HOME
The Info List - Ion (dialogue)





In Plato's Ion (/ˈaɪɒn/; Greek: Ἴων) Socrates
Socrates
discusses with the titular character, a professional rhapsode who also lectures on Homer, the question of whether the rhapsode, a performer of poetry, gives his performance on account of his skill and knowledge or by virtue of divine possession. It is one of the shortest of Plato's dialogues.[1]

Contents

1 Dialogue summary

1.1 Ion's skill: Is it genuine? (530a–533c) 1.2 The nature of poetic inspiration (533d–536d) 1.3 Ion's choice: To be skilled or inspired (536e–542a)

2 Commentary 3 See also 4 Notes 5 External links

Dialogue summary[edit] Ion's skill: Is it genuine? (530a–533c)[edit] Ion has just come from a festival of Asclepius
Asclepius
at the city of Epidaurus, after having won first prize in the competition. Socrates engages Ion in a philosophical discussion. Ion admits when Socrates asks, that his skill in performance recitation is limited to Homer, and that all other poets bore him. Socrates
Socrates
finds this puzzling, and sets out to solve the "riddle" of Ion's limited expertise. He points out to Ion that art critics and judges of sculpture normally do not limit themselves to judging the work of only a single artist, but can criticize the art no matter who the particular artist. The nature of poetic inspiration (533d–536d)[edit] Socrates
Socrates
deduces from this observation that Ion has no real skill, but is like a soothsayer or prophet in being divinely possessed: "For a poet is a light and winged and sacred thing, and is unable ever to indite until he has been inspired and put out of his senses, and his mind is no longer in him: every man, whilst he retains possession of that, is powerless to indite a verse or chant an oracle. Seeing then that it is not by art that they compose and utter so many fine things about the deeds of men— as you do about Homer—but by a divine dispensation, each is able only to compose that to which the Muse has stirred him, this man dithyrambs, another laudatory odes, another dance-songs, another epic or else iambic verse; but each is at fault in any other kind. For not by art do they utter these things, but by divine influence; since, if they had fully learnt by art to speak on one kind of theme, they would know how to speak on all. And for this reason God takes away the mind of these men and uses them as his ministers, just as he does soothsayers and godly seers, in order that we who hear them may know that it is not they who utter these words of great price, when they are out of their wits, but that it is God himself who speaks and addresses us through them."[534b–d] Socrates
Socrates
offers the metaphor of a magnet to explain how the rhapsode transmits the poet's original inspiration from the muse to the audience. He says that the god speaks first to the poet, then gives the rhapsode his skill, and thus, gods communicate to the people. Socrates
Socrates
posits that Ion must be out of his mind when he acts, because he can weep even though he has lost nothing, and recoil in fear when in front of an admiring audience. Ion says that the explanation for this is very simple: it is the promise of payment that inspires his deliberate disconnection from reality. Ion says that when he looks at the audience and sees them weeping, he knows he will laugh because it has made him richer, and that when they laugh, he will be weeping at losing the money (535e). Ion's choice: To be skilled or inspired (536e–542a)[edit] Ion tells Socrates
Socrates
that he cannot be convinced that he is possessed or mad when he performs (536d,e). Socrates
Socrates
then recites passages from Homer
Homer
which concern various arts such as medicine, divining, fishing, and making war. He asks Ion if these skills are distinct from his art of recitation. Ion admits that while Homer
Homer
discusses many different skills in his poetry, he never refers specifically to the rhapsode's craft, which is acting. Socrates
Socrates
presses him about the exact nature of his skill. Ion maintains that his knowledge makes him a capable military general but states that when he recites passages concerning military matters, he cannot tell whether he does it with a general's skill, or with a rhapsode's. Socrates
Socrates
notices that Ion changes his occupation. He was first a rhapsode and then has become a general. He gently berates the rhapsode for being Protean, which after all, is exactly what a rhapsode is: a man who is convincingly capable of being different people on stage. Through his character Socrates, Plato
Plato
argues that “Ion’s talent as an interpreter cannot be an art, a definable body of knowledge or an ordered system of skills,” but instead must come from the divine inspiration of the Muses.[2] Commentary[edit] Plato’s argument is supposed to be an early example of a so-called genetic fallacy since his conclusion arises from his famous lodestone (magnet) analogy. Ion, the rhapsode “dangles like a lodestone at the end of a chain of lodestones. The muse inspires the poet ( Homer
Homer
in Ion’s case) and the poet inspires the rhapsode.”[3] Plato’s dialogues are themselves “examples of artistry that continue to be stageworthy;” it is a paradox that “ Plato
Plato
the supreme enemy of art is also the supreme artist.”[3] Plato
Plato
develops a more elaborate critique of poetry in other dialogues such as in Phaedrus 245a, Symposium 209a, Republic 398a, Laws 817 b–d. [4] However, some researchers perceive it as a critique of unjustified belief rather than a critique of poetry in general.[5] See also[edit]

Poetics Poetics (Aristotle) Theia mania Crazy wisdom

Notes[edit]

^ Saunders, T. J. Introduction to Ion. London: Penguin Books, 1987, p. 39 ^ Barrish, J., The Antitheatrical Prejudice, p. 12. University of California Press, 1981. See also: Antitheatricality

^ a b Sonkowsky, R. P (1983) “Oral Performance and Ancient Greek Literature,” Thompson, D. W., ed., Performance of Literature in Historical Perspectives, p. 17. University Press of America ^ Saunders, p. 46 ^ Vlastos, G. (1991) “Socrates. Ironist and Moral Philosopher,” Cornell University Press

External links[edit]

Wikisource
Wikisource
has original text related to this article: Ion

Perseus Project Ion530a (entire text in Greek and English, trans. by W.R.M Lamb) Ion public domain audiobook at LibriVox

v t e

Socrates

General

Trial of Socrates

Legacy

Socratic dialogue Socratic method Socratic problem Socratic questioning Socratici viri

Phrases

"I know that I know nothing" "The unexamined life is not worth living"

Related

Euthyphro
Euthyphro
dilemma Form of the Good Peritrope Religious skepticism Social gadfly

Family

Sophroniscus (father) Phaenarete
Phaenarete
(mother) Xanthippe
Xanthippe
(wife) Lamprocles
Lamprocles
(son) Menexenus
Menexenus
(son) Myrto
Myrto
(wife)

Works about Socrates

Art

Double Herm of Socrates
Socrates
and Seneca (3rd century sculpture) The Death of Socrates
Socrates
(1787 painting) Socrates
Socrates
(1950 sculpture)

Stage

The Clouds
The Clouds
(423 BC play) Der geduldige Socrates
Socrates
(1721 opera) Socrates
Socrates
(1759 play) Socrate
Socrate
(1919 oratorio) Socrates
Socrates
on Trial (2007 play)

Literature

De genio Socratis
De genio Socratis
(1st century essay) On the Concept of Irony with Continual Reference to Socrates
Socrates
(1841 thesis) The Plot to Save Socrates
Socrates
(2006 novel)

Other

Barefoot in Athens
Barefoot in Athens
(1966 film) Socrates
Socrates
(1971 film)

Dialogues

Plato

Apology Axiochus Charmides Clitophon Cratylus Critias Crito Demodocus Epinomis Eryxias Euthydemus Euthyphro First Alcibiades Gorgias Hipparchus Hippias Major Hippias Minor Ion Laches Laws Lysis Menexenus Meno Minos On Justice On Virtue Parmenides Phaedo Phaedrus Philebus Protagoras Republic Rival Lovers Second Alcibiades Sisyphus Sophist Statesman Symposium Theaetetus Theages Timaeus

Xenophon

Apology Memorabilia Oeconomicus Symposium

Other

Halcyon

v t e

Plato

Life

Early life Platonism Platonic epistemology Platonic idealism Platonic realism Platonic love Neoplatonism
Neoplatonism
and Gnosticism Platonism
Platonism
in the Renaissance Demiurge Theory of Forms Transcendentals Form of the Good Third man argument Euthyphro
Euthyphro
dilemma Five regimes Philosopher king Unwritten doctrines Cultural influence of Plato's Republic

Works

Uncontested

Apology Charmides Cratylus Critias Crito Euthydemus Euthyphro Gorgias Hippias Minor Ion Laches

Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 228

Laws

Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 23

Lysis Menexenus Meno Parmenides Phaedo

Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 229

Phaedrus Philebus Protagoras Republic Sophist Statesman Symposium Theaetetus Timaeus

Of doubtful authenticity

Axiochus Clitophon Definitions Demodocus Epigrams Epinomis Epistles

Letter I Letter II Letter IV Letter V Letter VI Letter VII Letter IX Letter X Letter XI Letter XII

Eryxias First Alcibiades Halcyon Hipparchus Hippias Major Minos On Justice On Virtue Rival Lovers Second Alcibiades Sisyphus Theages

Allegories and metaphors

Atlantis Ring of Gyges The Cave The Divided Line The Sun Ship of State Myth of Er The Chariot Allegorical interpretations of Plato

Related

Commentaries The Academy in Athens Socratic problem Middle Platonism Neoplatonism

and Christianity

Poitier Meets Plato List of speakers in Plato's dialogues

Plato's Dream

Family

Ariston of Athens
Ariston of Athens
(father) Pyrilampes
Pyrilampes
(stepfather) Perictione
Perictione
(mother) Adeimantus of Collytus
Adeimantus of Collytus
(brother) Glaucon
Glaucon
(brother) Potone
Potone
(sister) Speusippus
Speusippus
(nephew)

Authority control

WorldCat Identities VIAF: 181828144 LCCN: n83031904 GND: 4257907-7 SUDOC: 122526430 BNF: cb1232

.