HOME
The Info List - Max Stirner


--- Advertisement ---



Johann Kaspar Schmidt (October 25, 1806 – June 26, 1856), better known as Max Stirner, was a German philosopher. He is often seen as one of the forerunners of nihilism, existentialism, psychoanalytic theory, postmodernism, and individualist anarchism.[3][4] Stirner's main work is The Ego and Its Own, also known as The Ego and His Own (Der Einzige und sein Eigentum in German, which translates literally as The Individual and His Property[5][6]). This work was first published in 1845 in Leipzig, and has since appeared in numerous editions and translations. His primary philosophical and political device (albeit minimalist) is described as the Union of Egoists.[citation needed]

Contents

1 Biography 2 Philosophy

2.1 Egoism 2.2 Anarchism

2.2.1 Union of egoists 2.2.2 Revolution

2.3 Hegel's possible influence

3 Works

3.1 The False Principle of our Education 3.2 Art and Religion 3.3 The Ego and Its Own 3.4 Stirner's Critics 3.5 The Philosophical Reactionaries: 'The Modern Sophists' by Kuno Fischer 3.6 History of Reaction

4 Critical reception 5 Comments by contemporaries 6 Influence

6.1 Marx and Engels 6.2 Stirner and post-structuralism 6.3 Possible influence on Nietzsche 6.4 Rudolf Steiner 6.5 Anarchism 6.6 Free love, homosexuals, and feminists

7 See also 8 Notes 9 References 10 Further reading 11 External links

11.1 General 11.2 Relationship with other philosophers 11.3 Texts

Biography[edit]

Max Stirner's birthplace in Bayreuth

Stirner was born in Bayreuth, Bavaria. What little is known of his life is mostly due to the Scottish-born German writer John Henry Mackay, who wrote a biography of Stirner ( Max Stirner
Max Stirner
– sein Leben und sein Werk), published in German in 1898 (enlarged 1910, 1914), and translated into English in 2005. Stirner was the only child of Albert Christian Heinrich Schmidt (1769–1807) and Sophia Elenora Reinlein (1778–1839). His father died of tuberculosis on April 19, 1807 at the age of 37.[7] In 1809 his mother remarried to Heinrich Ballerstedt, a pharmacist, and settled in West Prussian Kulm (now Chełmno, Poland). When Stirner turned 20, he attended the University of Berlin,[7] where he studied philology, philosophy, and theology. He attended the lectures of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, who was to become a source of inspiration for his thinking.[8] He attended Hegel's lectures on the history of philosophy, the philosophy of religion and the subjective spirit. Stirner then moved to the University of Erlangen, which he attended at the same time as Ludwig Feuerbach.[9] Stirner returned to Berlin and obtained a teaching certificate, but was unable to obtain a full-time teaching post from the Prussian government.[10] While in Berlin in 1841, Stirner participated in discussions with a group of young philosophers called "Die Freien" ("The Free"), and whom historians have subsequently categorized as the Young Hegelians. Some of the best known names in nineteenth century literature and philosophy were involved with this group, including Karl Marx, Friedrich Engels, Bruno Bauer, and Arnold Ruge. Contrary to popular belief, Feuerbach was not a member of Die Freien, although he was heavily involved in Young Hegelian discourse. While some of the Young Hegelians were eager subscribers to Hegel's dialectical method and attempted to apply dialectical approaches to Hegel's conclusions, the left-wing members of the group broke with Hegel. Feuerbach and Bauer led this charge. Frequently the debates would take place at Hippel's, a wine bar in Friedrichstraße, attended by, among others, Marx and Engels, who were both adherents of Feuerbach at the time. Stirner met with Engels many times, and Engels even recalled that they were "great friends",[11] but it is still unclear whether Marx and Stirner ever met. It does not appear that Stirner contributed much to the discussions, but he was a faithful member of the club and an attentive listener.[12] The most-often reproduced portrait of Stirner is a cartoon by Engels, drawn 40 years later from memory at biographer Mackay's request. It is highly likely that this and the group sketch of Die Freien
Die Freien
at Hippel's are the only firsthand images of Stirner. Stirner worked as a teacher in a school for young girls owned by Madame Gropius[13] when he wrote his major work, The Ego and Its Own, which in part is a polemic against Feuerbach and Bauer, but also against communists such as Wilhelm Weitling
Wilhelm Weitling
and the anarchist Pierre-Joseph Proudhon. He resigned from his teaching position in anticipation of controversy from this work's publication in October 1844. Stirner married twice. His first wife was Agnes Burtz (1815-1838), the daughter of his landlady, who he married on the 12th of December, 1837. She died from complications with pregnancy in 1838, soon after their marriage. In 1843 he married Marie Dähnhardt, an intellectual associated with Die Freien. They divorced in 1846. The Ego and Its Own was dedicated "to my sweetheart Marie Dähnhardt". Marie later converted to Catholicism and died in 1902 in London. After The Ego and Its Own, Stirner wrote Stirner's Critics and translated Adam Smith's The Wealth of Nations
The Wealth of Nations
and Jean-Baptiste Say's Traite d'Economie Politique into German, to little financial gain. He also wrote a compilation of texts titled History of Reaction in 1852. Stirner died in 1856 in Berlin from an infected insect bite; it is said that Bruno Bauer
Bruno Bauer
was the only Young Hegelian present at his funeral, held at the Friedhof II der Sophiengemeinde Berlin. Philosophy[edit] Main article: Philosophy of Max Stirner See also: Egotism and Egoist anarchism The philosophy of Stirner is credited as a major influence in the development of nihilism, existentialism, post-modernism, and individualist anarchism, postanarchism, and post-left anarchy. Stirner's main philosophical work was The Ego and Its Own, also known as The Ego and His Own (Der Einzige und sein Eigentum in German, which translates literally as The Unique One and His Property). Egoism[edit]

Part of a series on

Individualism

Topics and concepts

Autonomy Civil liberties Do it yourself Eremitism Free love Freethought Human rights Individual Individual rights Individual reclamation Individuation Laissez-faire Libertinism Liberty Methodological individualism Negative liberty Personal property Positive liberty Private property Self-actualization Self-ownership Self reliance Subjectivity

Thinkers

Antiphon Aristippus Aristotle Émile Armand Albert Camus Diogenes of Sinope Ralph Waldo Emerson Epicurus William Godwin Emma Goldman Friedrich Hayek Karl Hess Miguel Giménez Igualada Thomas Jefferson Laozi Albert Libertad John Locke Hipparchia of Maroneia H. L. Mencken John Stuart Mill Ludwig von Mises Michel de Montaigne Friedrich Nietzsche Renzo Novatore Robert Nozick Michel Onfray Georges Palante Horst Matthai Quelle Ayn Rand Murray Rothbard Han Ryner Marquis de Sade Arthur Schopenhauer Adam Smith Herbert Spencer Lysander Spooner Max Stirner Henry David Thoreau Benjamin Tucker James L. Walker Josiah Warren Oscar Wilde Zeno Yang Zhu

Philosophies

Anarchism Anarcho-capitalism Classical liberalism Egoist anarchism Ethical egoism Existentialism Hedonism Humanism Individualist
Individualist
anarchism Individualist
Individualist
feminism

Equity feminism Liberal feminism

Left-libertarianism Left-wing market anarchism Liberalism Libertarianism Libertarian socialism Minarchism Mutualism Objectivism Right libertarianism Social anarchism Voluntaryism

Principal concerns

Anti-individualism Authoritarianism Collectivism Conformity Dogmatism Group rights Herd mentality Indoctrination Mass society Mobbing Social engineering Statism Tyranny Tyranny
Tyranny
of the majority Theocracy Totalitarianism

v t e

Stirner argues that you and I are each something impossible to fully comprehend. All mere concepts of the self will always be inadequate to fully describe the nature of our experience. Stirner has been broadly understood as a proponent of both psychological egoism and ethical egoism, although the latter position can be disputed, as there is no claim in Stirner's writing, in which one 'ought to' pursue one's own interest, and further claiming any 'ought' could be seen as a new 'fixed idea'. However, he may be understood as a rational egoist in the sense that he considered it irrational not to act in one's self-interest. How this self-interest is defined, however, is necessarily subjective, allowing both selfish and altruistic normative claims to be included. Individual self-realization rests on each individual's desire to fulfill their egoism. The difference between an unwilling and a willing egoist, is that the former will be 'possessed' by an empty idea and believe that they are fulfilling a higher cause, but usually being unaware that they are only fulfilling their own desires to be happy or secure, and the latter, in contrast, will be a person that is able to freely choose its actions, fully aware that they are only fulfilling individual desires.

Sacred things exist only for the egoist who does not acknowledge himself, the involuntary egoist ... in short, for the egoist who would like not to be an egoist, and abases himself (combats his egoism), but at the same time abases himself only for the sake of "being exalted", and therefore of gratifying his egoism. Because he would like to cease to be an egoist, he looks about in heaven and earth for higher beings to serve and sacrifice himself to; but, however much he shakes and disciplines himself, in the end he does all for his own sake... [on] this account I call him the involuntary egoist. ...As you are each instant, you are your own creature in this very 'creature' you do not wish to lose yourself, the creator. You are yourself a higher being than you are, and surpass yourself ... just this, as an involuntary egoist, you fail to recognize; and therefore the 'higher essence' is to you – an alien essence. ... Alienness is a criterion of the "sacred". — Ibidem, Cambridge edition, pp. 37–38

The contrast is also expressed in terms of the difference between the voluntary egoist being the possessor of his concepts as opposed to being possessed. Only when one realizes that all sacred truths such as law, right, morality, religion etc., are nothing other than artificial concepts, and not to be obeyed, can one act freely. For Stirner, to be free is to be both one's own "creature" (in the sense of 'creation') and one's own "creator" (dislocating the traditional role assigned to the gods). To Stirner power is the method of egoism. It is the only justified method of gaining property. Anarchism[edit]

Egoist Anarchism

Stirner proposes that most commonly accepted social institutions – including the notion of State, property as a right, natural rights in general, and the very notion of society – were mere illusions, "spooks" or ghosts in the mind.[14] He advocated egoism and a form of amoralism, in which individuals would unite in 'unions of egoists' only when it was in their self-interest to do so. For him, property simply comes about through might: "Whoever knows how to take, to defend, the thing, to him belongs property." And, "What I have in my power, that is my own. So long as I assert myself as holder, I am the proprietor of the thing." He says, "I do not step shyly back from your property, but look upon it always as my property, in which I respect nothing. Pray do the like with what you call my property!"[15] Stirner considers the world and everything in it, including other persons, available to one's taking or use without moral constraint[16] – that rights do not exist in regard to objects and people at all. He sees no rationality in taking the interests of others into account unless doing so furthers one's self-interest, which he believes is the only legitimate reason for acting. He denies society as being an actual entity, calling society a "spook" and that "the individuals are its reality" (The Ego and Its Own). Union of egoists[edit] Main article: Union of egoists Stirner's idea of the "Union of Egoists", was first expounded in The Ego and Its Own. The Union is understood as a non-systematic association, which Stirner proposed in contradistinction to the state.[17] The Union is understood as a relation between egoists which is continually renewed by all parties' support through an act of will.[18] The Union requires that all parties participate out of a conscious egoism. If one party silently finds themselves to be suffering, but puts up and keeps the appearance, the union has degenerated into something else.[18] This union is not seen as an authority above a person's own will. Revolution[edit] Stirner criticizes conventional notions of revolution, arguing that social movements aimed at overturning the state are tacitly statist because they are implicitly aimed at the establishment of a new state thereafter. Hegel's possible influence[edit]

Caricature of Max Stirner
Max Stirner
taken from a sketch by Friedrich Engels (1820–1895) of the meetings of "Die Freien".

Scholar Lawrence Stepelevich argues that Hegel
Hegel
was a major influence on The Ego and Its Own. While the latter has an "un-Hegelian structure and tone" on the whole and is hostile to Hegel's conclusions about the self and the world, Stepelevich argues that Stirner's work is best understood as answering Hegel's question of the role of consciousness after it has contemplated "untrue knowledge" and become "absolute knowledge". Stirner, Stepelevich concludes, presents the consequences of the rediscovering one's self-consciousness after realizing self-determination.[19] Scholars such as Douglas Moggach and Widukind De Ridder have argued that Stirner was obviously a student of Hegel, like his contemporaries Ludwig Feuerbach
Ludwig Feuerbach
and Bruno Bauer, but this does not necessarily make him an 'Hegelian'. Contrary to the Young Hegelians, Stirner scorned all attempts at an immanent critique of Hegel
Hegel
and the Enlightenment, and renounced Bruno Bauer
Bruno Bauer
and Ludwig Feuerbach's emancipatory claims as well. Contrary to Hegel, who considered the given as an inadequate embodiment of rationality, Stirner leaves the given intact by considering it a mere object, not of transformation, but of enjoyment and consumption ("His Own").[20] Stirner does not go beyond Hegel according to Douglas Moggach, but in fact leaves the domain of philosophy in its entirety:

Stirner refused to conceptualize the human self, and rendered it devoid of any reference to rationality or universal standards. The self was moreover considered a field of action, a ‘never-being I’. The ‘I’ had no essence to realize and life itself was a process of self-dissolution. Far from accepting, like the humanist Hegelians, a construal of subjectivity endowed with a universal and ethical mission, Stirner’s notion of ‘the Unique’ ( Der Einzige ) distances itself from any conceptualization whatsoever: ‘There is no development of the concept of the Unique. No philosophical system can be built out of it, as it can out of Being, or Thinking, or the I. Rather, with it, all development of the concept ceases. The person who views it as a principle thinks that he can treat it philosophically or theoretically and necessarily wastes his breath arguing against it’. —  Douglas Moggach & Widukind De Ridder, "Hegelianism in Restoration Prussia,1841–1848: Freedom, Humanism
Humanism
and ‘Anti-Humanism’ in Young Hegelian Thought.", In: 'Hegel's Thought in Europe: Currents, Crosscurrents and Undercurrents', ed. Lisa Herzog (pp. 71–92). Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013, p. 75

Works[edit] The False Principle of our Education[edit] Main article: The False Principle of our Education In 1842 Das unwahre Prinzip unserer Erziehung (The False Principle of our Education) was published in Rheinische Zeitung, which was edited by Marx at the time.[21] Written as a reaction to Otto Friedrich Theodor Heinsius' treatise Humanism
Humanism
vs. Realism, Stirner explains that education in either the classical humanist method or the practical realist method still lacks true value. Education, therefore, is fulfilled in aiding the individual in becoming an individual. Art and Religion[edit] Kunst und Religion (Art and Religion) was also published in Rheinische Zeitung, June 14, 1842. It addresses Bruno Bauer
Bruno Bauer
and his publication against Hegel
Hegel
called Hegel's doctrine of religion and art judged from the standpoint of faith. Bauer had inverted Hegel's relation between Art and Religion, by claiming that Art was much more closely related to Philosophy than Religion, based on their shared determinacy and clarity, and a common ethical root. Stirner, however, went beyond both Hegel
Hegel
and Bauer's criticism, by asserting that Art rather created an object for Religion and could thus by no means be related to what Stirner considered – in opposition with Hegel
Hegel
and Bauer – to be ‘Philosophy’:

It [philosophy] neither stands opposed to an Object, as Religion, nor makes one, as Art, but rather places its pulverizing hand upon all the business of making Objects as well as the whole of objectivity itself,and so breathes the air of freedom . Reason, the spirit of Philosophy, concerns itself only with itself, and troubles itself over no Object. — Max Stirner, Kunst und Religion, p. 110.

Stirner deliberately left Philosophy out of the dialectical triad (Art-Religion-Philosophy), by claiming that Philosophy "doesn’t bother itself with objects" (Religion), nor does it "make an object" (Art). Philosophy, in Stirner's account, was in fact indifferent towards both Art and Religion. Stirner thus mocked and radicalised Bauer's criticism of religion.[20] The Ego and Its Own[edit] Main article: The Ego and Its Own Stirner's main work is Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum (in modern German spelling Der Einzige und sein Eigentum; engl. trans. The Ego and Its Own, literally The Unique and Its Property), which appeared in Leipzig
Leipzig
in October 1844, with as year of publication mentioned 1845. In The Ego And Its Own, Stirner launches a radical anti-authoritarian and individualist critique of contemporary Prussian society, and modern western society as such. He offers an approach to human existence in which he depicts himself as "the unique one," a "creative nothing," beyond the ability of language to fully express.

If I concern myself for myself, the unique one, then my concern rests on its transitory, mortal creator, who consumes himself, and I may say: All things are nothing to me. — Max Stirner, The Ego and Its Own, p. 324.

The book proclaims that all religions and ideologies rest on empty concepts. The same holds true for society's institutions that claim authority over the individual, be it the state, legislation, the church, or the systems of education such as Universities. Stirner's argument explores and extends the limits of criticism, aiming his critique especially at those of his contemporaries, particularly Ludwig Feuerbach
Ludwig Feuerbach
and Bruno Bauer, and at popular ideologies, including religion, liberalism, and humanism (which he regarded as analogous to religion with the abstract Man or humanity as the supreme being), nationalism, statism, capitalism, socialism, and communism.

In the time of spirits thoughts grew till they overtopped my head, whose offspring they yet were; they hovered about me and convulsed me like fever-phantasies – an awful power. The thoughts had become corporeal on their own account, were ghosts, e. g. God, Emperor, Pope, Fatherland, etc. If I destroy their corporeity, then I take them back into mine, and say: "I alone am corporeal." And now I take the world as what it is to me, as mine, as my property; I refer all to myself. — Max Stirner, The Ego and Its Own, p. 17.

Stirner's Critics[edit] Recensenten Stirners (Stirner's Critics) was published in September 1845 in Wigands Vierteljahrsschrift. It is a response, in which Stirner refers to himself in the third-person, to three critical reviews of The Ego and its Own by Moses Hess
Moses Hess
in Die letzten Philosophen (The Last Philosophers), by a certain "Szeliga" (alias of an adherent of Bruno Bauer) in an article in the journal Norddeutsche Blätter, and by Ludwig Feuerbach
Ludwig Feuerbach
anonymously in an article called Über 'Das Wesen des Christentums' in Beziehung auf Stirners 'Der Einzige und sein Eigentum' (On 'The Essence of Christianity' in Relation to Stirner's 'The Ego and its Own' ) in Wigands Vierteljahrsschrift. The Philosophical Reactionaries: 'The Modern Sophists' by Kuno Fischer[edit] Die Philosophischen Reactionäre (The Philosophical Reactionaries) was published in 1847 in Die Epigonen, a journal edited by Otto Wigand from Leipzig. At the time, Wigand had already published Der Einzige und sein Eigentum, and was about to finish the publication of Stirner’s translations of Adam Smith
Adam Smith
and Jean-Baptiste Say. As the subtitle indicates, Die Philosophischen Reactionäre was written in response to an article by Kuno Fischer (1824–1907) entitled Die Moderne Sophisten (1847). The article was signed ‘G. Edward’, and its authorship has been disputed ever since John Henry Mackay ‘cautiously’ attributed it to Stirner and included it in his collection of Stirner’s lesser writings. It was first translated into English in 2011, and the introductory note explains:

Mackay based his attribution of this text to Stirner on Kuno Fischer’s subsequent reply to it, in which the latter, ‘with such determination’, identified G. Edward as Max Stirner. The article was entitled ‘Ein Apologet der Sophistik und “ein Philosophischer Reactionäre” ’ and was published alongside ‘Die Philosophischen Reactionäre’. Moreover, it seems rather odd that Otto Wigand would have published ‘Edward’s’ piece back- to-back with an article that falsely attributed it to one of his personal associates at the time. And, indeed, as Mackay went on to argue, Stirner never refuted this attribution. This remains, however, a slim basis on which to firmly identify Stirner as the author. This circumstantial evidence has led some scholars to cast doubts over Stirner’s authorship, based on both the style and content of ‘Die Philosophischen Reactionäre’. One should, however, bear in mind that it was written almost three years after Der Einzige und sein Eigentum, at a time when Young Hegelianism had withered away. —  Max Stirner
Max Stirner
"The Philosophical Reactionaries: 'The Modern Sophists' by Kuno Fischer", Newman, Saul (ed.), Max Stirner
Max Stirner
(Critical Explorations in Contemporary Political Thought), Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, p. 90 (2011).

The majority of the text deals with Kuno Fischer’s definition of Sophism. With much wit, the self-contradictory nature of Fischer’s criticism of Sophism is exposed. Fischer had made a sharp distinction between Sophism and philosophy, while at the same time considering Sophism as the "mirror image of philosophy". The Sophists breathe "philosophical air" and were "dialectically inspired to a formal volubility". Stirner's answer is striking:

Have you philosophers really no clue that you have been beaten with your own weapons? Only one clue. What can your common sense reply when I dissolve dialectically what you have merely posited dialectically? You have showed me with what kind of ‘volubility’ one can turn everything to nothing and nothing to everything, black into white and white into black. What do you have against me, when I return to you your pure art? — Max Stirner, "The Philosophical Reactionaries: 'The Modern Sophists' by Kuno Fischer", Newman, Saul (ed.), Max Stirner
Max Stirner
(Critical Explorations in Contemporary Political Thought), Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, p. 99 (2011).

Looking back on 'Der Einzige und sein Eigentum', Stirner claims:

Stirner himself has described his book as, in part, a clumsy expression of what he wanted to say. It is the arduous work of the best years of his life, and yet he calls it, in part, ‘clumsy’. That is how hard he struggled with a language that was ruined by philosophers, abused by state- , religious- and other believers, and enabled a boundless confusion of ideas. — Max Stirner, "The Philosophical Reactionaries: 'The Modern Sophists' by Kuno Fischer", Newman, Saul (ed.), Max Stirner
Max Stirner
(Critical Explorations in Contemporary Political Thought), Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, p. 104 (2011).

History of Reaction[edit] Geschichte der Reaktion (History of Reaction) was published in two volumes in 1851 by Allgemeine Deutsche Verlags-Anstalt and immediately banned in Austria.[7] It was written in the context of the recent 1848 revolutions in German states and is mainly a collection of the works of others selected and translated by Stirner. The introduction and some additional passages were Stirner's work. Edmund Burke
Edmund Burke
and Auguste Comte are quoted to show two opposing views of revolution. Critical reception[edit] Stirner's work did not go unnoticed among his contemporaries. Stirner's attacks on ideology – in particular Feuerbach's humanism – forced Feuerbach into print. Moses Hess
Moses Hess
(at that time close to Marx) and Szeliga (pseudonym of Franz Zychlin von Zychlinski, an adherent of Bruno Bauer) also replied to Stirner. Stirner answered the criticism in a German periodical, in the article Stirner's Critics (org. Recensenten Stirners, September 1845), which clarifies several points of interest to readers of the book – especially in relation to Feuerbach. While Marx's Sankt Max (large part of Die Deutsche Ideologie/ The German Ideology), not published until 1932, so assured The Ego and Its Own a place of curious interest among Marxist
Marxist
readers, Marx's ridicule of Stirner has played a significant role in the subsequent marginalization of Stirner's work, in popular and academic discourse. Comments by contemporaries[edit] Twenty years after the appearance of Stirner's book, the author Friedrich Albert Lange
Friedrich Albert Lange
wrote the following:

Stirner went so far in his notorious work, 'Der Einzige und Sein Eigenthum' (1845), as to reject all moral ideas. Everything that in any way, whether it be external force, belief, or mere idea, places itself above the individual and his caprice, Stirner rejects as a hateful limitation of himself. What a pity that to this book – the extremest that we know anywhere – a second positive part was not added. It would have been easier than in the case of Schelling's philosophy; for out of the unlimited Ego I can again beget every kind of Idealism
Idealism
as my will and my idea. Stirner lays so much stress upon the will, in fact, that it appears as the root force of human nature. It may remind us of Schopenhauer. — History of Materialism, ii. 256 (1865)

Some people believe that, in a sense, a "second positive part" was soon to be added, though not by Stirner, but by Friedrich Nietzsche. The relationship between Nietzsche and Stirner seems to be much more complicated.[22] According to George J. Stack's Lange and Nietzsche,[23] Nietzsche read Lange's History of Materialism "again and again" and was therefore very familiar with the passage regarding Stirner. Influence[edit] While Der Einzige was a critical success and attracted much reaction from famous philosophers after publication, it was out of print and the notoriety that it had provoked had faded many years before Stirner's death.[24] Stirner had a destructive impact on left-Hegelianism, but his philosophy was a significant influence on Marx and his magnum opus became a founding text of individualist anarchism.[24] Edmund Husserl
Edmund Husserl
once warned a small audience about the "seducing power" of Der Einzige, but never mentioned it in his writing.[25] As the art critic and Stirner admirer Herbert Read observed, the book has remained "stuck in the gizzard" of Western culture since it first appeared.[26] Many thinkers have read and been affected by The Ego and Its Own in their youth including Rudolf Steiner, Gustav Landauer, Victor Serge,[27] Carl Schmitt
Carl Schmitt
and Jürgen Habermas. Few openly admit any influence on their own thinking.[28] Ernst Jünger's book Eumeswil, had the character of the "Anarch", based on Stirner's "Einzige".[29] Several other authors, philosophers and artists have cited, quoted or otherwise referred to Max Stirner. They include Albert Camus
Albert Camus
in The Rebel (the section on Stirner is omitted from the majority of English editions including Penguin's), Benjamin Tucker, James Huneker,[30] Dora Marsden, Renzo Novatore, Emma Goldman,[31] Georg Brandes, John Cowper Powys,[32] Martin Buber,[33] Sidney Hook,[34] Robert Anton Wilson, Horst Matthai, Frank Brand, Marcel Duchamp, several writers of the Situationist International
Situationist International
including Raoul Vaneigem,[35] and Max Ernst. Years before rising to power, Benito Mussolini
Benito Mussolini
was inspired by Stirner, and made several references to him in his newspaper articles. The similarities in style between The Ego and Its Own and Oscar Wilde's The Soul of Man Under Socialism
Socialism
have caused some historians to speculate that Wilde (who could read German) was familiar with the book.[36] Since its appearance in 1844, The Ego and Its Own has seen periodic revivals of popular, political and academic interest, based around widely divergent translations and interpretations – some psychological, others political in their emphasis. Today, many ideas associated with post-left anarchy's criticism of ideology and uncompromising individualism are clearly related to Stirner's. He has also been regarded as pioneering individualist feminism, since his objection to any absolute concept also clearly counts gender roles as "spooks". His ideas were also adopted by post-anarchism, with Saul Newman largely in agreement with many of Stirner's criticisms of classical anarchism, including his rejection of revolution and essentialism. Marx and Engels[edit]

Caricature by Friedrich Engels
Friedrich Engels
(1820–1895) of the meetings of "Die Freien"

Engels commented on Stirner in poetry at the time of Die Freien:

Look at Stirner, look at him, the peaceful enemy of all constraint. For the moment, he is still drinking beer, Soon he will be drinking blood as though it were water. When others cry savagely "down with the kings" Stirner immediately supplements "down with the laws also." Stirner full of dignity proclaims; You bend your willpower and you dare to call yourselves free. You become accustomed to slavery Down with dogmatism, down with law.[37]

He once even recalled at how they were "great friends (Duzbrüder)".[11] In November 1844, Engels wrote a letter to Marx. He reported first on a visit to Moses Hess
Moses Hess
in Cologne
Cologne
and then went on to note that during this visit Hess had given him a press copy of a new book by Max Stirner, Der Einzige und Sein Eigenthum. In his letter to Marx, Engels promised to send a copy of Der Einzige to him, for it certainly deserved their attention, as Stirner: "had obviously, among the 'Free Ones', the most talent, independence and diligence".[11] To begin with Engels was enthusiastic about the book, and expressed his opinions freely in letters to Marx:

But what is true in his principle, we, too, must accept. And what is true is that before we can be active in any cause we must make it our own, egoistic cause-and that in this sense, quite aside from any material expectations, we are communists in virtue of our egoism, that out of egoism we want to be human beings and not merely individuals."[38]

Later, Marx and Engels wrote a major criticism of Stirner's work. The number of pages Marx and Engels devote to attacking Stirner in (the unexpurgated text of) The German Ideology, in which they derided him as "Sankt Max" (Saint Max), exceeds the total of Stirner's written works.[39] As Isaiah Berlin
Isaiah Berlin
has described it, Stirner "is pursued through five hundred pages of heavy-handed mockery and insult".[40] The book was written in 1845–1846, but not published until 1932. Marx's lengthy, ferocious polemic against Stirner has since been considered an important turning point in Marx's intellectual development from idealism to materialism. It has been argued that historical materialism was Marx's method of reconciling communism with a Stirnerite rejection of morality.[41] Stirner and post-structuralism[edit] See also: Post-anarchism The influential French poststructuralist thinker Jacques Derrida
Jacques Derrida
in his book Specters of Marx dealt with Stirner and his relationship with Marx while also analysing Stirner's concept of "specters" or "spooks".[42] Gilles Deleuze, another key thinker associated with post-structuralism mentions Stirner briefly in his book The Logic of Sense.[43] Saul Newman calls Stirner a proto-poststructuralist who on the one hand had essentially anticipated modern post-structuralists such as Foucault, Lacan, Deleuze, and Derrida, but on the other had already transcended them, thus providing what they were unable to: a ground for a non-essentialist critique of present liberal capitalist society. This is particularly evident in Stirner's identification of the self with a "creative nothing", a thing that cannot be bound by ideology (like leftist or marxists ideology of French post-structuralists), inaccessible to representation in language. Possible influence on Nietzsche[edit] Main article: Relationship between Friedrich Nietzsche
Friedrich Nietzsche
and Max Stirner The ideas of Max Stirner
Max Stirner
and Friedrich Nietzsche
Friedrich Nietzsche
have often been compared, and many authors have discussed apparent similarities in their writings, sometimes raising the question of influence.[44] In Germany, during the early years of Nietzsche's emergence as a well-known figure, the only thinker discussed in connection with his ideas more often than Stirner was Schopenhauer.[45] It is certain that Nietzsche read about The Ego and Its Own, which was mentioned in Lange's History of Materialism and Eduard von Hartmann's Philosophy of the Unconscious, both of which Nietzsche knew well.[46] However, there is no indication that he actually read it, as no mention of Stirner is known to exist anywhere in Nietzsche's publications, papers or correspondence.[47] In 2002, a biographical discovery revealed it is probable that Nietzsche had encountered Stirner's ideas before he read Hartmann and Lange, in October 1865, when he met with Eduard Mushacke, an old friend of Stirner's during the 1840s.[48] And yet as soon as Nietzsche's work began to reach a wider audience, the question of whether he owed a debt of influence to Stirner was raised. As early as 1891 (while Nietzsche was still alive, though incapacitated by mental illness), Eduard von Hartmann
Eduard von Hartmann
went so far as to suggest that he had plagiarized Stirner.[49] By the turn of the century, the belief that Nietzsche had been influenced by Stirner was so widespread that it became something of a commonplace, at least in Germany, prompting one observer to note in 1907 "Stirner's influence in modern Germany has assumed astonishing proportions, and moves in general parallel with that of Nietzsche. The two thinkers are regarded as exponents of essentially the same philosophy."[50] Nevertheless, from the beginning of what was characterized as "great debate"[51] regarding Stirner's possible positive influence on Nietzsche, serious problems with the idea were noted.[52] By the middle of the twentieth century, if Stirner was mentioned at all in works on Nietzsche, the idea of influence was often dismissed outright or abandoned as unanswerable.[53] But the idea that Nietzsche was influenced in some way by Stirner continues to attract a significant minority, perhaps because it seems necessary to explain the oft-noted (though arguably superficial) similarities in their writings.[54] In any case, the most significant problems with the theory of possible Stirner influence on Nietzsche are not limited to the difficulty in establishing whether the one man knew of or read the other. They also consist in establishing precisely how and why Stirner in particular might have been a meaningful influence on a man as widely read as Nietzsche.[55] Rudolf Steiner[edit] The individualist-anarchist orientation of Rudolf Steiner's early philosophy – before he turned to theosophy around 1900 – has strong parallels to, and was admittedly influenced by Stirner's conception of the ego, for which Steiner claimed to have provided a philosophical foundation.[56] Anarchism[edit]

Part of the Politics series on

Anarchism

Schools of thought

Black Capitalist Christian Collectivist Communist Egoist Existentialist Feminist Green Individualist Insurrectionary Leftist Left-wing market Magonist Mutualist Naturist Pacifist Philosophical Platformist Post-anarchist Post-colonial Post-left Primitivist Queer Social Syndicalist Synthesist Vegan Without adjectives

Theory Practice

Anarchy Anarchist
Anarchist
Black Cross Anationalism Anti-authoritarianism Anti-militarism Affinity group Black bloc Classless society Class struggle Communes Consensus democracy Conscientious objector Counter-economics Decentralization Deep ecology Direct action Direct democracy Dual power Especifismo Expropriative anarchism Free association Free love Free school Freethought Horizontalidad Illegalism Individualism Individual reclamation Isocracy Law Mutual aid Participatory politics Permanent autonomous zone Prefigurative politics Proletarian internationalism Propaganda of the deed Refusal of work Revolution Rewilding Self-ownership Social center Social ecology Social insertion Somatherapy Spontaneous order Squatting Temporary Autonomous Zone Union of egoists

People

Émile Armand Mikhail Bakunin Alexander Berkman Alfredo M. Bonanno Murray Bookchin Noam Chomsky Buenaventura Durruti Sébastien Faure David D. Friedman Mahatma Gandhi William Godwin Emma Goldman Francesc Ferrer i Guàrdia Peter Kropotkin Gustav Landauer Ricardo Flores Magón Nestor Makhno Errico Malatesta Louise Michel Johann Most Rudolf Rocker Murray Rothbard Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Diego Abad de Santillán Lysander Spooner Max Stirner Henry David Thoreau Leo Tolstoy Benjamin Tucker Volin Colin Ward Josiah Warren John Zerzan

Issues

Anarcho-capitalism Crypto-anarchism Animal rights Capitalism Education Criticisms Islam Lifestylism Marxism Nationalism Orthodox Judaism Religion Love and sex Violence

History

Paris Commune Cantonal Revolution Hague Congress International Conference of Rome Trial of the Thirty Haymarket affair May Day Anarchist
Anarchist
Exclusion Act Congress of Amsterdam Tragic Week High Treason Incident Manifesto of the Sixteen Individualist anarchism
Individualist anarchism
in the United States 1919 United States bombings Biennio Rosso German Revolution
Revolution
of 1918–19 Bavarian Council Republic Kronstadt rebellion Third Russian Revolution Free Territory Amakasu Incident Escuela Moderna

Individualist anarchism
Individualist anarchism
in Europe (in France)

Spanish Revolution Barcelona May Days Red inverted triangle Labadie Collection May 1968 Provo LIP Kate Sharpley Library Australian Anarchist
Anarchist
Centenary Carnival Against Capital 1999 Seattle WTO protests Occupy movement

Culture

Films Anarchist
Anarchist
Bookfair Anarcho-punk Arts Culture jamming DIY culture Freeganism Hip hop Independent Media Center Infoshop The Internationale Jewish anarchism "Land and liberty" Lifestylism "No gods, no masters" Popular education "Property is theft!" Radical cheerleading Radical environmentalism Red and Anarchist
Anarchist
Skinheads Squatting Symbolism Glossary A las Barricadas

Economics

Communization Co-operatives Cost the limit of price Economic democracy Economic secession Gift economy Give-away shop Market abolitionism Mass strike Mutual aid Participatory economics Really Really Free Market Socialization Wage slavery Workers' self-management

By region

Africa Argentina Australia Azerbaijan Bolivia Brazil Canada China Cuba Ecuador Egypt France French Guiana Germany Greece India Iceland Ireland Israel Italy Japan Korea Mexico Monaco New Zealand Poland Puerto Rico Romania Russia Singapore South Africa Spain Sweden Transnistria Turkey Ukraine United Kingdom United States Venezuela Vietnam

Lists

Anarcho-punk
Anarcho-punk
bands Communities Fictional characters Jewish anarchists Love & sex Musicians Organizations Periodicals Poets Russian anarchists Films

Related topics

Anti-capitalism Anti-corporatism Anti-consumerism Anti-fascism Anti-globalization Anti-statism Anti-war Autarchism Autonomism Communism Labour movement Left communism Libertarianism Libertarian socialism Libertarian marxism Marxism Situationist International Socialism Spontaneous order

Anarchism
Anarchism
portal Politics portal

v t e

Main articles: Egoist anarchism
Egoist anarchism
and Individualist
Individualist
anarchism Stirner's philosophy was important in the development of modern anarchist thought, particularly individualist anarchism and egoist anarchism. Although Stirner is usually associated with individualist anarchism, he was influential to many social anarchists such as anarcha-feminists Emma Goldman
Emma Goldman
and Federica Montseny. In european individualist anarchism he influenced its main proponents after him such as Emile Armand, Han Ryner, Renzo Novatore, John Henry Mackay, Miguel Giménez Igualada, and Lev Chernyi. In American individualist anarchism
American individualist anarchism
he found adherence in Benjamin Tucker and his magazine Liberty
Liberty
while these abandoned natural rights positions for egoism.[57] "Several periodicals were undoubtedly influenced by Liberty's presentation of egoism. They included: I published by C.L. Swartz, edited by W.E. Gordak and J.W. Lloyd (all associates of Liberty); The Ego and The Egoist, both of which were edited by Edward H. Fulton. Among the egoist papers that Tucker followed were the German Der Eigene, edited by Adolf Brand, and The Eagle and The Serpent, issued from London. The latter, the most prominent English-language egoist journal, was published from 1898 to 1900 with the subtitle "A Journal of Egoistic Philosophy and Sociology".[57] Other American egoist anarchists around the early twentieth century include James L. Walker, George Schumm, John Beverley Robinson, Steven T. Byington, and E.H. Fulton.[57] In the United Kingdom Herbert Read
Herbert Read
was influenced by Stirner, and noted the closeness of Stirner's egoism to existentialism (see existentialist anarchism). Later in the 1960s Daniel Guérin in Anarchism: From Theory to Practice says that Stirner "rehabilitated the individual at a time when the philosophical field was dominated by Hegelian anti-individualism and most reformers in the social field had been led by the misdeeds of bourgeois egotism to stress its opposite" and pointed to "the boldness and scope of his thought."[58] In the seventies an American situationist collective called For Ourselves published a book called The Right To Be Greedy: Theses On The Practical Necessity Of Demanding Everything in which they advocate a "communist egoism" basing themselves on Stirner.[59] Later in the USA emerged the tendency of post-left anarchy which was influenced profoundly by Stirner in aspects such as the critique of ideology. Jason McQuinn
Jason McQuinn
says that "when I (and other anti-ideological anarchists) criticize ideology, it is always from a specifically critical, anarchist perspective rooted in both the skeptical, individualist-anarchist philosophy of Max Stirner.[60] Also Bob Black and Feral Faun/Wolfi Landstreicher strongly adhere to Stirnerist egoism. In the hybrid of post-structuralism and Anarchism
Anarchism
called post-anarchism Saul Newman has written on Stirner and his similarities to post-structuralism. Insurrectionary anarchism
Insurrectionary anarchism
also has an important relationship with Stirner as can be seen in the work of Wolfi Landstreicher and Alfredo Bonanno
Alfredo Bonanno
who has also written on him in works such as Max Stirner
Max Stirner
and " Max Stirner
Max Stirner
und der Anarchismus".[61] Free love, homosexuals, and feminists[edit] The German stirnerist Adolf Brand
Adolf Brand
produced the homosexual periodical Der Eigene
Der Eigene
in 1896. This was the first ongoing homosexual publication in the world,[62] and ran until 1931. The name was taken from the writings of Stirner, who had greatly influenced the young Brand, and refers to Stirner's concept of "self-ownership" of the individual. Another early homosexual activist influenced by Stirner was John Henry Mackay. Feminists influenced by Stirner include Dora Marsden
Dora Marsden
who edited the journals The Freewoman and The New Freewoman and Anarchist Emma Goldman. Stirner also influenced free love and polyamory propagandist Émile Armand
Émile Armand
in the context of French individualist anarchism of the early twentieth century which is known for "The call of nudist naturism, the strong defense of birth control methods, the idea of "unions of egoists" with the sole justification of sexual practices".[63] See also[edit]

Individualist anarchism
Individualist anarchism
in Europe Philosophy of Max Stirner Relationship between Friedrich Nietzsche
Friedrich Nietzsche
and Max Stirner

Notes[edit]

^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, volume 8, The Macmillan Company and The Free Press, New York 1967. ^ Bernd A. Laska, Otto Gross
Otto Gross
zwischen Max Stirner
Max Stirner
und Wilhelm Reich, In: Raimund Dehmlow and Gottfried Heuer, eds.: 3. Internationaler Otto-Gross-Kongress, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität, München. Marburg, 2003, pp. 125–62, ISBN 3-936134-06-5 LiteraturWissenschaft.de. ^ Leopold, David (2006-08-04). "Max Stirner". In Zalta, Edward N. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  ^ Goodway, David. Anarchist
Anarchist
Seeds Beneath the Snow. Liverpool University Press, 2006, p. 99. ^ A Ready Reference to Philosophy East and West ^ Anarchism: A Criticjsm and History of the Anarchist
Anarchist
Theory ^ a b c John Henry Mackay: Max Stirner
Max Stirner
– Sein Leben und sein Werk p. 28 ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, volume 8, The Macmillan Company and The Free Press, New York 1967. ^ Stepelevich 1985, p. 602. ^ Marshall, Peter (1992). Demanding the Impossible. Harper Collins. p. 221. ISBN 0002178559.  ^ a b c Lawrence L Stepelevich, The revival of Max Stirner ^ Gide, Charles & Rist, Charles. A History of Economic Doctrines from the Time of the Physiocrats to the Present Day. Harrap 1956, p. 612 ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, volume 8, The Macmillan Company and The Free Press, New York 1967 ^ Heider, Ulrike. Anarchism: Left, Right and Green, San Francisco: City Lights Books, 1994, pp. 95–96 ^ Stirner, Max. The Ego and Its Own, p. 248 ^ Moggach, Douglas. The New Hegelians. Cambridge University Press, 2006 p. 194 ^ Thomas, Paul (1985). Karl Marx
Karl Marx
and the Anarchists. London: Routledge/Kegan Paul. p. 142. ISBN 0-7102-0685-2.  ^ a b Nyberg, Svein Olav. "The union of egoists" (PDF). Non Serviam. Oslo, Norway: Svein Olav Nyberg. 1: 13–14. OCLC 47758413. Archived from the original (PDF) on 7 December 2010. Retrieved 1 September 2012  ^ Stepelevich 1985. ^ a b Moggach, Douglas & De Ridder, Widukind. Hegelianism in Restoration Prussia,1841–1848: Freedom, Humanism
Humanism
and ‘Anti-Humanism’ in Young Hegelian Thought. In: 'Hegel's Thought in Europe: Currents, Crosscurrents and Undercurrents', ed. Lisa Herzog (pp. 71–92). Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013, pp. 82–83 ^ Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, The Macmillan company Press, New York, 1967 ^ See Bernd A. Laska: Nietzsche's initial crisis. In: Germanic Notes and Reviews, vol. 33, n. 2, fall/Herbst 2002, pp. 109–33 ^ George J. Stack, Lange and Nietzsche, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, New York, 1983, p. 12, ISBN 978-3-11-008866-3 ^ a b Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Max Stirner". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  ^ Max Stirner, a durable dissident – in a nutshell ^ Quoted in Read's book, "The Contrary Experience", Faber and Faber, 1963. ^ See Memoirs of a revolutionary, 1901–1941 by Victor Serge. Publisher Oxford U.P., 1967 ^ See Bernd A. Laska: Ein dauerhafter Dissident. Nürnberg: LSR-Verlag 1996 (online) ^ See Bernd A. Laska: Katechon und Anarch. Nürnberg: LSR-Verlag 1997 (online) ^ Huneker's book Egoists, a Book of Supermen (1909)contains an essay on Stirner. ^ See Goldman, Anarchism
Anarchism
and Other Essays, p. 50. ^ Wilson, A N (November 1, 2004). "World of books". The Daily Telegraph. London. Retrieved May 12, 2010.  ^ Between Man and Man by Martin Buber, Beacon Press, 1955. ^ From Hegel
Hegel
to Marx by Sidney Hook, London, 1936. ^ "The long revolution is preparing to write works in the ink of action whose unknown or nameless authors will flock to join Sade, Fourier, Babeuf, Marx, Lacenaire, Stirner, Lautréamont, L’hautier, Vaillant, Henry, Villa, Zapata, Makhno, the Communards, the insurrectionaries of Hamburg, Kiel, Kronstadt, Asturias – all those who have not yet played their last card in a game which we have only just joined: the great gamble whose stake is freedom." Raoul Vaneigem. The Revolution
Revolution
of Everyday Life ^ David Goodway, Anarchist
Anarchist
Seeds Beneath the Snow, Liverpool University Press, 2006. p. 75. ^ Henri Arvon, Aux sources de 1'existentialisme Max Stirner
Max Stirner
(Paris, 1954), p. 14 ^ Zwischen 18 and 25, pp. 237–38. ^ "Chapter Sankt Max in Die deutsche Ideologie ^ I. Berlin, Karl Marx
Karl Marx
(New York, 1963), 143. ^ G. Stedman-Jones, 'Introduction' in K. Marx & F. Engels, The Communist Manifesto (London, 2002) ^ Jacques Derrida. Specters of Marx. Routledge. 1994 ^ "Human or divine, as Stirner said, the predicates are the same whether they belong analytically to the divine being, or whether they are synthetically bound to the human form" (Gilles Deleuze. The Logic of Sense. Continuum. 2004). p. 122. ^ Albert Levy, Stirner and Nietzsche, Paris, 1904; Robert Schellwien, Max Stirner
Max Stirner
and Friedrich Nietzsche, 1892; H.L. Mencken, The Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche, 1908; K. Löwith, From Hegel
Hegel
To Nietzsche New York, 1964, p187; R.A. Nicholls, "Beginnings of the Nietzsche Vogue in Germany", in Modern Philology, Vol. 56, No. 1, Aug., 1958, pp. 24–37; T. A. Riley, "Anti- Statism in German Literature, as Exemplified by the Work of John Henry Mackay", in PMLA, Vol. 62, No. 3, Sep. 1947, pp. 828–43; Seth Taylor, Left Wing Nietzscheans, The Politics of German Expressionism 1910–1920, p144, 1990, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin/New York; Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche et la Philosophy, Presses Universitaires de France, 1962; R. C. Solomon & K. M. Higgins, The Age of German Idealism, p300, Routledge, 1993 ^ While discussion of possible influence has never ceased entirely, the period of most intense discussion occurred between 1892 and 1900 in the German-speaking world. During this time, the most comprehensive account of Nietzsche's reception in the German language, the 4 volume work of Richard Frank Krummel: Nietzsche und der deutsche Geist indicates 83 entries discussing Stirner and Nietzsche. The only thinker more frequently discussed in connection with Nietzsche during this time is Schopenhauer, with about twice the number of entries. Discussion steadily declines thereafter, but is still significant. Nietzsche and Stirner show 58 entries between 1901 and 1918. From 1919 to 1945 there are 28 entries regarding Nietzsche and Stirner. ^ "Apart from the information which can be gained from the annotations, the library (and the books Nietzsche read) shows us the extent, and the bias, of Nietzsche's knowledge of many fields, such as evolution and cosmology. Still more obvious, the library shows us the extent and the bias of Nietzsche's knowledge about many persons to whom he so often refers with ad hominem statements in his works. This includes not only such important figures as Mill, Kant, and Pascal but also such minor ones (for Nietzsche) as Max Stirner
Max Stirner
and William James who are both discussed in books Nietzsche read." T. H. Brobjer, "Nietzsche's Reading and Private Library", 1885–1889, in Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 58, No. 4, Oct., 1997, pp. 663–93; Stack believes it is doubtful that Nietzsche read Stirner, but notes "he was familiar with the summary of his theory he found in Lange's history." George J. Stack, Lange and Nietzsche, Walter de Gruyter, 1983, p. 276 ^ Albert Levy, Stirner and Nietzsche, Paris, 1904 ^ Bernd A. Laska: Nietzsche's initial crisis. In: Germanic Notes and Reviews, vol. 33, n. 2, fall/Herbst 2002, pp. 109–33 ^ Eduard von Hartmann, Nietzsches "neue Moral", in Preussische Jahrbücher, 67. Jg., Heft 5, Mai 1891, S. 501–521; augmented version with more express reproach of plagiarism in: Ethische Studien, Leipzig, Haacke 1898, pp. 34–69 ^ This author believes that one should be careful in comparing the two men. However, he notes: "It is this intensive nuance of individualism that appeared to point from Nietzsche to Max Stirner, the author of the remarkable work Der Einzige und sein Eigentum. Stirner's influence in modern Germany has assumed astonishing proportions, and moves in general parallel with that of Nietzsche. The two thinkers are regarded as exponents of essentially the same philosophy." O. Ewald, "German Philosophy in 1907", in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 17, No. 4, Jul., 1908, pp. 400–26 ^ [in the last years of the nineteenth century] "The question of whether Nietzsche had read Stirner was the subject of great debate" R.A. Nicholls, "Beginnings of the Nietzsche Vogue in Germany", in Modern Philology, Vol. 56, No. 1, Aug., 1958, pp. 29–30 ^ Levy pointed out in 1904 that the similarities in the writing of the two men appeared superficial. Albert Levy, Stirner and Nietzsche, Paris, 1904 ^ R.A. Nicholls, "Beginnings of the Nietzsche Vogue in Germany", in Modern Philology, Vol. 56, No. 1, Aug., 1958, pp. 24–37 ^ "Stirner, like Nietzsche, who was clearly influenced by him, has been interpreted in many different ways", Saul Newman, From Bakunin to Lacan: Anti-authoritarianism
Anti-authoritarianism
and the Dislocation of Power, Lexington Books, 2001, p. 56; "We do not even know for sure that Nietzsche had read Stirner. Yet, the similarities are too striking to be explained away." R. A. Samek, The Meta Phenomenon, p. 70, New York, 1981; Tom Goyens, (referring to Stirner's book The Ego and His Own) "The book influenced Friedrich Nietzsche, and even Marx and Engels devoted some attention to it." T. Goyens, Beer and Revolution: The German Anarchist Movement In New York City, p197, Illinois, 2007 ^ "We have every reason to suppose that Nietzsche had a profound knowledge of the Hegelian movement, from Hegel
Hegel
to Stirner himself. The philosophical learning of an author is not assessed by the number of quotations, nor by the always fanciful and conjectural check lists of libraries, but by the apologetic or polemical directions of his work itself." Gilles Deleuze
Gilles Deleuze
(translated by Hugh Tomlinson), Nietzsche and Philosophy, 1962 (2006 reprint, pp. 153–54) ^ Guido Giacomo Preparata, "Perishable Money in a Threefold Commonwealth: Rudolf Steiner
Rudolf Steiner
and the Social Economics of an Anarchist Utopia". Review of Radical Economics 38/4 (Fall 2006). pp. 619–48 ^ a b c "Only the influence of the German philosopher of egoism, Max Stirner (né Johann Kaspar Schmidt, 1806–1856), as expressed through The Ego and His Own (Der Einzige und sein Eigentum) compared with that of Proudhon. In adopting Stirnerite egoism (1886), Tucker rejected natural rights which had long been considered the foundation of libertarianism. This rejection galvanized the movement into fierce debates, with the natural rights proponents accusing the egoists of destroying libertarianism itself. So bitter was the conflict that a number of natural rights proponents withdrew from the pages of Liberty in protest even though they had hitherto been among its frequent contributors. Thereafter, Liberty
Liberty
championed egoism although its general content did not change significantly."Wendy Mcelroy. "Benjamin Tucker, Individualism, & Liberty: Not the Daughter but the Mother of Order" ^ Daniel Guérin,Anarchism: From Theory to Practice ^ Four Ourselves, The Right To Be Greedy: Theses On The Practical Necessity Of Demanding Everything Archived 2013-06-22 at the Wayback Machine. ^ "What is Ideology?" by Jason McQuinn ^ BONANNO, Alfredo Maria ^ Karl Heinrich Ulrichs
Karl Heinrich Ulrichs
had begun a journal called Prometheus in 1870, but only one issue was published. (Kennedy, Hubert, Karl Heinrich Ulrichs: First Theorist of Homosexuality, In: 'Science and Homosexualities', ed. Vernon Rosario. New York: Routledge, 1997, pp. 26–45.) ^ "La insumisión voluntaria. El anarquismo individualista español durante la dictadura y la Segunda República" by Xavier Díez

References[edit]

Stirner, Max: Der Einzige und sein Eigentum (1845 [October 1844]). Stuttgart: Reclam-Verlag, 1972ff; engl. trans. The Ego and Its Own (1907), ed. David Leopold, Cambridge/ New York: CUP 1995 Stirner, Max: "Recensenten Stirners" (September 1845). In: Parerga, Kritiken, Repliken, Bernd A. Laska, ed., Nürnberg: LSR-Verlag, 1986; engl. trans. Stirner's Critics (abridged), see below Max Stirner, Political Liberalism
Liberalism
(1845)

Further reading[edit]

Max Stirner's 'Der Einzige und sein Eigentum' im Spiegel der zeitgenössischen deutschen Kritik. Eine Textauswahl (1844–1856). Hg. Kurt W. Fleming. Leipzig: Verlag Max-Stirner-Archiv 2001 (Stirneriana) Arena, Leonardo V., Note ai margini del nulla, ebook, 2013. Arvon, Henri, Aux Sources de l'existentialisme, Paris: P.U.F. 1954 Essbach, Wolfgang, Gegenzüge. Der Materialismus des Selbst. Eine Studie über die Kontroverse zwischen Max Stirner
Max Stirner
und Karl Marx. Frankfurt: Materialis 1982 Helms, Hans G, Die Ideologie der anonymen Gesellschaft. Max Stirner 'Einziger' und der Fortschritt des demokratischen Selbstbewusstseins vom Vormärz bis zur Bundesrepublik, Köln: Du Mont Schauberg, 1966 Koch, Andrew M., "Max Stirner: The Last Hegelian or the First Poststructuralist". In: Anarchist
Anarchist
Studies, vol. 5 (1997) pp. 95–108 Laska, Bernd A., Ein dauerhafter Dissident. Eine Wirkungsgeschichte des Einzigen, Nürnberg: LSR-Verlag 1996 (TOC, index) Laska, Bernd A., Ein heimlicher Hit. Editionsgeschichte des "Einzigen". Nürnberg: LSR-Verlag 1994 (abstract) Marshall, Peter H. "Max Stirner" in "Demanding the Impossible: A History of Anarchism
Anarchism
"(London: HarperCollins, 1992). Moggach, Douglas & De Ridder, Widukind, "Hegelianism in Restoration Prussia,1841–1848: Freedom, Humanism
Humanism
and ‘Anti-Humanism’ in Young Hegelian Thought". In: Herzog, Lisa (ed.): Hegel's Thought in Europe: Currents, Crosscurrents and Undercurrents. Basingstoke and New York, Palgrave Macmillan, 2013, pp. 71–92 (Google Books) Newman, Saul (ed.), Max Stirner
Max Stirner
(Critical Explorations in Contemporary Political Thought), Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011 (full book) Newman, Saul, Power and Politics in Poststructural Thought. London and New York: Routledge
Routledge
2005 Paterson, R.W.K., The Nihilistic Egoist: Max Stirner, Oxford: Oxford University Press 1971 Spiessens, Jeff. The Radicalism of Departure. A Reassessment of Max Stirner’s Hegelianism, Cambridge Scholars Publishing: Newcastle Upon Tyne, 2018. Stepelevich, Lawrence S. (1985). " Max Stirner
Max Stirner
as Hegelian". Journal of the History of Ideas. 46 (4): 597–614. doi:10.2307/2709548. ISSN 0022-5037. JSTOR 2709548.  Stepelevich, Lawrence S., Ein Menschenleben. Hegel
Hegel
and Stirner". In: Moggach, Douglas (ed.): The New Hegelians. Philosophy and Politics in the Hegelian School. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2006, pp. 166–76 Welsh, John F. Max Stirner's Dialectical
Dialectical
Egoism: A New Interpretation. Lexington Books. 2010. Wilkinson, Will (2008). "Stirner, Max (1806–1856)". In Hamowy, Ronald. The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE; Cato Institute. pp. 493–94. doi:10.4135/9781412965811.n300. ISBN 978-1-4129-6580-4. LCCN 2008009151. OCLC 750831024.  Di Mascio, Carlo, Stirner Giuspositivista. Rileggendo l'Unico e la sua proprietà, 2 ed., Edizioni Del Faro, Trento, 2015, p. 253, ISBN 978-88-6537-378-1

External links[edit]

Works written by or about Max Stirner
Max Stirner
at Wikisource Quotations related to Max Stirner
Max Stirner
at Wikiquote Media related to Max Stirner
Max Stirner
at Wikimedia Commons

General[edit]

Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Max Stirner". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. , an extensive introduction Svein Olav Nybergs website on Max Stirner, with extensive links to texts and references Max Stirner
Max Stirner
within the LSR project (English section) Max Stirner
Max Stirner
Project by H. Ibrahim Türkdogan Archive of texts on Stirner at the Anarchist
Anarchist
Library Max Stirner
Max Stirner
at Goodreads

Relationship with other philosophers[edit]

Max Stirner, a durable dissident, 'How Marx and Nietzsche suppressed their colleague Max Stirner
Max Stirner
and why he has intellectually survived them' Stirner Delighted in His Construction – "loves miracles, but can only perform a logical miracle", by Karl Marx Nietzsche's initial crisis due to an encounter with Stirner's "The Ego", by Bernd A. Laska (2002) "At the End of the Path of Doubt: Max Stirner", By Lawrence S. Stepelevich (Owl of Minerva 41:1–2 (2009–10) pp. 85–106)

Texts[edit]

Works by Max Stirner
Max Stirner
at Project Gutenberg Works by or about Max Stirner
Max Stirner
at Internet Archive Works by Max Stirner
Max Stirner
at LibriVox
LibriVox
(public domain audiobooks) Online book Der Einzige und sein Eigentum The complete original text in German of Der Einzige und sein Eigentum The complete English edition of "The Ego and his Own", in the translation of Steven T. Byington. Some of Stirner's illuminating "Shorter Essays", translated into English Recensenten Stirners / Stirner's Critics bilingual: full text in German / abridged text in English (trans. Frederick M. Gordon) Stirner's Critics by Max Stirner
Max Stirner
translated by Wolfi Landstreicher, with an introduction by Jason McQuinn
Jason McQuinn
(2013 revision of the only full-text English translation of both “Stirner’s Critics” and “The Philosophical Reactionaries” by Wolfi Landstreicher published by CAL Press) Archive of the 4 works of Stirner translated into English including a 2011 complete translation of Stirner´s Critics (translated by Wolfi Landstreicher at the Anarchist
Anarchist
Library)

v t e

Max Stirner

Works

The False Principle of our Education The Ego and Its Own (publication history)

Philosophy

Stirner's philosophy Relationship with Friedrich Nietzsche Union of egoists Young Hegelians

Influence

Egoist anarchism Existentialist anarchism Individualist
Individualist
anarchism Insurrectionary anarchism Post-anarchism Post-left anarchy Psychological egoism

v t e

Criticism of religion

By religion

Bahá'í Faith Buddhism Christianity

Catholic

Opus Dei

Jehovah's Witnesses Latter Day Saint movement Protestantism Seventh-day Adventist Unification Church Westboro Baptist Church

Hinduism Islam

Islamism Twelver Shia Islam Wahhabism

Jainism Judaism Monotheism New religious movement Scientology Sikhism Yazdânism Zoroastrianism

Religious texts

Bible Quran Hadiths Mormon sacred texts

Book of Mormon

Talmud

Religious figures

Aisha Charles Taze Russell Ellen White Jesus Moses Muhammad Mirza Ghulam Ahmad Saul

Religious violence

Buddhism Christianity

Mormonism

Judaism Islam Terrorism

Christian Hindu Islamic Jewish

Persecution

Christian thought on persecution and tolerance

War

In Islam In Judaism

Sectarian violence By country

India

Anti-Christian violence In Odisha

Nigeria Pakistan

Books

Atheist Manifesto Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon Christianity Unveiled God
God
in the Age of Science? God
God
Is Not Great God: The Failed Hypothesis Letter to a Christian Nation The Age of Reason The Blind Watchmaker The Caged Virgin The End of Faith The God
God
Delusion The Rage Against God Why I Am Not a Christian Why I Am Not a Muslim Books critical of Christianity Books critical of Islam

Movements

Agnosticism Antitheism Atheism Criticism of atheism Cārvāka New Atheism Nontheistic religions Parody religion

v t e

Anarchism

Schools of thought

Classical

Individualist

Egoist

Social

Collectivist Communist

Magonist

Leftist Syndicalist

Mutualist

Post-classical

Feminist Green

Primitivist Naturist

Pacifist Insurrectionary Nationalist Religious

Christian Buddhist Jewish Neopaganism

Without adjectives

Contemporary

Agorist Black Capitalist Market Post-anarchist

Postcolonial

Post-left Queer Transhumanism

Organization

Platformist Synthesist

Philosophical Existentialist Voluntaryism

Theory and practice

Anarchy Anarchist
Anarchist
Black Cross Anationalism Anti-authoritarianism Anti-militarism Affinity group Black bloc Classless society Class struggle Commune

model of government

Consensus democracy Conscientious objector Counter-economics Decentralization Deep ecology Direct action Direct democracy Dual power Especifismo Expropriative anarchism Free association Free love Free school Freethought Horizontalidad Illegalism Individualism Individual reclamation Isocracy Law Non-Aggression Principle Participism

Parecon Parpolity

Permanent autonomous zone Prefigurative politics Proletarian internationalism Propaganda of the deed Revolution Rewilding Social center Social ecology Social insertion Somatherapy Spontaneous order Squatting Temporary Autonomous Zone Union of egoists

Issues

Anarcho-capitalism Crypto-anarchism Animal rights Arts Capitalism Education Criticisms Islam Marxism Nationalism Orthodox Judaism Religion Love and sex Violence

People

18th c.

Sylvain Maréchal Gracchus Babeuf

19th c.

William Godwin Max Stirner Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Josiah Warren Henry David Thoreau Mikhail Bakunin Lysander Spooner Eugène Pottier Louise Michel Élisée Reclus Leo Tolstoy Ravachol Johann Most Giovanni Passannante Peter Kropotkin Francisco Ferrer Guardia Leon Czolgosz Voltairine de Cleyre

20th c.

Errico Malatesta Gustav Landauer Luigi Galleani Benjamin Tucker Ricardo Flores Magón Alexander Berkman Franz Kafka Emma Goldman Max Nettlau Erich Mühsam Sacco and Vanzetti Nestor Makhno Volin Rudolf Rocker Buenaventura Durruti Albert Camus Daniel Guérin Federica Montseny Jacques Ellul Léo Ferré Murray Rothbard Abbie Hoffman Murray Bookchin Ivan Illich Kurt Vonnegut Howard Zinn Ursula Le Guin Noam Chomsky Gary Snyder Alfredo M. Bonanno John Zerzan

21st c.

Subcomandante Marcos David Graeber Banksy

History

19th c.

Paris Commune Cantonal rebellion Hague Congress International Conference of Rome Trial of the Thirty Haymarket affair May Day

20th c.

Anarchist
Anarchist
Exclusion Act Congress of Amsterdam Tragic Week High Treason Incident Manifesto of the Sixteen 1919 United States bombings Biennio Rosso German Revolution
Revolution
of 1918–19 Bavarian Soviet Republic Kronstadt rebellion Third Russian Revolution Free Territory Amakasu incident Escuela Moderna Individualist anarchism
Individualist anarchism
in Europe (in France) Spanish Revolution
Revolution
and Civil War Barcelona May Days Labadie Collection May 1968 Provo LIP Kate Sharpley Library Australian Anarchist
Anarchist
Centenary Carnival Against Capital 1999 WTO Conference protest

21st c.

Occupy movement

Culture

Films Anarchist
Anarchist
Bookfair Anarcho-punk Culture jamming DIY culture Freeganism Independent Media Center Infoshop "The Internationale" Jewish anarchism "Land and liberty" Lifestylism "No gods, no masters" Popular education "Property is theft!" Radical cheerleading Radical environmentalism Squatting Symbolism Glossary A las Barricadas

Economics

Communization Co-operatives Cost the limit of price Counter-economics Decentralized planning Economic democracy Economic secession Free store Gift economy Laissez-faire Market abolitionism Mass strike Mutual aid Participatory economics Really Really Free Market Social ownership Wage slavery Refusal of work Workers' self-management

By region

Africa Argentina Australia Azerbaijan Brazil Canada China Cuba Ecuador Egypt France Germany Greece India Iceland Ireland Israel Italy Japan Korea Mexico Monaco New Zealand Poland Romania Russia South Africa Spain Sweden Turkey Ukraine United Kingdom United States Vietnam

Lists

Anarcho-punk
Anarcho-punk
bands Communities Fictional characters Jewish anarchists Love and sex Musicians Organizations Outline of anarchism Periodicals Poets Russian anarchists

Related topics

Anti-corporatism Anti-capitalism Anti-consumerism Anti-fascism Anti-globalization Anti-statism Anti-war Autarchism Autonomism International relations theory Classical liberalism Labour movement Left communism Libertarian socialism Libertarianism Neozapatismo Non-aggression principle Situationist International Spontaneous order

Anarchism
Anarchism
portal Philosophy portal Politics portal

Authority control

WorldCat Identities VIAF: 51780445 LCCN: n79054586 ISNI: 0000 0001 2132 8572 GND: 118618261 SELIBR: 199381 SUDOC: 033430586 BNF: cb124296680 (data) NLA: 35481082 NDL: 00457765 NKC: skuk000

.