Rawlsian utility
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
welfare economics Welfare economics is a branch of economics that uses microeconomic techniques to evaluate well-being (welfare) at the aggregate (economy-wide) level. Attempting to apply the principles of welfare economics gives rise to the field of public ec ...
, a social welfare function is a
function Function or functionality may refer to: Computing * Function key, a type of key on computer keyboards * Function model, a structured representation of processes in a system * Function object or functor or functionoid, a concept of object-oriente ...
that ranks social states (alternative complete descriptions of the society) as less desirable, more desirable, or indifferent for every possible pair of social states. Inputs of the function include any variables considered to affect the
economic welfare The welfare definition of economics is an attempt by Alfred Marshall, a pioneer of neoclassical economics, to redefine his field of study. This definition expands the field of economic science to a larger study of humanity. Specifically, Marshall's ...
of a society. In using welfare measures of persons in the society as inputs, the social welfare function is
individualistic Individualism is the moral stance, political philosophy, ideology and social outlook that emphasizes the intrinsic worth of the individual. Individualists promote the exercise of one's goals and desires and to value independence and self-relianc ...
in form. One use of a social welfare function is to
represent Represent may refer to: * ''Represent'' (Compton's Most Wanted album) or the title song, 2000 * ''Represent'' (Fat Joe album), 1993 * ''Represent'', an album by DJ Magic Mike, 1994 * "Represent" (song), by Nas, 1994 * "Represent", a song by the ...
prospective patterns of collective choice as to alternative social states. The social welfare function provides the government with a simple guideline for achieving the optimal distribution of income. The social welfare function is analogous to the
consumer theory The theory of consumer choice is the branch of microeconomics that relates preferences to consumption expenditures and to consumer demand curves. It analyzes how consumers maximize the desirability of their consumption as measured by their pref ...
of indifference-curve– budget constraint tangency for an individual, except that the social welfare function is a mapping of individual preferences or judgments of everyone in the society as to collective choices, which apply to all, whatever individual preferences are for (variable) constraints on factors of production. One point of a social welfare function is to determine how close the analogy is to an ordinal
utility function As a topic of economics, utility is used to model worth or value. Its usage has evolved significantly over time. The term was introduced initially as a measure of pleasure or happiness as part of the theory of utilitarianism by moral philosoph ...
for an individual with at least minimal restrictions suggested by welfare economics, including constraints on the number of
factors of production In economics, factors of production, resources, or inputs are what is used in the production process to produce output—that is, goods and services. The utilized amounts of the various inputs determine the quantity of output according to the rel ...
. There are two major distinct but related types of social welfare functions: * A Bergson–Samuelson social welfare function considers welfare for a ''given set'' of individual preferences or welfare rankings. * An Arrow social welfare function considers welfare across ''different possible sets'' of individual preferences or welfare rankings and seemingly reasonable axioms that constrain the function.Prasanta K. Pattanaik, 2008. "social welfare function," ''
The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics ''The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics'' (2018), 3rd ed., is a twenty-volume reference work on economics published by Palgrave Macmillan. It contains around 3,000 entries, including many classic essays from the original Inglis Palgrave Diction ...
'', 2nd Edition
Abstract.
/ref>


Bergson–Samuelson social welfare function

In a 1938 article,
Abram Bergson Abram Bergson (born Abram Burk, April 21, 1914 in Baltimore, Maryland – April 23, 2003 in Cambridge, Massachusetts) was an American economist, academician, and professor in the Harvard Economics Department since 1956. Early life and educatio ...
introduced the ''social welfare function''. The object was "to state in precise form the value judgments required for the derivation of the conditions of maximum economic welfare" set out by earlier writers, including
Marshall Marshall may refer to: Places Australia * Marshall, Victoria, a suburb of Geelong, Victoria Canada * Marshall, Saskatchewan * The Marshall, a mountain in British Columbia Liberia * Marshall, Liberia Marshall Islands * Marshall Islands, an i ...
and Pigou, Pareto and Barone, and
Lerner Lerner is a German and Jewish family name. Its literal meaning can be either "student" or "scholar". It may refer to: Organizations * Lerner Enterprises, a real estate company * Lerner Newspapers * Lerner Publishing Group, a publisher of child ...
. The function was real-valued and
differentiable In mathematics, a differentiable function of one real variable is a function whose derivative exists at each point in its domain. In other words, the graph of a differentiable function has a non-vertical tangent line at each interior point in its ...
. It was specified to describe the society as a whole. Arguments of the function included the quantities of different commodities produced and consumed and of
resources Resource refers to all the materials available in our environment which are technologically accessible, economically feasible and culturally sustainable and help us to satisfy our needs and wants. Resources can broadly be classified upon their av ...
used in producing different commodities, including labor. Necessary general conditions are that at the maximum value of the function: * The marginal "dollar's worth" of welfare is equal for each individual and for each commodity * The marginal "diswelfare" of each "dollar's worth" of labor is equal for each commodity produced of each labor supplier * The marginal "dollar" cost of each unit of resources is equal to the marginal value productivity for each commodity. Bergson showed how
welfare economics Welfare economics is a branch of economics that uses microeconomic techniques to evaluate well-being (welfare) at the aggregate (economy-wide) level. Attempting to apply the principles of welfare economics gives rise to the field of public ec ...
could describe a standard of economic efficiency despite dispensing with ''interpersonally-comparable''
cardinal utility In economics, a cardinal utility function or scale is a utility index that preserves preference orderings uniquely up to positive affine transformations. Two utility indices are related by an affine transformation if for the value u(x_i) of one i ...
, the hypothesization of which may merely conceal value judgments, and purely subjective ones at that. Auxiliary specifications enable comparison of different social states by each member of society in preference satisfaction. These help define ''
Pareto efficiency Pareto efficiency or Pareto optimality is a situation where no action or allocation is available that makes one individual better off without making another worse off. The concept is named after Vilfredo Pareto (1848–1923), Italian civil engi ...
'', which holds if all alternatives have been exhausted to put at least one person in a more preferred position with no one put in a less preferred position. Bergson described an "economic welfare increase" (later called a ''Pareto improvement'') as at least one individual moving to a more preferred position with everyone else indifferent. The social welfare function could then be specified in a ''substantively'' individualistic sense to derive Pareto efficiency (optimality).
Paul Samuelson Paul Anthony Samuelson (May 15, 1915 – December 13, 2009) was an American economist who was the first American to win the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences. When awarding the prize in 1970, the Swedish Royal Academies stated that he " ...
(2004, p. 26) notes that Bergson's function "could derive Pareto optimality conditions as ''necessary'' but not sufficient for defining interpersonal normative equity." Still, Pareto efficiency could also characterize ''one'' dimension of a particular social welfare function with distribution of commodities among individuals characterizing ''another'' dimension. As Bergson noted, a welfare improvement from the social welfare function could come from the "position of some individuals" improving at the expense of others. That social welfare function could then be described as characterizing an equity dimension. Samuelson ( 1947, p. 221) himself stressed the flexibility of the social welfare function to characterize ''any'' one ethical belief, Pareto-bound or not, consistent with: * a complete and transitive ranking (an ethically "better", "worse", or "indifferent" ranking) of all social alternatives and * one set out of an infinity of welfare indices and cardinal indicators to characterize the belief. He also presented a lucid verbal and mathematical exposition of the social welfare function (1947, pp. 219–49) with minimal use of Lagrangean multipliers and without the difficult notation of differentials used by Bergson throughout. As Samuelson (1983, p. xxii) notes, Bergson clarified how production and consumption efficiency conditions are distinct from the interpersonal ethical values of the social welfare function. Samuelson further sharpened that distinction by specifying the ''Welfare function'' and the ''Possibility function'' (1947, pp. 243–49). Each has as
arguments An argument is a statement or group of statements called premises intended to determine the degree of truth or acceptability of another statement called conclusion. Arguments can be studied from three main perspectives: the logical, the dialectic ...
the set of utility functions for everyone in the society. Each can (and commonly does) incorporate Pareto efficiency. The Possibility function also depends on technology and resource restraints. It is written in implicit form, reflecting the ''feasible'' locus of utility combinations imposed by the restraints and allowed by Pareto efficiency. At a given point on the Possibility function, if the utility of all but one person is determined, the remaining person's utility is determined. The Welfare function ranks different hypothetical ''sets'' of utility for everyone in the society from ethically lowest on up (with ties permitted), that is, it makes interpersonal comparisons of utility. Welfare maximization then consists of maximizing the Welfare function subject to the Possibility function as a constraint. The same welfare maximization conditions emerge as in Bergson's analysis.


Arrow social welfare function (constitution)

Kenneth Arrow Kenneth Joseph Arrow (23 August 1921 – 21 February 2017) was an American economist, mathematician, writer, and political theorist. He was the joint winner of the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences with John Hicks in 1972. In economics ...
(
1963 Events January * January 1 – Bogle–Chandler case: Commonwealth Scientific and Industrial Research Organisation scientist Dr. Gilbert Bogle and Mrs. Margaret Chandler are found dead (presumed poisoned), in bushland near the Lane Co ...
) generalizes the analysis. Along earlier lines, his version of a social welfare function, also called a 'constitution', maps a set of individual orderings (ordinal utility functions) for everyone in the society to a social ordering, a rule for ranking alternative social states (say passing an enforceable law or not, ceteris paribus). Arrow finds that nothing of behavioral significance is lost by dropping the requirement of social orderings that are ''real-valued'' (and thus cardinal utility, cardinal) in favor of orderings, which are merely ''complete'' and ''transitive'', such as a standard indifference curve map. The earlier analysis mapped any set of individual orderings to ''one'' social ordering, whatever it was. This social ordering selected the top-ranked ''feasible'' alternative from the economic environment as to production possibility frontier, resource constraints. Arrow proposed to examine mapping different sets of individual orderings to possibly different social orderings. Here the social ordering would depend on the set of individual orderings, rather than being ''imposed'' (invariant to them). Stunningly (relative to a course of theory from Invisible hand, Adam Smith and Jeremy Bentham on), Arrow proved the ''Arrow's impossibility theorem, general impossibility theorem'' which says that it is impossible to have a social welfare function that satisfies a certain set of "apparently reasonable" conditions.


Cardinal social welfare functions

A cardinal social welfare function is a function that takes as input numeric representations of individual utilities (also known as
cardinal utility In economics, a cardinal utility function or scale is a utility index that preserves preference orderings uniquely up to positive affine transformations. Two utility indices are related by an affine transformation if for the value u(x_i) of one i ...
), and returns as output a numeric representation of the collective welfare. The underlying assumption is that individuals utilities can be put on a common scale and compared. Examples of such measures can be: * life expectancy, * per capita income. For the purposes of this section, income is adopted as the measurement of utility. The form of the social welfare function is intended to express a statement of objectives of a society. The utilitarian or Benthamite social welfare function measures social welfare as the total or sum of individual incomes: :W = \sum_^n Y_i where W is social welfare and Y_i is the income of individual i among n individuals in society. In this case, maximizing the social welfare means maximizing the total income of the people in the society, without regard to how incomes are distributed in society. It does not distinguish between an income transfer from rich to poor and vice versa. If an income transfer from the poor to the rich results in a bigger increase in the utility of the rich than the decrease in the utility of the poor, the society is expected to accept such a transfer, because the total utility of the society has increased as a whole. Alternatively, society's welfare can also be measured under this function by taking the average of individual incomes: :W = \frac\sum_^n Y_i = \overline In contrast, the max-min or Rawlsian social welfare function (based on the philosophical work of John Rawls) measures the social welfare of society on the basis of the welfare of the least well-off individual member of society: :W = \min(Y_1, Y_2, \cdots, Y_n) Here maximizing societal welfare would mean maximizing the income of the poorest person in society without regard for the income of other individuals. These two social welfare functions express very different views about how a society would need to be organised in order to maximize welfare, with the first emphasizing total incomes and the second emphasizing the needs of the worst-off. The max-min welfare function can be seen as reflecting an extreme form of uncertainty aversion on the part of society as a whole, since it is concerned only with the worst conditions that a member of society could face. Amartya Sen proposed a welfare function in 1973: :W_\mathrm = \overline (1-G) The average per capita income of a measured group (e.g. nation) is multiplied with (1-G) where G is the Gini index, a relative inequality measure. James E. Foster (1996) proposed to use one of Anthony Barnes Atkinson, Atkinson's Indexes, which is an entropy measure. Due to the relation between Atkinsons entropy measure and the Theil index, Foster's welfare function also can be computed directly using the Theil-L Index. :W_\mathrm = \overline \mathrm^ The value yielded by this function has a concrete meaning. There are several possible incomes which could be earned by a ''person'', who randomly is selected from a population with an unequal distribution of incomes. This welfare function marks the income, which a randomly selected person is most likely to have. Similar to the median, this income will be smaller than the average per capita income. :W_\mathrm = \overline \mathrm^ Here the Theil-T index is applied. The inverse value yielded by this function has a concrete meaning as well. There are several possible incomes to which a ''Euro'' may belong, which is randomly picked from the sum of all unequally distributed incomes. This welfare function marks the income, which a randomly selected Euro most likely belongs to. The inverse value of that function will be larger than the average per capita income. The Theil index, article on the Theil index provides further information about how this index is used in order to compute welfare functions.


Axioms of cardinal welfarism

Suppose we are given a preference relation ''R'' on utility profiles. ''R'' is a weak total order on utility profiles—it can tell us, given any two utility profiles, if they are indifferent or one of them is better than the other. A reasonable preference ordering should satisfy several axioms: 1. Monotonicity, i.e., if the utility of an individual increases while all other utilities remain equal, ''R'' should strictly prefer the second profile. E.g., it should prefer the profile (1,4,4,5) to (1,2,4,5). This is related to Pareto optimality. 2. Symmetry, i.e., ''R'' should be indifferent to permutation of the numbers in the utility profile. E.g., it should be indifferent between (1,4,4,5) and (5,4,1,4). 3. Continuity: for every profile ''v'', the set of profiles weakly better than ''v'' and the set of profiles weakly worse than ''v'' are closed sets. 4. Independence of unconcerned agents, i.e., ''R'' should be independent of individuals whose utilities have not changed. E.g., if ''R'' prefers (2,2,4) to (1,3,4), then it also prefers (2,2,9) to (1,3,9); the utility of agent 3 should not affect the comparison between two utility profiles of agents 1 and 2. This property can also be called locality or separability. It allows us to treat allocation problems in a local way, and separate them from the allocation in the rest of society. Every preference relation with properties 1–4 can be represented as by a function ''W'' which is a sum of the form: :W(u_1,\dots,u_n) = \sum_^n w(u_i) where ''w'' is a continuous increasing function. It is also reasonable to require: 5. Independence of common scale, i.e., the relation between two utility profiles does not change if both of them are multiplied by the same scalar (e.g., the relation does not depend on whether we measure the income in cents, dollars or thousands). If the preference relation has properties 1–5, then the function ''w'' belongs to the following one-parameter family: * w_p(x) = x^p for p>0, * w_0(x) = \ln(x) for p=0, * w_p(x) = -x^p for p<0. This family has some familiar members: * The limit when p\to -\infty is the ''leximin'' ordering; * For p=0 we get the Nash bargaining solution—maximizing the product of utilities; * For p=1 we get the utilitarian welfare function—maximizing the sum of utilities; * The limit when p\to \infty is the ''leximax'' ordering. If, in addition, we require: 6. the Pigou–Dalton principle, then the parameter ''p'', in the above family, must be at most 1.


See also

* Aggregation problem * Arrow's impossibility theorem * Community indifference curve * Distribution (economics) * Economic welfare * Extended sympathy * Gorman polar form * Justice (economics) * Liberal paradox * Production-possibility frontier * Social choice theory * Welfare economics


Notes


References

*Kenneth Arrow, Kenneth J. Arrow, 1951, 2nd ed., 1963, ''Social Choice and Individual Values'' *
Abram Bergson Abram Bergson (born Abram Burk, April 21, 1914 in Baltimore, Maryland – April 23, 2003 in Cambridge, Massachusetts) was an American economist, academician, and professor in the Harvard Economics Department since 1956. Early life and educatio ...
(Burk),"A Reformulation of Certain Aspects of Welfare Economics," ''Quarterly Journal of Economics'', 52(2), February 1938, 310–34
Bergson–Samuelson social welfare functions
in Paretian welfare economics from the New School. * James E. Foster and Amartya Sen, 1996, ''On Economic Inequality'', expanded edition with annexe, . * John C. Harsanyi, 1987, “interpersonal utility comparisons," ''The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics'', v. 2, 955–58 * ::Also available as
a journal article.
* Jan de Van Graaff, 1957, "Theoretical Welfare Economics", 1957, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. * Lionel Robbins, 1935, 2nd ed.. ''An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science'', ch. VI * ____, 1938, "Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility: A Comment," ''Economic Journal'', 43(4), 635–41 * Paul A. Samuelson, 1947, Enlarged ed. 1983, ''Foundations of Economic Analysis'', pp. xxi–xxiv & ch. VIII, "Welfare Economics," * _____, 1977. "Reaffirming the Existence of 'Reasonable' Bergson–Samuelson Social Welfare Functions," ''Economica'', N.S., 44(173),
pp. 81
€“88. Reprinted in (1986) ''The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A. Samuelson'', pp
47–54.
* _____, 1981. "Bergsonian Welfare Economics", in S. Rosefielde (ed.), ''Economic Welfare and the Economics of Soviet Socialism: Essays in Honor of Abram Bergson'', Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 223–66. Reprinted in (1986) ''The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A. Samuelson'', pp. 
–46.
* Amartya Sen, Sen, Amartya K. (1963). "Distribution, Transitivity and Little's Welfare Criteria," ''Economic Journal'', 73(292)
pp. 771
€“78. * _____, 1970 [1984], ''Collective Choice and Social Welfare'
(description)
ch. 3, "Collective Rationality." * _____ (1982). ''Choice, Welfare and Measurement'', MIT Press
Description
and scroll to chapter-previe
links.
* Kotaro Suzumura (1980). "On Distributional Value Judgments and Piecemeal Welfare Criteria," ''Economica'', 47(186),
pp. 125
€“39. * _____, 1987, “social welfare function," ''The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics'', v. 4, 418–20 {{Authority control Welfare economics Social choice theory Mathematical economics