Subjunctive possibility
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Subjunctive possibility (also called alethic possibility) is a form of modality studied in modal logic. Subjunctive possibilities are the sorts of possibilities considered when conceiving
counterfactual Counterfactual conditionals (also ''subjunctive'' or ''X-marked'') are conditional sentences which discuss what would have been true under different circumstances, e.g. "If Peter believed in ghosts, he would be afraid to be here." Counterfactual ...
situations; subjunctive modalities are modalities that bear on whether a statement ''might have been'' or ''could be'' true—such as ''might'', ''could'', ''must'', ''possibly'', ''necessarily'', ''contingently'', ''essentially'', ''accidentally'', and so on. Subjunctive possibilities include
logical possibility Logical possibility refers to a logical proposition that cannot be disproved, using the axioms and rules of a given system of logic. The logical possibility of a proposition will depend upon the system of logic being considered, rather than on th ...
,
metaphysical Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the fundamental nature of reality, the first principles of being, identity and change, space and time, causality, necessity, and possibility. It includes questions about the nature of conscio ...
possibility,
nomological In philosophy, nomology refers to a "science of laws" based on the theory that it is possible to elaborate descriptions dedicated not to particular aspects of reality but inspired by a scientific vision of universal validity expressed by scientific ...
possibility, and temporal possibility.


Subjunctive possibility and other modalities

Subjunctive possibility is contrasted with (among other things)
epistemic possibility In philosophy and modal logic, epistemic possibility relates a statement under consideration to the current state of our knowledge about the actual world: a statement is said to be: * ''epistemically possible'' if it ''may be true, for all we kn ...
(which deals with how the world ''may'' be, ''for all we know'') and deontic possibility (which deals with how the world ''ought'' to be).


Epistemic possibility

The contrast with epistemic possibility is especially important to draw, since in ordinary language the same phrases ("it's possible," "it can't be", "it must be") are often used to express either sort of possibility. But they are not the same. We do not ''know'' whether Goldbach's conjecture is true or not (no-one has come up with a proof yet); so it is (epistemically) ''possible that'' it is true and it is (epistemically) ''possible that'' it is false. But if it ''is'', in fact, provably true (as it may be, for all we know), then it would have to be (subjunctively) ''necessarily'' true; what being provable ''means'' is that it would not be (logically) ''possible for'' it to be false. Similarly, it might not be at all (epistemically) ''possible that'' it is raining outside—we might ''know'' beyond a shadow of a doubt that it is not—but that would hardly mean that it is (subjunctively) ''impossible for'' it to rain outside. This point is also made by Norman Swartz and Raymond Bradley.Norman Swartz and Raymond Bradley, ''Possible Worlds — An Introduction to logic and its philosophy'', 1979, Hackett Publishing company, inc., . pp. 329–330


Deontic possibility

There is some overlap in language between subjunctive possibilities and deontic possibilities: for example, we sometimes use the statement "You can/cannot do that" to express (i) what it is or is not subjunctively possible for you to do, and we sometimes use it to express (ii) what it would or would not be right for you to do. The two are less likely to be confused in ordinary language than subjunctive and epistemic possibility as there are some important differences in the logic of subjunctive modalities and deontic modalities. In particular, subjunctive necessity entails truth: if people logically must such and such, then you can infer that they actually do it. But in this non-ideal world, a deontic ‘must’ does not carry the moral certitude that people morally must do such and such.


Types of subjunctive possibility

There are several different types of subjunctive modality, which can be classified as broader or more narrow than one another depending on how restrictive the rules for what counts as "possible" are. Some of the most commonly discussed are: *
Logical possibility Logical possibility refers to a logical proposition that cannot be disproved, using the axioms and rules of a given system of logic. The logical possibility of a proposition will depend upon the system of logic being considered, rather than on th ...
is usually considered the broadest sort of possibility; a proposition is said to be logically possible if there is no logical contradiction involved in its being true. " Dick Cheney is a bachelor" is logically possible, though in fact false; most philosophers have thought that statements like "If I flap my arms very hard, I will fly" are ''logically'' possible, although they are ''nomologically'' impossible. " Dick Cheney is a married bachelor," on the other hand, is ''logically impossible''; anyone who is a bachelor is ''therefore'' not married, so this proposition is logically self-contradictory (though the sentence isn't, because it is logically possible for "bachelor" to mean "married man"). *
Metaphysical Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the fundamental nature of reality, the first principles of being, identity and change, space and time, causality, necessity, and possibility. It includes questions about the nature of conscio ...
possibility is either equivalent to logical possibility or narrower than it (what a philosopher thinks the relationship between the two is depends, in part, on the philosopher's view of
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premise ...
). Some philosophers have held that ''discovered identities'' such as Kripke's "Water is H2O" are metaphysically necessary but not logically necessary (they would claim that there is no formal contradiction involved in "Water is ''not'' H2O" even though it turns out to be metaphysically impossible). *
Nomological In philosophy, nomology refers to a "science of laws" based on the theory that it is possible to elaborate descriptions dedicated not to particular aspects of reality but inspired by a scientific vision of universal validity expressed by scientific ...
possibility is ''possibility under the actual laws of nature''. Most philosophers since
David Hume David Hume (; born David Home; 7 May 1711 NS (26 April 1711 OS) – 25 August 1776) Cranston, Maurice, and Thomas Edmund Jessop. 2020 999br>David Hume" ''Encyclopædia Britannica''. Retrieved 18 May 2020. was a Scottish Enlightenment phil ...
have held that the laws of nature are ''metaphysically contingent''—that there could have been different natural laws than the ones that actually obtain. If so, then it would not be ''logically'' or ''metaphysically'' impossible, for example, for you to travel to Alpha Centauri in one day; it would just have to be the case that you could travel faster than the
speed of light The speed of light in vacuum, commonly denoted , is a universal physical constant that is important in many areas of physics. The speed of light is exactly equal to ). According to the special theory of relativity, is the upper limit ...
. But of course there is an important sense in which this is ''not'' possible; ''given'' that the laws of nature are what they are, there is no way that you could do it. (Some philosophers, such as Sydney Shoemaker , have argued that the laws of nature are in fact ''necessary'', not contingent; if so, then nomological possibility is equivalent to metaphysical possibility.) * Temporal possibility is ''possibility given the actual history of the world''. David Lewis ''could have'' chosen to take his degree in Accounting rather than Philosophy; but there is an important sense in which he ''cannot now''. The "could have" expresses the fact that there is no logical, metaphysical, or even nomological impossibility involved in Lewis's having a degree in Economics instead of Philosophy; the "cannot now" expresses the fact that that possibility is no longer open to becoming actual, given that the past is as it actually is. Similarly David Lewis could have taken a degree in Economics but not in, say, Aviation (because it was not taught at Harvard) or Cognitive Neuroscience (because the so-called 'conceptual space' for such a major did not exist). There is some debate whether this final type of possibility in fact constitutes a type of possibility distinct from Temporal, and is sometimes called Historical Possibility by thinkers like Ian Hacking.


References

{{Reflist Modal logic Possibility Concepts in metaphysics