HOME
The Info List - Platonism


--- Advertisement ---



Platonism, rendered as a proper noun, is the philosophy of Plato
Plato
or the name of other philosophical systems considered closely derived from it. In narrower usage, platonism, rendered as a common noun, refers to the philosophy that affirms the existence of abstract objects, which are asserted to "exist" in a "third realm" distinct both from the sensible external world and from the internal world of consciousness, and is the opposite of nominalism.[1] Lower case "platonists" need not accept any of the doctrines of Plato.[1] In a narrower sense, the term might indicate the doctrine of Platonic realism. The central concept of Platonism, a distinction essential to the Theory of Forms, is the distinction between the reality which is perceptible but unintelligible, and the reality which is imperceptible but intelligible. The forms are typically described in dialogues such as the Phaedo, Symposium and Republic as transcendent perfect archetypes of which objects in the everyday world are imperfect copies. In the Republic the highest form is identified as the Form of the Good, the source of all other forms, which could be known by reason. In the Sophist, a later work, the forms being, sameness and difference are listed among the primordial "Great Kinds". In the 3rd century BC, Arcesilaus
Arcesilaus
adopted skepticism, which became a central tenet of the school until 90 BC when Antiochus added Stoic elements, rejected skepticism, and began a period known as Middle Platonism. In the 3rd century AD, Plotinus
Plotinus
added mystical elements, establishing Neoplatonism, in which the summit of existence was the One or the Good, the source of all things; in virtue and meditation the soul had the power to elevate itself to attain union with the One. Platonism had a profound effect on Western thought, and many Platonic notions were adopted by the Christian church which understood Plato's forms as God's thoughts, while Neoplatonism
Neoplatonism
became a major influence on Christian mysticism, in the West through St Augustine, Doctor of the Catholic Church whose Christian writings were heavily influenced by Plotinus' Enneads,[2] and in turn were foundations for the whole of Western Christian thought.[3]

Contents

1 Philosophy 2 History

2.1 The Academy 2.2 Middle Platonism 2.3 Neoplatonism 2.4 Christianity
Christianity
and Platonism

3 Modern Platonism 4 See also 5 References 6 Further reading 7 External links

Philosophy[edit] The primary concept is the Theory of Forms. The only true being is founded upon the forms, the eternal, unchangeable, perfect types, of which particular objects of moral and responsible sense are imperfect copies. The multitude of objects of sense, being involved in perpetual change, are thereby deprived of all genuine existence.[4] The number of the forms is defined by the number of universal concepts which can be derived from the particular objects of sense.[4] The following excerpt may be representative of Plato's middle period metaphysics and epistemology:

[Socrates:] "Since the beautiful is opposite of the ugly, they are two." [Glaucon:] "Of course." "And since they are two, each is one?" "I grant that also." "And the same account is true of the just and unjust, the good and the bad, and all the forms. Each of them is itself one, but because they manifest themselves everywhere in association with actions, bodies, and one another, each of them appears to be many." "That's right." "So, I draw this distinction: On one side are those you just now called lovers of sights, lovers of crafts, and practical people; on the other side are those we are now arguing about and whom one would alone call philosophers." "How do you mean?" "The lovers of sights and sounds like beautiful sounds, colors, shapes, and everything fashioned out of them, but their thought is unable to see and embrace the nature of the beautiful itself." "That's for sure." "In fact, there are very few people who would be able to reach the beautiful itself and see it by itself. Isn't that so?" "Certainly." "What about someone who believes in beautiful things, but doesn't believe in the beautiful itself and isn't able to follow anyone who could lead him to the knowledge of it? Don't you think he is living in a dream rather than a wakened state? Isn't this dreaming: whether asleep or awake, to think that a likeness is not a likeness but rather the thing itself that it is like?" "I certainly think that someone who does that is dreaming." "But someone who, to take the opposite case, believes in the beautiful itself, can see both it and the things that participate in it and doesn't believe that the participants are it or that it itself is the participants--is he living in a dream or is he awake? "He's very much awake." (Republic Bk. V, 475e-476d, translation G.M.A Grube) Book VI of the Republic identifies the highest form as the Form of the Good, the cause of all other Ideas, and that on which the being and knowing of all other Forms is contingent. Conceptions derived from the impressions of sense can never give us the knowledge of true being; i.e. of the forms.[4] It can only be obtained by the soul's activity within itself, apart from the troubles and disturbances of sense; that is to say, by the exercise of reason.[4] Dialectic, as the instrument in this process, leading us to knowledge of the forms, and finally to the highest form of the Good, is the first of sciences.[4] Later Neoplatonism, beginning with Plotinus, identified the Good of the Republic with the so-called transcendent, absolute One of the first hypothesis of the Parmenides
Parmenides
(137c-142a). Platonist ethics is based on the Form of the Good. Virtue
Virtue
is knowledge, the recognition of the supreme form of the good.[4] And, since in this cognition, the three parts of the soul, which are reason, spirit, and appetite, all have their share, we get the three virtues, Wisdom, Courage, and Moderation.[4] The bond which unites the other virtues is the virtue of Justice, by which each part of the soul is confined to the performance of its proper function.[4] Platonism
Platonism
had a profound effect on Western thought. In many interpretations of the Timaeus Platonism,[5] like Aristotelianism, poses an eternal universe, as opposed to the nearby Judaic
Judaic
tradition that the universe had been created in historical time, with its continuous history recorded. Unlike Aristotelianism, Platonism describes idea as prior to matter and identifies the person with the soul. Many Platonic notions secured a permanent place in Christianity.[6] History[edit] The Academy[edit] Main article: Platonic Academy

Site of Plato's Academy in Athens

Platonism
Platonism
was originally expressed in the dialogues of Plato, in which the figure of Socrates
Socrates
is used to expound certain doctrines, that may or may not be similar to the thought of the historical Socrates, Plato's master. Plato
Plato
delivered his lectures at the Academy, a precinct containing a sacred grove outside the walls of Athens. The school continued there long after Plato's death. There were three periods: the Old, Middle, and New Academy. The chief figures in the Old Academy were Speusippus
Speusippus
(Plato's nephew), who succeeded him as the head of the school (until 339 BC), and Xenocrates
Xenocrates
(until 313 BC). Both of them sought to fuse Pythagorean speculations on number with Plato's theory of forms. Around 266 BC, Arcesilaus
Arcesilaus
became head of the Academy. This phase, known as the Middle Academy, strongly emphasized Academic skepticism. It was characterized by its attacks on the Stoics
Stoics
and their assertion of the certainty of truth and our knowledge of it. The New Academy began with Carneades
Carneades
in 155 BC, the fourth head in succession from Arcesilaus. It was still largely skeptical, denying the possibility of knowing an absolute truth; both Arcesilaus
Arcesilaus
and Carneades
Carneades
believed that they were maintaining a genuine tenet of Plato. Middle Platonism[edit] Main article: Middle Platonism Around 90 BC, Antiochus of Ascalon rejected skepticism, making way for the period known as Middle Platonism, in which Platonism
Platonism
was fused with certain Peripatetic and many Stoic dogmas. In Middle Platonism, the Platonic Forms were not transcendent but immanent to rational minds, and the physical world was a living, ensouled being, the World-Soul. Pre-eminence in this period belongs to Plutarch. The eclectic nature of Platonism
Platonism
during this time is shown by its incorporation into Pythagoreanism
Pythagoreanism
(Numenius of Apamea) and into Jewish philosophy (Philo of Alexandria). Neoplatonism[edit] Main article: Neoplatonism In the third century, Plotinus
Plotinus
recast Plato's system, establishing Neoplatonism, in which Middle Platonism
Middle Platonism
was fused with mysticism. At the summit of existence stands the One or the Good, as the source of all things.[7] It generates from itself, as if from the reflection of its own being, reason, the nous, - wherein is contained the infinite store of ideas.[7] The world-soul, the copy of the nous, is generated by and contained in it, as the nous is in the One, and, by informing matter in itself nonexistent, constitutes bodies whose existence is contained in the world-soul.[7] Nature therefore is a whole, endowed with life and soul. Soul, being chained to matter, longs to escape from the bondage of the body and return to its original source.[7] In virtue and philosophical thought it has the power to elevate itself above the reason into a state of ecstasy, where it can behold, or ascend to, that one good primary Being whom reason cannot know.[7] To attain this union with the Good, or God, is the true function of human beings.[7] Plotinus' disciple, Porphyry, followed by Iamblichus, developed the system in conscious opposition to Christianity. The Platonic Academy was re-established during this period; its most renowned head was Proclus (died 485), a celebrated commentator on Plato's writings. The Academy persisted until Roman emperor Justinian
Justinian
closed it in 529. Christianity
Christianity
and Platonism[edit]

Many Western churchmen, including Augustine
Augustine
of Hippo, have been influenced by Platonism.

Main article: Neoplatonism
Neoplatonism
and Christianity Platonism
Platonism
has had some influence on Christianity
Christianity
through Clement of Alexandria and Origen,[6] and the Cappadocian Fathers.[8] St. Augustine
Augustine
was heavily influenced by Platonism
Platonism
as well, which he encountered through the Latin translations of Marius Victorinus of the works of Porphyry and/or Plotinus.[6] Platonism
Platonism
was considered authoritative in the Middle Ages.[6] Platonism
Platonism
also influenced both Eastern and Western mysticism.[6][9] Meanwhile, Platonism
Platonism
influenced various philosophers.[6] While Aristotle
Aristotle
became more influential than Plato
Plato
in the 13th century, St. Thomas Aquinas's philosophy was still in certain respects fundamentally Platonic.[6] With the Renaissance, scholars became more interested in Plato himself.[6] In 16th, 17th century, and 19th century England, Plato's ideas influenced many religious thinkers.[6] Orthodox Protestantism
Protestantism
in continental Europe, however, distrusts natural reason and has often been critical of Platonism.[6] An issue in the reception of Plato
Plato
in early modern Europe
Europe
was how to deal with the same-sex elements of his corpus. [10] Christoplatonism is a term used to refer to a dualism opined by Plato, which influenced some church, which holds spirit is good but matter is evil.[11] Though the Bible's teaching directly contradicts this philosophy and thus receives constant criticism from many teachers in the Christian Church today. According to the Methodist Church, Christoplatonism directly "contradicts the Biblical record of God calling everything He created good."[11] Modern Platonism[edit] Apart from historical Platonism
Platonism
originating from thinkers such as Plato
Plato
himself, Numenius, Plotinus, Augustine
Augustine
and Proclus, we also encounter the theory of abstract objects in the modern sense.

Platonism
Platonism
is the view that there exist such things as abstract objects — where an abstract object is an object that does not exist in space or time and which is therefore entirely non-physical and non-mental. Platonism
Platonism
in this sense is a contemporary view.[12]

This modern Platonism
Platonism
(sometimes rendered "platonism," with a lower-case p, to distinguish it from the ancient schools) has been endorsed in one way or another at one time or another by numerous philosophers (mostly Austrian Realists[13] and analytic philosophers taking a particular interest in the philosophy and foundations of logic and mathematics), including Bernard Bolzano, Gottlob Frege, Edmund Husserl, Bertrand Russell, Alonzo Church, Kurt Gödel, W. V. O. Quine, Hilary Putnam, George Bealer and Edward Zalta[citation needed]. Modern Platonism
Platonism
recognizes a range of objects, including numbers, sets, truth values, properties, types, propositions and meanings. In the recent Continental tradition, prominent philosophers interested in Platonism
Platonism
(in the sense of Platonic thought) include Leo Strauss, Simone Weil
Simone Weil
and Alain Badiou. See also[edit]

Harold F. Cherniss, scholar of Plato's relation to Aristotle List of ancient Platonists Plato's unwritten doctrines, debates over Plato's esotericism Platonism
Platonism
in the Renaissance

References[edit]

^ a b " Philosophers who affirm the existence of abstract objects are sometimes called platonists; those who deny their existence are sometimes called nominalists. This terminology is lamentable, since these words have established senses in the history of philosophy, where they denote positions that have little to do with the modern notion of an abstract object. However, the contemporary senses of these terms are now established, and so the reader should be aware of them. In this connection, it is essential to bear in mind that modern platonists (with a small 'p') need not accept any of the doctrines of Plato, just as modern nominalists need not accept the doctrines of the medieval Nominalists." - "Abstract Objects", Gideon Rosen, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Philosophy
(Spring 2012 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), [1] ^ O'Connell SJ, RJ, The Enneads
Enneads
and St Augustine's Vision of Happiness. Vigiliae Christianae 17 (1963) 129-164 (JSTOR) ^ Pelikan, Jaroslav. The Christian Tradition: A History
History
of the Development of Doctrine. Vol 1, The Emergence of the Catholic Tradition 100-600; Pelikan, Jaroslav. The Christian Tradition: A History
History
of the Development of Doctrine. Vol 3, The Growth of Mediaeval Theology 600-1300, section, "The Augustinian Synthesis" ^ a b c d e f g h Oskar Seyffert, (1894), Dictionary of Classical Antiquities, page 481 ^ cf. Proclus' commentary on the Timaeus; Cornford 1937 ^ a b c d e f g h i j "Platonism." Cross, F. L., ed. The Oxford dictionary of the Christian church. New York: Oxford University Press. 2005 ^ a b c d e f Oskar Seyffert, (1894), Dictionary of Classical Antiquities, page 484 ^ Armstrong, A. H., ed., The Cambridge History
History
of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy, Cambridge, 1970. ^ Louth, Andrew. The Origins of the Christian Mystical Tradition: From Plato
Plato
to Denys. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983. ^ Reeser, Todd W. 2016. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ^ a b Robin Russell (6 April 2009). "Heavenly minded: It's time to get our eschatology right, say scholars, authors". UM Portal. Archived from the original on 22 July 2011. Retrieved 10 March 2011. Greek philosophers—who believed that spirit is good but matter is evil—also influenced the church, says Randy Alcorn, author of Heaven (Tyndale, 2004). He coined the term "Christoplatonism" to describe that kind of dualism, which directly contradicts the biblical record of God
God
calling everything he created "good."  ^ Balaguer, Mark (25 March 2018). Zalta, Edward N., ed. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 25 March 2018 – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  ^ Gestalt Theory: Official Journal of the Society for Gestalt Theory and Its Applications (GTA), 22, Steinkopff, 2000, p. 94: "Attention has varied between Continental Phenomenology (late Husserl, Merleau-Ponty) and Austrian Realism (Brentano, Meinong, Benussi, early Husserl)".

Further reading[edit]

Ackermann, C. The Christian Element in Plato
Plato
and the Platonic philosophy. Translated by Asbury Samuel Ralph. Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1861. Cassirer, Ernst. The Platonic Renaissance
Renaissance
in England. Translated by James P. Pettegrove. Edinburgh: Nelson, 1953. Kristeller, Paul Oskar, " Renaissance
Renaissance
Platonism." In Renaissance Thought: the Classic, Scholastic, and Humanistic Strains. New York: Harper, 1961. Walker, Daniel Pickering. The Ancient Theology: Studies in Christian Platonism
Platonism
from the Fifteenth to the Eighteenth Century. London: Duckworth, 1972.

External links[edit]

Christian Platonism
Platonism
and Christian Neoplatonism Islamic Platonists and Neoplatonists

v t e

Ancient Greek schools of philosophy

Pre-Socratic

Schools

Atomism Eleatics Ionian

Ephesian Milesian

Pluralism Pythagoreanism Sophistic

Philosophers

Anaxagoras Anaximander Anaximenes Democritus Empedocles Heraclitus Leucippus Melissus Parmenides Protagoras Pythagoras Thales Zeno of Elea

Socratic

Schools

Cynicism Cyrenaics Eretrian school Megarian school Peripateticism Platonism

Philosophers

Antisthenes Aristippus Aristotle Diogenes
Diogenes
of Sinope Euclid of Megara Phaedo
Phaedo
of Elis Plato Socrates

Hellenistic

Schools

Epicureanism Neoplatonism Neopythagoreanism Pyrrhonism Stoicism

Philosophers

Apollonius of Tyana Augustine Epictetus Epicurus John Philoponus Lucretius Plotinus Proclus Pyrrho Sextus Empiricus Zeno of Citium

v t e

Plato

Life

Early life Platonism Platonic epistemology Platonic idealism Platonic realism Platonic love Neoplatonism
Neoplatonism
and Gnosticism Platonism
Platonism
in the Renaissance Demiurge Theory of Forms Transcendentals Form of the Good Third man argument Euthyphro
Euthyphro
dilemma Five regimes Philosopher king Unwritten doctrines Cultural influence of Plato's Republic

Works

Uncontested

Apology Charmides Cratylus Critias Crito Euthydemus Euthyphro Gorgias Hippias Minor Ion Laches

Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 228

Laws

Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 23

Lysis Menexenus Meno Parmenides Phaedo

Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 229

Phaedrus Philebus Protagoras Republic Sophist Statesman Symposium Theaetetus Timaeus

Of doubtful authenticity

Axiochus Clitophon Definitions Demodocus Epigrams Epinomis Epistles

Letter I Letter II Letter IV Letter V Letter VI Letter VII Letter IX Letter X Letter XI Letter XII

Eryxias First Alcibiades Halcyon Hipparchus Hippias Major Minos On Justice On Virtue Rival Lovers Second Alcibiades Sisyphus Theages

Allegories and metaphors

Atlantis Ring of Gyges The Cave The Divided Line The Sun Ship of State Myth of Er The Chariot Allegorical interpretations of Plato

Related

Commentaries The Academy in Athens Socratic problem Middle Platonism Neoplatonism

and Christianity

Poitier Meets Plato List of speakers in Plato's dialogues

Plato's Dream

Family

Ariston of Athens
Ariston of Athens
(father) Pyrilampes
Pyrilampes
(stepfather) Perictione
Perictione
(mother) Adeimantus of Collytus
Adeimantus of Collytus
(brother) Glaucon
Glaucon
(brother) Potone
Potone
(sister) Speusippus
Speusippus
(nephew)

v t e

Logic

Outline History

Fields

Argumentation theory Axiology Critical thinking Logic
Logic
in computer science Mathematical logic Metalogic Metamathematics Non-classical logic Philosophical logic Philosophy
Philosophy
of logic Set theory

Foundations

Abduction Analytic and synthetic propositions Antinomy A priori and a posteriori Deduction Definition Description Induction Inference Logical form Logical consequence Logical truth Name Necessity and sufficiency Meaning Paradox Possible world Presupposition Probability Reason Reference Semantics Statement Strict implication Substitution Syntax Truth Validity

Lists

topics

Mathematical logic Boolean algebra Set theory

other

Logicians Rules of inference Paradoxes Fallacies Logic
Logic
symbols

Portal Category WikiProject (talk) changes

v t e

Aristotelianism

Overview

Peripatetic school Physics Biology Ethics Logic Theology (unmoved mover)

Ideas and interests

Correspondence theory of truth Hexis Virtue
Virtue
ethics (golden mean) Four causes Telos Phronesis Eudaimonia Arete Temporal finitism Antiperistasis Philosophy
Philosophy
of nature (sublunary sphere) Potentiality and actuality Universals (substantial form) Hylomorphism Mimesis Catharsis Substance (hypokeimenon, ousia, transcendentals) Essence–accident Category of being Minima naturalia Magnanimity Sensus communis Rational animal Genus–differentia Mythos

Corpus Aristotelicum

Physics Organon Nicomachean Ethics Politics Metaphysics On the Soul Rhetoric Poetics

Followers

Alexander the Great Theophrastus Avicenna Averroes Maimonides Thomas Aquinas Mortimer Adler Alasdair MacIntyre Martha Nussbaum

Related topics

Platonism Commentaries on Aristotle Recovery of Aristotle Scholasticism Conimbricenses Pseudo-Aristotle Views on women Aristotle's wheel paradox Aristotle's razor

Philosophy
Philosophy
portal

Authority control

.