ávila Luis de León John of the Cross Peter Canisius Luis de Molina
Luis de Molina
(Molinism) Robert Bellarmine Francisco Suárez Lawrence of Brindisi Francis de Sales

Baroque
Baroque
period to French Revolution

Tommaso Campanella Pierre de Bérulle Pierre Gassendi René Descartes Mary of Jesus
Jesus
of Ágreda António Vieira Jean-Jacques Olier Louis Thomassin Jacques-Bénigne Bossuet François Fénelon Cornelius Jansen
Cornelius Jansen
(Jansenism) Blaise Pascal Nicolas Malebranche Giambattista Vico Alphonsus Liguori Louis de Montfort Maria Gaetana Agnesi Alfonso Muzzarelli Johann Michael Sailer Clement Mary Hofbauer Bruno Lanteri

19th century

Joseph Görres Felicité de Lamennais Luigi Taparelli Antonio Rosmini Ignaz von Döllinger John Henry Newman Henri Lacordaire Jaime Balmes Gaetano Sanseverino Giovanni Maria Cornoldi Wilhelm Emmanuel Freiherr von Ketteler Giuseppe Pecci Joseph Hergenröther Tommaso Maria Zigliara Matthias Joseph Scheeben Émile Boutroux Modernism Léon Bloy Désiré-Joseph Mercier Friedrich von Hügel Vladimir Solovyov Marie-Joseph Lagrange George Tyrrell Maurice Blondel Thérèse of Lisieux

20th century

G. K. Chesterton Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange Joseph Maréchal Pierre Teilhard de Chardin Jacques Maritain Étienne Gilson Ronald Knox Dietrich von Hildebrand Gabriel
Gabriel
Marcel Marie-Dominique Chenu Romano Guardini Edith Stein Fulton Sheen Henri de Lubac Jean Guitton Josemaría Escrivá Adrienne von Speyr Karl Rahner Yves Congar Bernard Lonergan Emmanuel Mounier Jean Daniélou Hans Urs von Balthasar Alfred Delp Edward Schillebeeckx Thomas Merton René Girard Johann Baptist Metz Jean Vanier Henri Nouwen

21st century

Pope
Pope
Benedict XVI Walter Kasper Raniero Cantalamessa Michał Heller Peter Kreeft Jean-Luc Marion Tomáš Halík Scott Hahn Robert Barron

Catholicism portal Pope
Pope
portal

v t e

The Seven Virtues in Christian ethics

Great Commandment; "All the Law
Law
and the Prophets hang on these two commandments." – Matthew 22:35-40

Four Cardinal virtues

Prudence
Prudence
(Prudentia) Justice
Justice
(Iustitia) Fortitude (Fortitudo) Temperance (Temperantia)

Sources: Plato

Republic, Book IV

Cicero Ambrose Augustine of Hippo Thomas Aquinas

Three Theological virtues

Faith
Faith
(Fides) Hope
Hope
(Spes) Love (Caritas)

Sources: Paul the Apostle

1 Corinthians 13

Seven deadly sins

Lust
Lust
(Luxuria) Gluttony
Gluttony
(Gula) Greed
Greed
(Avaritia) Sloth (Acedia) Wrath (Ira) Envy
Envy
(Invidia) Pride
Pride
(Superbia)

Source: Prudentius, Psychomachia

People: Evagrius Ponticus John Cassian Pope
Pope
Gregory I Dante
Dante
Alighieri Peter Binsfeld

Related concepts

Ten Commandments Eschatology Sin

Original sin

Old Covenant Hamartiology

Christian ethics Christian philosophy Christianity
Christianity
portal Philosophy portal

v t e

Medieval philosophers

Islamic

Early

Al-Jahiz Alkindus Ibn al-Rawandi Al-Razi (Rhazes) Al-Farabi
Al-Farabi
(Alpharabius) Ibn Masarra Al Amiri Ebn Meskavayh Ibn al-Haytham (Alhazen) Abu Rayhan Biruni "Brethren of Purity"

High

Ibn Sīnā (Avicenna) Ibn Hazm Al-Ghazali
Al-Ghazali
(Algazel) Abu'l-Barakāt al-Baghdādī Ibn Bajjah (Avempace) Ayn al-Quzat Hamadani Ibn Tufail Ibn Rushd (Averroes)

Late

Ibn Sab'in Shahab al-Din Suhrawardi Fakhr ad-Din ar-Razi Rashid al-Din Ibn Arabi Zachariah Kazwin Abd-el-latif Athīr al-Dīn al-Abharī Nasir al-Din al-Tusi Ibn al-Nafis Qutb al-Din al-Shirazi Ibn Taymiyyah Ibn Khaldun

Jewish

Medieval

Isaac
Isaac
Israeli ben Solomon Saadia Gaon Solomon
Solomon
ibn Gabirol Judah Halevi Abraham
Abraham
ibn Daud Maimonides Nachmanides Gersonides Hasdai Crescas Joseph Albo

Christian

Early

"Church Fathers" Augustine of Hippo Boethius Pseudo-Dionysius
Pseudo-Dionysius
the Areopagite Isidore of Seville Johannes Scotus Eriugena Alcuin

11–12th century

"Scholasticism" Anselm of Canterbury Peter Abelard Anselm of Laon Hugh of Saint
Saint
Victor Richard of Saint
Saint
Victor Roscelin Peter Lombard Alexander of Hales Bernard of Chartres Dominicus Gundissalinus Gilbert de la Porrée Alain de Lille

13–14th century

Robert Grosseteste Albertus Magnus Bonaventure Thomas Aquinas Siger of Brabant Boetius of Dacia Henry of Ghent Roger Bacon John Peckham Ramon Llull Petrus Aureolus Petrus Peregrinus de Maricourt Durandus Giles of Rome Godfrey of Fontaines Duns Scotus William of Ockham

Late

Jean Buridan Nicole Oresme Albert of Saxony Francesc Eiximenis Vincent Ferrer Paul of Venice Lambertus de Monte John Hennon

See also Renaissance philosophy

v t e

Doctors of the Catholic Church

Gregory the Great Ambrose Augustine of Hippo Jerome John Chrysostom Basil of Caesarea Gregory of Nazianzus Athanasius of Alexandria Cyril of Alexandria Cyril of Jerusalem John of Damascus Bede
Bede
the Venerable Ephrem the Syrian Thomas Aquinas Bonaventure Anselm of Canterbury Isidore of Seville Peter Chrysologus Leo the Great Peter Damian Bernard of Clairvaux Hilary of Poitiers Alphonsus Liguori Francis de Sales Peter Canisius John of the Cross Robert Bellarmine Albertus Magnus Anthony of Padua Lawrence of Brindisi Teresa of Ávila Catherine of Siena Thérèse of Lisieux John of Ávila Hildegard of Bingen Gregory of Narek

Catholicism portal

v t e

Social and political philosophy

Pre-modern philosophers

Aquinas Aristotle Averroes Augustine Chanakya Cicero Confucius Al-Ghazali Han Fei Laozi Marsilius Mencius Mozi Muhammad Plato Shang Socrates Sun Tzu Thucydides

Modern philosophers

Bakunin Bentham Bonald Bosanquet Burke Comte Emerson Engels Fourier Franklin Grotius Hegel Hobbes Hume Jefferson Kant Kierkegaard Le Bon Le Play Leibniz Locke Machiavelli Maistre Malebranche Marx Mill Montesquieu Möser Nietzsche Paine Renan Rousseau Royce Sade Smith Spencer Spinoza Stirner Taine Thoreau Tocqueville Vivekananda Voltaire

20th–21th-century Philosophers

Ambedkar Arendt Aurobindo Aron Azurmendi Badiou Baudrillard Bauman Benoist Berlin Judith Butler Camus Chomsky De Beauvoir Debord Du Bois Durkheim Foucault Gandhi Gehlen Gentile Gramsci Habermas Hayek Heidegger Irigaray Kirk Kropotkin Lenin Luxemburg Mao Marcuse Maritain Michels Mises Negri Niebuhr Nozick Oakeshott Ortega Pareto Pettit Plamenatz Polanyi Popper Radhakrishnan Rand Rawls Rothbard Russell Santayana Sarkar Sartre Schmitt Searle Simonović Skinner Sombart Spann Spirito Strauss Sun Taylor Walzer Weber Žižek

Social theories

Ambedkarism Anarchism Authoritarianism Collectivism Communism Communitarianism Conflict theories Confucianism Consensus theory Conservatism Contractualism Cosmopolitanism Culturalism Fascism Feminist political theory Gandhism Individualism Legalism Liberalism Libertarianism Mohism National liberalism Republicanism Social constructionism Social constructivism Social Darwinism Social determinism Socialism Utilitarianism Vaisheshika

Concepts

Civil disobedience Democracy Four occupations Justice Law Mandate of Heaven Peace Property Revolution Rights Social contract Society War more...

Related articles

Jurisprudence Philosophy and economics Philosophy of education Philosophy of history Philosophy of love Philosophy of sex Philosophy of social science Political ethics Social epistemology

Category Portal Task Force

v t e

Ethics

Theories

Casuistry Consequentialism Deontology

Kantian ethics

Ethics
Ethics
of care Existentialist ethics Meta-ethics Particularism Pragmatic ethics Role ethics Virtue
Virtue
ethics

Concepts

Autonomy Axiology Belief Conscience Consent Equality Care Free will Good and evil Happiness Ideal Justice Morality Norm Freedom Principles Suffering
Suffering
or Pain Stewardship Sympathy Trust Value Virtue Wrong full index...

Philosophers

Laozi Plato Aristotle Diogenes Valluvar Cicero Confucius Augustine of Hippo Mencius Mozi Xunzi Thomas Aquinas Baruch Spinoza David
David
Hume Immanuel Kant Georg W. F. Hegel Arthur Schopenhauer Jeremy Bentham John Stuart Mill Søren Kierkegaard Henry Sidgwick Friedrich Nietzsche G. E. Moore Karl Barth Paul Tillich Dietrich Bonhoeffer Philippa Foot John Rawls John Dewey Bernard Williams J. L. Mackie G. E. M. Anscombe William Frankena Alasdair MacIntyre R. M. Hare Peter Singer Derek Parfit Thomas Nagel Robert Merrihew Adams Charles Taylor Joxe Azurmendi Christine Korsgaard Martha Nussbaum more...

Applied ethics

Bioethics Business ethics Discourse ethics Engineering ethics Environmental ethics Legal ethics Media ethics Medical ethics Nursing ethics Professional ethics Sexual ethics Ethics
Ethics
of eating meat Ethics
Ethics
of technology

Related articles

Christian ethics Descriptive ethics Ethics
Ethics
in religion Evolutionary ethics Feminist ethics History of ethics Ideology Islamic ethics Jewish ethics Normative ethics Philosophy of law Political philosophy Population ethics Social philosophy

Portal Category

v t e

Saints of the Catholic Church

Virgin Mary

Mother of God (Theotokos) Immaculate Conception Perpetual virginity Assumption Marian apparition

Guadalupe Laus Miraculous Medal Lourdes Fatima

Titles of Mary

Apostles

Andrew Barnabas Bartholomew James of Alphaeus James the Greater John Jude Matthew Matthias Paul Peter Philip Simon Thomas

Archangels

Gabriel Michael Raphael

Confessors

Anatolius Chariton the Confessor Edward the Confessor Maximus the Confessor Michael of Synnada Paphnutius the Confessor Paul I of Constantinople Salonius Theophanes the Confessor

Disciples

Apollos Mary Magdalene Priscilla and Aquila Silvanus Stephen Timothy Titus Seventy disciples

Doctors

Gregory the Great Ambrose Augustine of Hippo Jerome John Chrysostom Basil of Caesarea Gregory of Nazianzus Athanasius of Alexandria Cyril of Alexandria Cyril of Jerusalem John of Damascus Bede
Bede
the Venerable Ephrem the Syrian Thomas Aquinas Bonaventure Anselm of Canterbury Isidore of Seville Peter Chrysologus Leo the Great Peter Damian Bernard of Clairvaux Hilary of Poitiers Alphonsus Liguori Francis de Sales Peter Canisius John of the Cross Robert Bellarmine Albertus Magnus Anthony of Padua Lawrence of Brindisi Teresa of Ávila Catherine of Siena Thérèse of Lisieux John of Ávila Hildegard of Bingen Gregory of Narek

Evangelists

Matthew Mark Luke John

Church Fathers

Alexander of Alexandria Alexander of Jerusalem Ambrose
Ambrose
of Milan Anatolius Athanasius of Alexandria Augustine of Hippo Caesarius of Arles Caius Cappadocian Fathers Clement of Alexandria Clement of Rome Cyprian
Cyprian
of Carthage Cyril of Alexandria Cyril of Jerusalem Damasus I Desert Fathers Desert Mothers Dionysius of Alexandria Dionysius of Corinth Dionysius Ephrem the Syrian Epiphanius of Salamis Fulgentius of Ruspe Gregory the Great Gregory of Nazianzus Gregory of Nyssa Hilary of Poitiers Hippolytus of Rome Ignatius of Antioch Irenaeus
Irenaeus
of Lyons Isidore of Seville Jerome
Jerome
of Stridonium John Chrysostom John of Damascus Maximus the Confessor Melito of Sardis Quadratus of Athens Papias of Hierapolis Peter Chrysologus Polycarp
Polycarp
of Smyrna Theophilus of Antioch Victorinus of Pettau Vincent of Lérins Zephyrinus

Martyrs

Canadian Martyrs Carthusian Martyrs Forty Martyrs of England and Wales Four Crowned Martyrs Great Martyr The Holy Innocents Irish Martyrs Joan of Arc Lübeck martyrs Korean Martyrs Martyrology Martyrs of Albania Martyrs of China Martyrs of Japan Martyrs of Laos Martyrs of Natal Martyrs of Otranto Martyrs of the Spanish Civil War Maximilian Kolbe Perpetua and Felicity Saints of the Cristero War Stephen Three Martyrs of Chimbote Uganda Martyrs Vietnamese Martyrs

Patriarchs

Adam Abel Abraham Isaac Jacob Joseph Joseph (father of Jesus) David Noah Solomon Matriarchs

Popes

Adeodatus I Adeodatus II Adrian III Agapetus I Agatho Alexander I Anacletus Anastasius I Anicetus Anterus Benedict II Boniface I Boniface IV Caius Callixtus I Celestine I Celestine V Clement I Cornelius Damasus I Dionysius Eleuterus Eugene I Eusebius Eutychian Evaristus Fabian Felix I Felix III Felix IV Gelasius I Gregory I Gregory II Gregory III Gregory VII Hilarius Hormisdas Hyginus Innocent I John I John XXIII John Paul II Julius I Leo I Leo II Leo III Leo IV Leo IX Linus Lucius I Marcellinus Marcellus I Mark Martin I Miltiades Nicholas I Paschal I Paul I Peter Pius I Pius V Pius X Pontian Sergius I Silverius Simplicius Siricius Sixtus I Sixtus II Sixtus III Soter Stephen I Stephen IV Sylvester I Symmachus Telesphorus Urban I Victor I Vitalian Zachary Zephyrinus Zosimus

Prophets

Agabus Amos Anna Baruch ben Neriah David Dalua Elijah Ezekiel Habakkuk Haggai Hosea Isaiah Jeremiah Job Joel John the Baptist Jonah Judas Barsabbas Malachi Melchizedek Micah Moses Nahum Obadiah Samuel Seven Maccabees and their mother Simeon Zechariah (prophet) Zechariah (NT) Zephaniah

Virgins

Agatha of Sicily Agnes of Rome Bernadette Soubirous Brigid of Kildare Cecilia Clare of Assisi Eulalia of Mérida Euphemia Genevieve Kateri Tekakwitha Lucy of Syracuse Maria Goretti Mother Teresa Narcisa de Jesús Rose of Lima

See also

Military saints Virtuous pagan

Catholicism portal Saints portal

v t e

Aristotelianism

Overview

Peripatetic school Physics Biology Ethics Logic Theology (unmoved mover)

Ideas and interests

Correspondence theory of truth Hexis Virtue
Virtue
ethics (golden mean) Four causes Telos Phronesis Eudaimonia Arete Temporal finitism Antiperistasis Philosophy of nature (sublunary sphere) Potentiality and actuality Universals (substantial form) Hylomorphism Mimesis Catharsis Substance (hypokeimenon, ousia, transcendentals) Essence–accident Category of being Minima naturalia Magnanimity Sensus communis Rational animal Genus–differentia Mythos

Corpus Aristotelicum

Physics Organon Nicomachean Ethics Politics Metaphysics On the Soul Rhetoric Poetics

Followers

Alexander the Great Theophrastus Avicenna Averroes Maimonides Thomas Aquinas Mortimer Adler Alasdair MacIntyre Martha Nussbaum

Related topics

Platonism Commentaries on Aristotle Recovery of Aristotle Scholasticism Conimbricenses Pseudo-Aristotle Views on women Aristotle's wheel paradox Aristotle's razor

Philosophy portal

Authority control

WorldCat Identities VIAF: 100910150 LCCN: n78095790 ISNI: 0000 0001 2096 7428 GND: 118622110 SELIBR: 199675 SUDOC: 027161129 BNF: cb11926496p (data) ULAN: 500330859 MusicBrainz: ea7f0f74-18fc-409c-ba6c-ed1cae12cddc NLA: 36520996 NDL: 00458645 NKC: jn19981002237 ICCU: ITICCUCFIV08124 BNE: XX933930 SNAC: w6sb47xx

v t e

Violence against women

Issues

Abuse during childbirth Acid throwing Breast ironing Bride burning Bride buying Dating abuse Domestic violence

outline management and pregnancy

Dowry death Eve teasing Honor killing Female genital mutilation

Gishiri cutting Infibulation Husband stitch

Female infanticide Femicide Foot binding Force-feeding Forced abortion Forced marriage Forced pregnancy Forced prostitution Human trafficking Murder of pregnant women Raptio Sati Violence against prostitutes

Sexual assault, rape

Sexual assault

Campus sexual assault Mass sexual assault

Rape

and pregnancy laws

Types of rape

by deception corrective date gang genocidal in war marital prison statutory

Sexual slavery Sexual violence

Related topics

Prosecution of gender-targeted crimes November 25th February 6th Serial rapi

.