Subsets
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematics, Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset of ''B''. The relationship of one set being a subset of another is called inclusion (or sometimes containment). ''A'' is a subset of ''B'' may also be expressed as ''B'' includes (or contains) ''A'' or ''A'' is included (or contained) in ''B''. A ''k''-subset is a subset with ''k'' elements. The subset relation defines a partial order on sets. In fact, the subsets of a given set form a Boolean algebra (structure), Boolean algebra under the subset relation, in which the join and meet are given by Intersection (set theory), intersection and Union (set theory), union, and the subset relation itself is the Inclusion (Boolean algebra), Boolean inclusion relation.


Definition

If ''A'' and ''B'' are sets and every element (mathematics), element of ''A'' is also an element of ''B'', then: :*''A'' is a subset of ''B'', denoted by A \subseteq B, or equivalently, :* ''B'' is a superset of ''A'', denoted by B \supseteq A. If ''A'' is a subset of ''B'', but ''A'' is not equal (math), equal to ''B'' (i.e. there exists at least one element of B which is not an element of ''A''), then: :*''A'' is a proper (or strict) subset of ''B'', denoted by A \subsetneq B, or equivalently, :* ''B'' is a proper (or strict) superset of ''A'', denoted by B \supsetneq A. The empty set, written \ or \varnothing, is a subset of any set ''X'' and a proper subset of any set except itself, the inclusion Binary relation, relation \subseteq is a partial order on the set \mathcal(S) (the power set of ''S''—the set of all subsets of ''S'') defined by A \leq B \iff A \subseteq B. We may also partially order \mathcal(S) by reverse set inclusion by defining A \leq B \text B \subseteq A. When quantified, A \subseteq B is represented as \forall x \left(x \in A \implies x \in B\right). We can prove the statement A \subseteq B by applying a proof technique known as the element argument:
Let sets ''A'' and ''B'' be given. To prove that A \subseteq B, # suppose that ''a'' is a particular but arbitrarily chosen element of A # show that ''a'' is an element of ''B''.
The validity of this technique can be seen as a consequence of Universal generalization: the technique shows c \in A \implies c \in B for an arbitrarily chosen element ''c''. Universal generalisation then implies \forall x \left(x \in A \implies x \in B\right), which is equivalent to A \subseteq B, as stated above. The set of all subsets of A is called its powerset, and is denoted by \mathcal(A). The set of all k-subsets of A is denoted by \tbinom, in analogue with the notation for binomial coefficients, which count the number of k-subsets of an n-element set. In set theory, the notation [A]^k is also common, especially when k is a transfinite number, transfinite cardinal number.


Properties

* A set ''A'' is a subset of ''B'' if and only if their intersection is equal to A. :Formally: : A \subseteq B \text A \cap B = A. * A set ''A'' is a subset of ''B'' if and only if their union is equal to B. :Formally: : A \subseteq B \text A \cup B = B. * A finite set ''A'' is a subset of ''B'', if and only if the cardinality of their intersection is equal to the cardinality of A. :Formally: : A \subseteq B \text , A \cap B, = , A, .


⊂ and ⊃ symbols

Some authors use the symbols \subset and \supset to indicate and respectively; that is, with the same meaning as and instead of the symbols \subseteq and \supseteq. For example, for these authors, it is true of every set ''A'' that A \subset A. Other authors prefer to use the symbols \subset and \supset to indicate (also called strict) subset and superset respectively; that is, with the same meaning as and instead of the symbols \subsetneq and \supsetneq. This usage makes \subseteq and \subset analogous to the inequality (mathematics), inequality symbols \leq and <. For example, if x \leq y, then ''x'' may or may not equal ''y'', but if x < y, then ''x'' definitely does not equal ''y'', and ''is'' less than ''y''. Similarly, using the convention that \subset is proper subset, if A \subseteq B, then ''A'' may or may not equal ''B'', but if A \subset B, then ''A'' definitely does not equal ''B''.


Examples of subsets

* The set A = is a proper subset of B = , thus both expressions A \subseteq B and A \subsetneq B are true. * The set D = is a subset (but a proper subset) of E = , thus D \subseteq E is true, and D \subsetneq E is not true (false). * Any set is a subset of itself, but not a proper subset. (X \subseteq X is true, and X \subsetneq X is false for any set X.) * The set is a proper subset of * The set of natural numbers is a proper subset of the set of rational numbers; likewise, the set of points in a line segment is a proper subset of the set of points in a :ine (mathematics), line. These are two examples in which both the subset and the whole set are infinite, and the subset has the same Cardinality#Infinite sets, cardinality (the concept that corresponds to size, that is, the number of elements, of a finite set) as the whole; such cases can run counter to one's initial intuition. * The set of Rational number, rational numbers is a proper subset of the set of real numbers. In this example, both sets are infinite, but the latter set has a larger cardinality (or ) than the former set. Another example in an Euler diagram: File:Example of A is a proper subset of B.svg, A is a proper subset of B File:Example of C is no proper subset of B.svg, C is a subset but not a proper subset of B


Other properties of inclusion

Inclusion is the canonical partial order, in the sense that every partially ordered set (X, \preceq) is isomorphic to some collection of sets ordered by inclusion. The ordinal numbers are a simple example: if each ordinal ''n'' is identified with the set [n] of all ordinals less than or equal to ''n'', then a \leq b if and only if [a] \subseteq [b]. For the power set \operatorname(S) of a set ''S'', the inclusion partial order is—up to an order isomorphism—the Cartesian product of k = , S, (the cardinality of ''S'') copies of the partial order on \ for which 0 < 1. This can be illustrated by enumerating S = \left\,, and associating with each subset T \subseteq S (i.e., each element of 2^S) the ''k''-tuple from \^k, of which the ''i''th coordinate is 1 if and only if s_i is a set membership, member of ''T''.


See also

* Convex subset * Inclusion order * Region (mathematics), Region * Subset sum problem * Hierarchy#Subsumptive_containment_hierarchy, Subsumptive containment * Total subset


References


Bibliography

*


External links

* * {{Common logical symbols Basic concepts in set theory