HOME
The Info List - Gorgias


--- Advertisement ---



Gorgias
Gorgias
(/ˈɡɔːrdʒiəs/;[1] Greek: Γοργίας, Ancient Greek: [ɡorɡíaːs]; c. 485 – c. 380 BC[2]) was a Greek sophist, Siceliote, pre-Socratic philosopher and rhetorician who was a native of Leontini
Leontini
in Sicily. Along with Protagoras, he forms the first generation of Sophists. Several doxographers report that he was a pupil of Empedocles, although he would only have been a few years younger. "Like other Sophists, he was an itinerant that practiced in various cities and giving public exhibitions of his skill at the great pan-Hellenic centers of Olympia and Delphi, and charged fees for his instruction and performances. A special feature of his displays was to ask miscellaneous questions from the audience and give impromptu replies."[3] He has been called " Gorgias
Gorgias
the Nihilist" although the degree to which this epithet adequately describes his philosophy is controversial.[4][5][6][7] His chief claim to recognition is that he transplanted rhetoric from his native Sicily
Sicily
to Attica, and contributed to the diffusion of the Attic dialect as the language of literary prose.

Contents

1 Life 2 Nihilism 3 Rhetorical innovation 4 On the Non-Existent 5 Rhetorical works

5.1 Encomium of Helen 5.2 Defense of Palamedes 5.3 Epitaphios (or the Athenian funeral oration)

6 Critics 7 See also 8 References 9 Sources

9.1 Primary sources 9.2 Secondary sources

10 External links

Life[edit] Gorgias
Gorgias
originated from Leontini, a Greek colony in Sicily, and what is often called 'the home of Spartan rhetoric.' It is known that Gorgias
Gorgias
had a father named Charmantides and two siblings – a brother named Herodicus and a sister who dedicated a statue to Gorgias
Gorgias
in Delphi
Delphi
(Consigny 6-7). He was around sixty years old in 427 BC when he was sent to Athens by his fellow-citizens at the head of an embassy to ask for Athenian protection against the aggression of the Syracusans. He subsequently settled in Athens, probably due to the enormous popularity of his style of oratory and the profits made from his performances and rhetoric classes. According to Aristotle, his students included Isocrates.[8] (Other students are named in later traditions; the Suda adds Pericles, Polus, and Alcidamas,[9] Diogenes Laërtius
Diogenes Laërtius
mentions Antisthenes,[10] and according to Philostratus, "I understand that he attracted the attention of the most admired men, Critias and Alcibiades
Alcibiades
who were young, and Thucydides
Thucydides
and Pericles
Pericles
who were already old. Agathon
Agathon
too, the tragic poet, whom Comedy regards as wise and eloquent, often Gorgianizes in his iambic verse").[11] Gorgias
Gorgias
is reputed to have lived to be one hundred and eight years old (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). He won admiration for his ability to speak on any subject (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). He accumulated considerable wealth; enough to commission a gold statue of himself for a public temple.[12] After his Pythian Oration, the Greeks installed a solid gold statue of him in the temple of Apollo
Apollo
at Delphi (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). He died at Larissa
Larissa
in Thessaly. Nihilism[edit] Gorgias
Gorgias
has been labelled "The Nihilist"[4][5][6][13][14] because some scholars have interpreted his thesis on "the non-existent" to be an argument against the existence of anything that is straightforwardly endorsed by Gorgias
Gorgias
himself.[15] Nihilism
Nihilism
is the belief that all values are baseless and that nothing can be known or communicated. It is associated with pessimism and a radical skepticism that condemns existence.[16] Gorgias
Gorgias
presented his nihilist arguments in On Non-Existence; however, the original text is no longer extant. We only know his arguments through commentary by Sextus Empiricus
Sextus Empiricus
and Pseudo-Aristotle’s De Melisso, Xenophane, Gorgia.[17] Ostensibly Gorgias
Gorgias
developed three sequential arguments: first, that nothing exists; second, that even if existence exists, it is inapprehensible to humans; and third, that even if existence is apprehensible, it certainly cannot be communicated or interpreted to one’s neighbors. That being said, there is consensus in late 20th century and early 21st century scholarship that the label 'nihilist' is misleading, in part because if his argument were genuinely meant to support nihilism it would be self-undermining. The argument, of course, is itself something, and has pretensions to communicate knowledge, in conflict with its explicit pronouncement that there is nothing and that it can't be known or communicated. Gisela Striker argues: "I find it hard to believe that anyone should ever have thought that Gorgias
Gorgias
seriously advocated the view that nothing is and that he was, therefore, a 'nihilist.'[18] Similarly Caston states: " Gorgias
Gorgias
would have to be not merely disconsolate, but quite dull-witted, to have missed the conflict between his presentation and its content"[19] Finally, Wardy says, "This sadly mistaken reading overlooks the most obvious consequence of Gorgias' paradoxologia (παραδοξολογία): his message refutes itself, and in consequence, so far from constituting a theory of logos, it confronts us with a picture of what language cannot be, with what it cannot be assumed to aspire to be."[20] Gigon and Newiger make similar points.[21][22] Rhetorical innovation[edit] Gorgias
Gorgias
ushered in rhetorical innovations involving structure and ornamentation, and the introduced paradoxologia – the idea of paradoxical thought and paradoxical expression. For these advancements, Gorgias
Gorgias
has been labeled the "father of sophistry" (Wardy 6). Gorgias
Gorgias
is also known for contributing to the diffusion of the Attic Greek
Attic Greek
dialect as the language of literary prose. Gorgias
Gorgias
was the first orator known to develop and teach a "distinctive style of speaking" (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). Gorgias’ extant rhetorical works— Encomium of Helen (Ἑλένης ἐγκώμιον), Defense of Palamedes (Ὑπέρ Παλαμήδους ἀπολογία), On Non-Existence (Περὶ τοῦ μὴ ὄντος ἢ Περὶ φύσεως), and Epitaphios (Επιτάφιος) —come to us via a work entitled Technai (Τέχναι), a manual of rhetorical instruction, which may have consisted of models to be memorized and demonstrate various principles of rhetorical practice (Leitch, et al. 29). Although some scholars claim that each work presents opposing statements, the four texts can be read as interrelated contributions to the up-and-coming theory and art (technē) of rhetoric (McComiskey 32). Of Gorgias’ surviving works, only the Encomium and the Defense are believed to exist in their entirety. Meanwhile, there are his own speeches, rhetorical, political, or other. A number of these are referred to and quoted by Aristotle, including a speech on Hellenic unity, a funeral oration for Athenians fallen in war, and a brief quotation from an Encomium on the Eleans. Apart from the speeches, there are paraphrases of the treatise "On Nature or the Non-Existent." These works are each part of the Diels-Kranz collection, and although academics consider this source reliable, many of the works included are fragmentary and corrupt. Questions have also been raised as to the authenticity and accuracy of the texts attributed to Gorgias
Gorgias
(Consigny 4). Gorgias’ writings are intended to be both rhetorical (persuasive) and performative. He goes to great lengths to exhibit his ability of making an absurd, argumentative position appear stronger. Consequently, each of his works defend positions that are unpopular, paradoxical and even absurd. The performative nature of Gorgias’ writings is exemplified by the way that he playfully approaches each argument with stylistic devices such as parody, artificial figuration and theatricality (Consigny 149). Gorgias’ style of argumentation can be described as poetics-minus-the-meter (poiêsis-minus-meter). Gorgias
Gorgias
argues that persuasive words have power (dunamis) that is equivalent to that of the gods and as strong as physical force. In the Encomium, Gorgias
Gorgias
likens the effect of speech on the soul to the effect of drugs on the body: "Just as different drugs draw forth different humors from the body – some putting a stop to disease, others to life – so too with words: some cause pain, others joy, some strike fear, some stir the audience to boldness, some benumb and bewitch the soul with evil persuasion" ( Gorgias
Gorgias
32). The Encomium "argues for the totalizing power of language."[23] Gorgias
Gorgias
also believed that his "magical incantations" would bring healing to the human psyche by controlling powerful emotions. He paid particular attention to the sounds of words, which, like poetry, could captivate audiences. His florid, rhyming style seemed to hypnotize his audiences (Herrick 42). Unlike other Sophists, such as Protagoras, Gorgias
Gorgias
did not profess to teach arete (excellence, or, virtue). He believed that there was no absolute form of arete, but that it was relative to each situation. For example, virtue in a slave was not the same as virtue in a statesman. He believed that rhetoric, the art of persuasion, was the king of all sciences, since he saw it as a techné with which one could persuade an audience toward any course of action. While rhetoric existed in the curriculum of every Sophist, Gorgias
Gorgias
placed more prominence upon it than any of the others. Much debate over both the nature and value of rhetoric begins with Gorgias. Plato's dialogue Gorgias
Gorgias
presents a counter-argument to Gorgias’ embrace of rhetoric, its elegant form, and performative nature (Wardy 2). The dialogue tells the story of a debate about rhetoric, politics and justice that occurred at a dinner gathering between Socrates
Socrates
and a small group of Sophists. Plato
Plato
attempts to show that rhetoric does not meet the requirements to actually be considered a technê but rather is a somewhat dangerous "knack" to possess, both for the orator and for his audience, because it gives the ignorant the power to seem more knowledgeable than an expert to a group. On the Non-Existent[edit] Gorgias
Gorgias
is the author of a lost work: On Nature or the Non-Existent (also On Non-Existence). Rather than being one of his rhetorical works, it presented a theory of being that at the same time refuted and parodied the Eleatic thesis. The original text was lost and today there remain just two paraphrases of it. The first is preserved by the philosopher Sextus Empiricus
Sextus Empiricus
in Against the Professors and the other by the anonymous author of On Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias. Each work, however, excludes material that is discussed in the other, which suggests that each version may represent intermediary sources (Consigny 4). It is clear, however, that the work developed a skeptical argument, which has been extracted from the sources and translated as below:

Nothing exists; Even if something exists, nothing can be known about it; and Even if something can be known about it, knowledge about it can't be communicated to others. Even if it can be communicated, it cannot be understood.

The argument has largely been seen as an ironic refutation of Parmenides' thesis on Being. Gorgias
Gorgias
set out to prove that it is as easy to demonstrate that being is one, unchanging and timeless as it is to prove that being has no existence at all. Regardless of how it "has largely been seen" it seems clear that Gorgias
Gorgias
was focused instead on the notion that true objectivity is impossible since the human mind can never be separated from its possessor. "How can anyone communicate the idea of color by means of words since the ear does not hear colors but only sounds?" This quote, written by the Sicilian philosopher Gorgias, was used to show his theory that ‘there is nothing’, ‘if there were anything no one would know it’, ‘and if anyone did know it, no one could communicate it’. This theory, thought of in the late 5th century BC, is still being contemplated by many philosophers throughout the world. This argument has led some to label Gorgias
Gorgias
a nihilist (one who believes nothing exists, or that the world is incomprehensible, and that the concept of truth is fictitious). For the first main argument where Gorgias
Gorgias
says, "there is no-thing", he tries to persuade the reader that thought and existence are not the same. By claiming that if thought and existence truly were the same, then everything that anyone thought would suddenly exist. He also attempted to prove that words and sensations couldn’t be measured by the same standards, for even though words and sensations are both derived from the mind, they are essentially different. This is where his second idea comes into place. Rhetorical works[edit] Encomium of Helen[edit]

Helen of Troy
Helen of Troy
by Evelyn De Morgan
Evelyn De Morgan
(1898, London)

The Encomium of Helen is considered to be a good example of epideictic oratory and was supposed to have been Gorgias' "show piece or demonstration piece," which was used to attract students (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). In their writings, Gorgias
Gorgias
and other sophists speculated "about the structure and function of language" as a framework for expressing the implications of action and the ways decisions about such actions were made" (Jarratt 103). And this is exactly the purpose of Gorgias’ Encomium of Helen. Of the three divisions of rhetoric discussed by Aristotle
Aristotle
in his Rhetoric (forensic, deliberative, and epideictic), the Encomium can be classified as an epideictic speech, expressing praise for Helen of Troy
Troy
and ridding her of the blame she faced for leaving Sparta
Sparta
with Paris (Wardy 26). Helen – the proverbial "Helen of Troy" – exemplified both sexual passion and tremendous beauty for the Greeks. She was the daughter of Zeus
Zeus
and Leda, the Queen of Sparta, and her beauty was seen by the Trojans as the direct cause of the decade long Trojan War
Trojan War
between Greece
Greece
and Troy. The war began after the goddesses Hera, Athena, and Aphrodite
Aphrodite
asked Paris (a Trojan prince) to select who was the most beautiful of the three. Each goddess tried to influence Paris’ decision, but he ultimately chose Aphrodite
Aphrodite
who then promised Paris the most beautiful woman. Paris then traveled to Greece
Greece
where he was greeted by Helen and her husband Menelaus. Under the influence of Aphrodite, Helen allowed Paris to persuade her to elope with him. Together they traveled to Troy, not only sparking the war, but also a popular and literary tradition of blaming Helen for her wrongdoing. It is this tradition which Gorgias
Gorgias
confronts in the Encomium. The Encomium opens with Gorgias
Gorgias
explaining that "a man, woman, speech, deed, city or action that is worthy of praise should be honored with acclaim, but the unworthy should be branded with blame" ( Gorgias
Gorgias
30). In the speech Gorgias
Gorgias
discusses the possible reasons for Helen’s journey to Troy. He explains that Helen could have been persuaded in one of four ways: by the gods, by physical force, by love, or by speech (logos). If it were indeed the plan of the gods that caused Helen to depart for Troy, Gorgias
Gorgias
argues that those who blame her should face blame themselves, "for a human’s anticipation cannot restrain a god’s inclination" ( Gorgias
Gorgias
31). Gorgias
Gorgias
explains that, by nature, the weak are ruled by the strong, and, since the gods are stronger than humans in all respects, Helen should be freed from her undesirable reputation. If, however, Helen was abducted by force, it is clear that the aggressor committed a crime. Thus, it should be he, not Helen, who should be blamed. And if Helen was persuaded by love, she should also be rid of ill repute because "if love is a god, with the divine power of the gods, how could a weaker person refuse and reject him? But if love is a human sickness and a mental weakness, it must not be blamed as mistake, but claimed as misfortune" (Gorgias 32). Finally, if speech persuaded Helen, Gorgias
Gorgias
claims he can easily clear her of blame. Gorgias
Gorgias
explains: "Speech is a powerful master and achieves the most divine feats with the smallest and least evident body. It can stop fear, relieve pain, create joy, and increase pity" ( Gorgias
Gorgias
31). It is here that Gorgias
Gorgias
compares the effect of speech on the mind with the effect of drugs on the body. He states that Helen has the power to "lead" many bodies in competition by using her body as a weapon (Gumpert, 74). This image of "bodies led and misled, brought together and led apart, is of paramount importance in Gorgias' speech," (Gumpert, 74). While Gorgias
Gorgias
primarily used metaphors and paradox, he famously used "figures of speech, or schemata," (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa). This included balanced clauses (isocolon), the joining of contrasting ideas (antithesis), the structure of successive clauses (parison), and the repetition of word endings (homoeoteleuton) (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). The Encomium shows Gorgias' interest in argumentation, as he makes his point by "systematically refuting a series of possible alternatives," (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). It is an encomium of the "rhetorical craft itself, and a demonstration of its power over us," (Gumpert, 73). According to Van Hook, The Encomium of Helen abounds in "amplification and brevity, a rhythm making prose akin to poetry, bold metaphors and poetic or unusual epithets" (122).[24] Defense of Palamedes[edit] In the Defense of Palamedes Gorgias
Gorgias
describes logos as a positive instrument for creating ethical arguments (McComiskey 38). The Defense, an oration that deals with issues of morality and political commitment (Consigny 38), defends Palamedes who, in Greek mythology, is credited with the invention of the alphabet, written laws, numbers, armor, and measures and weights (McComiskey 47). In the speech Palamedes defends himself against the charge of treason. In Greek mythology, Odysseus
Odysseus
– in order to avoid going to Troy
Troy
with Agamemnon
Agamemnon
and Menelaus
Menelaus
to bring Helen back to Sparta
Sparta
– pretended to have gone mad and began sowing the fields with salt. When Palamedes threw Odysseus' son, Telemachus, in front of the plow, Odysseus avoided him, demonstrating that he was sane. Odysseus, who never forgave Palamedes for making him reveal himself, later accused Palamedes of betraying the Greeks to the Trojans. Soon after, Palamedes was condemned and killed (Jarratt 58). In this epideictic speech, like the Encomium, Gorgias
Gorgias
is concerned with experimenting with how plausible arguments can cause conventional truths to be doubted (Jarratt 59). Throughout the text, Gorgias presents a method for composing logical (logos), ethical (ethos) and emotional (pathos) arguments from possibility, which are similar to those described by Aristotle
Aristotle
in Rhetoric. These types of arguments about motive and capability presented in the Defense are later described by Aristotle
Aristotle
as forensic topoi. Gorgias
Gorgias
demonstrates that in order to prove that treason had been committed, a set of possible occurrences also need to be established. In the Defense these occurrences are as follows: communication between Palamedes and the enemy, exchange of a pledge in the form of hostages or money, and not being detected by guards or citizens. In his defense, Palamedes claims that a small sum of money would not have warranted such a large undertaking and reasons that a large sum of money, if indeed such a transaction had been made, would require the aid of many confederates in order for it to be transported. Palamedes reasons further that such an exchange could neither have occurred at night because the guards would be watching, nor in the day because everyone would be able to see. Palamedes continues, explaining that if the aforementioned conditions were, in fact, arranged then action would need to follow. Such action needed to take place either with or without confederates; however, if these confederates were free men then they were free to disclose any information they desired, but if they were slaves there was a risk of their voluntarily accusing to earn freedom, or accusing by force when tortured. Slaves, Palamedes says, are untrustworthy. Palamedes goes on to list a variety of possible motives, all of which he proves false. Through the Defense Gorgias
Gorgias
demonstrates that a motive requires an advantage such as status, wealth, honour, and security, and insists that Palamedes lacked a motive (McComiskey 47-49). Epitaphios (or the Athenian funeral oration)[edit] This text is considered to be an important contribution to the genre of epitaphios. During the 5th and 4th centuries BC, such funeral orations were delivered by well-known orators during public burial ceremonies in Athens, whereby those who died in wars were honoured. Gorgias’ text provides a clever critique of 5th century propagandist rhetoric in imperial Athens and is the basis for Plato’s parody, Menexenus
Menexenus
(Consigny 2). Critics[edit] Plato
Plato
was one of Gorgias’ greatest critics and a student of Socrates. Plato’s dislike for sophistic doctrines is well known, and it is in his eponymous dialogue that both Gorgias
Gorgias
himself as well as his rhetorical beliefs are ridiculed (McComiskey 17). In the Gorgias, Plato
Plato
distinguishes between philosophy and rhetoric, characterizing Gorgias
Gorgias
as an orator who entertains his audience with his eloquent words and who believes that it is unnecessary to learn the truth about actual matters when one has discovered the art of persuasion (Consigny 36). In the dialogue, Gorgias
Gorgias
responds to one of Socrates’ statements as follows: " Rhetoric
Rhetoric
is the only area of expertise you need to learn. You can ignore all the rest and still get the better of the professionals!" ( Plato
Plato
24). Gorgias, whose On Non-Existence is taken to be critical of the Eleatic tradition and its founder Parmenides, describes philosophy as a type of seduction, but he does not deny philosophy entirely, giving some respect to philosophers (Consigny 37). Plato
Plato
answers Gorgias
Gorgias
by reaffirming the Parmenidean ideal that being is the basic substance and reality of which all things are composed, insisting that philosophy is a dialectic distinct from and superior to rhetoric (Wardy 52). Aristotle
Aristotle
also criticizes Gorgias, labeling him a mere Sophist whose primary goal is to make money by appearing wise and clever, thus deceiving the public by means of misleading or sophistic arguments (Consigny 36). See also[edit]

Hellenistic philosophy

References[edit]

^ "Gorgias" entry in Collins English Dictionary. ^ Oxford Classical Dictionary, 3rd. ed. s.v. "Gorgias" (Oxford, 1996) ^ W. K. C. Guthrie, The Sophists (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1971), p. 270. ^ a b J. Radford Thomson (1887). A dictionary of philosophy in the words of philosophers. Reeves and Turner. p. 225.  ^ a b Rosenkrantz, G. (2002). The Possibility of Metaphysics: Substance, Identity, and Time*. Philosophy
Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research, 64(3), 728-736. ^ a b Gronbeck, B. E. (1972). Gorgias
Gorgias
on rhetoric and poetic: A rehabilitation. Southern Journal of Communication, 38(1), 27-38. ^ Caston, V. (2002). Gorgias
Gorgias
on Thought and its Objects. Presocratic philosophy: Essays in honor of Alexander Mourelatos. ^ Aristotle, fr. 130 Rose = Quintilian
Quintilian
3.1.13. ^ Suda, Gorgias ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vi. 2 ^ Lives of the Sophists 1.9, trans. George Kennedy in The Older Sophists, ed. R.K. Sprague (Columbia, S.C., 1972), p. 31. ^ Sprague, Rosamond Kent, The Older Sophists, Hackett Publishing Company (ISBN 0-87220-556-8), p. 31 ^ A History of Philosophy
Philosophy
from Thales
Thales
to the Present Time by Friedrich Ueberweg: History of the ancient and mediaeval philosophy, Volume 1, Friedrich Ueberweg, Hodder and Stoughton, 1872 p. 72 ^ The Crime of Credulity, Herbert Newton Casson,P. Eckler, 1901 p. 15 ^ Higgins, C. Francis. "Gorgias". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2013.  ^ Pratt, Alan. "Nihilism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2013.  ^ McComiskey, Bruce (1997). "Gorgias, "On Non-Existence": Sextus Empiricus, "Against the Logicians" 1.65-87, Translated from the Greek Text in Hermann Diels's "Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker". Philosophy and rhetoric. 30 (1): 45. JSTOR 40237935.  ^ Striker, Gisela. "Methods of sophistry." Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology
Epistemology
and Ethics (1996): p.13 ^ Caston, Victor. " Gorgias
Gorgias
on Thought and its Objects." Presocratic philosophy: Essays in honor of Alexander Mourelatos (2002): p.205 ^ Wardy, Robert. The birth of rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato
Plato
and their successors. Routledge, 2005. ^ Gigon, Olof. "Gorgias' Über das Nichtsein'." Hermes (1936): p213 ^ Newiger, Hans-Joachim. Untersuchungen zu Gorgias' Schrift über das Nichtseiende. Walter de Gruyter, 1973. ^ Bizzell; Herzberg. The Rhetorical Tradition.  ^ Van Hook, LaRue (February 15, 1913). "The Encomium of Helen by Gorgias". The Classical Weekly. 6 (16): 122–3. doi:10.2307/4386697. 

Sources[edit] Primary sources[edit]

Gorgias. " Encomium of Helen." The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism. Eds. Vincent B. Leitch, et al. New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 2001. 30-33. Plato. Gorgias. Trans. Robin Waterfield. Oxford University Press, 1994.

Secondary sources[edit]

Consigny, Scott. Gorgias: Sophist and Artist. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 2001. Gumpert, Matthew. Grafting Helen: the Abduction of the Classical Past. Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press, 2001. Jarratt, Susan C. Rereading the Sophists: Classical Rhetoric Refigured. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1991. Leitch, Vincent B. et al., eds. The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism. New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2001. McComiskey, Bruce. Gorgias
Gorgias
and the Art of Rhetoric: Toward a Holistic Reading of the Extant Gorgianic Fragments. Taylor & Francis, Ltd., 1997. McComiskey, Bruce. Gorgias
Gorgias
and the New Sophistic Rhetoric. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 2001. Matsen, Patricia P. Philip Rollinson and Marion Sousa. Readings from Classical Rhetoric, Illinois: Southern Illinois University Press, 1990. Poulakos, John. "Sophistical Rhetoric
Rhetoric
in Classical Greece", University of South Carolina Press, 1995. Sprague, Rosamond Kent. The Older Sophists, Hackett Publishing Company(ISBN 0-87220-556-8). Walker, Jeffrey. Rhetoric
Rhetoric
and Poetics in Antiquity, New York: Oxford University Press, 2000. Wardy, Robert. The Birth of Rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato
Plato
and Their Successors, New York: Routledge, 1996.

External links[edit]

 Greek Wikisource
Wikisource
has original text related to this article: Γοργίας Encomium on Helen: Greek text and English translation Gorgias, selected texts (from Plato's Gorgias) in Greek (with German translation and vocabulary notes) Gorgias, entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy On the Nonexistent in Sextus Empiricus, Adv. Ac. VII, 65-87 Encomium on Helen: public domain audiobook Mappa concettuale del ragionamento di Gorgia (Italian) Works by or about Gorgias
Gorgias
at Internet Archive Works by Gorgias
Gorgias
at LibriVox
LibriVox
(public domain audiobooks)

v t e

Sophists of the 5th century BC

Protagoras Gorgias Prodicus Hippias Antiphon Lycophron Damon Callicles Thrasymachus Euthydemus Dionysodorus Euenus Critias Dissoi logoi

v t e

Pre-Socratic
Pre-Socratic
philosophers by school

Milesian

Thales Anaximander Anaximenes

Pythagorean

Pythagoras Hippasus Philolaus Archytas

Ephesian

Heraclitus

Eleatic

Parmenides Zeno Melissus

Pluralist

Anaxagoras Archelaus Empedocles

Atomist

Leucippus Democritus

Sophistic

Protagoras Gorgias Prodicus Hippias

Others

Xenophanes Pherecydes Hippo Diogenes Alcmaeon

v t e

Ancient Greece

Outline Timeline

History Geography

Periods

Cycladic civilization Minoan civilization Mycenaean civilization Greek Dark Ages Archaic period Classical Greece Hellenistic Greece Roman Greece

Geography

Aegean Sea Aeolis Alexandria Antioch Cappadocia Crete Cyprus Doris Ephesus Epirus Hellespont Ionia Ionian Sea Macedonia Magna Graecia Miletus Peloponnesus Pergamon Pontus Taurica Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek
colonies

City states Politics Military

City states

Argos Athens Byzantion Chalcis Corinth Eretria Kerkyra Larissa Megalopolis Megara Rhodes Samos Sparta Syracuse Thebes

Politics

Boeotarch Boule Koinon Proxeny Strategos Tagus Tyrant Amphictyonic League

Athenian

Agora Areopagus Ecclesia Graphē paranómōn Heliaia Ostracism

Spartan

Apella Ephor Gerousia Harmost

Macedon

Synedrion Koinon

Military

Wars Athenian military Antigonid Macedonian army Army of Macedon Ballista Cretan archers Hellenistic armies Hippeis Hoplite Hetairoi Macedonian phalanx Phalanx Peltast Pezhetairos Sarissa Sacred Band of Thebes Sciritae Seleucid army Spartan army Toxotai Xiphos Xyston

People

List of ancient Greeks

Rulers

Kings of Argos Archons of Athens Kings of Athens Kings of Commagene Diadochi Kings of Lydia Kings of Macedonia Kings of Paionia Attalid kings of Pergamon Kings of Pontus Kings of Sparta Tyrants of Syracuse

Philosophers

Anaxagoras Anaximander Anaximenes Antisthenes Aristotle Democritus Diogenes of Sinope Empedocles Epicurus Gorgias Heraclitus Hypatia Leucippus Parmenides Plato Protagoras Pythagoras Socrates Thales Zeno

Authors

Aeschylus Aesop Alcaeus Archilochus Aristophanes Bacchylides Euripides Herodotus Hesiod Hipponax Homer Ibycus Lucian Menander Mimnermus Panyassis Philocles Pindar Plutarch Polybius Sappho Simonides Sophocles Stesichorus Theognis Thucydides Timocreon Tyrtaeus Xenophon

Others

Agesilaus II Agis II Alcibiades Alexander the Great Aratus Archimedes Aspasia Demosthenes Epaminondas Euclid Hipparchus Hippocrates Leonidas Lycurgus Lysander Milo of Croton Miltiades Pausanias Pericles Philip of Macedon Philopoemen Praxiteles Ptolemy Pyrrhus Solon Themistocles

Groups

Philosophers Playwrights Poets Tyrants

By culture

Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek
tribes Thracian Greeks Ancient Macedonians

Society Culture

Society

Agriculture Calendar Clothing Coinage Cuisine Economy Education Festivals Funeral and burial practices Homosexuality Law Olympic Games Pederasty Philosophy Prostitution Religion Slavery Warfare Wedding customs Wine

Arts and science

Architecture

Greek Revival architecture

Astronomy Literature Mathematics Medicine Music

Musical system

Pottery Sculpture Technology Theatre

Religion

Funeral and burial practices Mythology

mythological figures

Temple Twelve Olympians Underworld

Sacred places

Eleusis Delphi Delos Dodona Mount Olympus Olympia

Structures

Athenian Treasury Lion Gate Long Walls Philippeion Theatre of Dionysus Tunnel of Eupalinos

Temples

Aphaea Artemis Athena
Athena
Nike Erechtheion Hephaestus Hera, Olympia Parthenon Samothrace Zeus, Olympia

Language

Proto-Greek Mycenaean Homeric Dialects

Aeolic Arcadocypriot Attic Doric Ionic Locrian Macedonian Pamphylian

Koine

Writing

Linear A Linear B Cypriot syllabary Greek alphabet Greek numerals Attic numerals

Lists

Cities

in Epirus

People Place names Stoae Temples Theatres

Category Portal

Authority control

WorldCat Identities VIAF: 305414374 LCCN: n82106049 ISNI: 0000 0001 1241 4233 GND: 118696521 SELIBR: 245686 SUDOC: 029810450 BNF: cb12135750x (data) BIBSYS: 90088646 ICCU: ITICCUMILV7

.