HOME
The Info List - Ethics



--- Advertisement ---


ETHICS or MORAL PHILOSOPHY is a branch of philosophy that involves systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong conduct . The term _ethics_ derives from Ancient Greek ἠθικός _(ethikos)_, from ἦθος _(ethos )_, meaning 'habit , custom'. The branch of philosophy axiology comprises the sub-branches of ethics and aesthetics , each concerned with values .

As a branch of philosophy, ethics investigates the questions "What is the best way for people to live?" and "What actions are right or wrong in particular circumstances?" In practice, ethics seeks to resolve questions of human morality by defining concepts such as good and evil , right and wrong , virtue and vice , justice and crime . As a field of intellectual enquiry, moral philosophy also is related to the fields of moral psychology , descriptive ethics , and value theory .

Three major areas of study within ethics recognised today are:

* Meta-ethics , concerning the theoretical meaning and reference of moral propositions, and how their truth values (if any) can be determined * Normative ethics , concerning the practical means of determining a moral course of action * Applied ethics , concerning what a person is obligated (or permitted) to do in a specific situation or a particular domain of action

CONTENTS

* 1 Defining ethics * 2 Meta-ethics

* 3 Normative ethics

* 3.1 Virtue ethics

* 3.1.1 Stoicism * 3.1.2 Contemporary virtue ethics

* 3.2 Hedonism

* 3.2.1 Cyrenaic hedonism * 3.2.2 Epicureanism

* 3.3 State consequentialism

* 3.4 Consequentialism/Teleology

* 3.4.1 Utilitarianism

* 3.5 Deontology * 3.6 Pragmatic ethics * 3.7 Ethics of care * 3.8 Role ethics * 3.9 Anarchist ethics * 3.10 Postmodern ethics

* 4 Applied ethics

* 4.1 Specific questions

* 4.2 Particular fields of application

* 4.2.1 Bioethics * 4.2.2 Business ethics * 4.2.3 Machine ethics * 4.2.4 Military ethics * 4.2.5 Political ethics * 4.2.6 Public sector ethics * 4.2.7 Publication ethics * 4.2.8 Relational ethics * 4.2.9 Animal ethics

* 5 Moral psychology

* 5.1 Evolutionary ethics

* 6 Descriptive ethics * 7 See also * 8 Notes * 9 References * 10 Further reading * 11 External links

DEFINING ETHICS

Rushworth Kidder states that "standard definitions of _ethics_ have typically included such phrases as 'the science of the ideal human character' or 'the science of moral duty'". Richard William Paul and Linda Elder define ethics as "a set of concepts and principles that guide us in determining what behavior helps or harms sentient creatures". The _Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy _ states that the word ethics is "commonly used interchangeably with 'morality ' ... and sometimes it is used more narrowly to mean the moral principles of a particular tradition, group or individual." Paul and Elder state that most people confuse ethics with behaving in accordance with social conventions, religious beliefs and the law and don't treat ethics as a stand-alone concept.

The word "ethics" in English refers to several things. It can refer to philosophical ethics or moral philosophy—a project that attempts to use reason in order to answer various kinds of ethical questions. As the English philosopher Bernard Williams writes, attempting to explain moral philosophy: "What makes an inquiry a philosophical one is reflective generality and a style of argument that claims to be rationally persuasive." And Williams describes the content of this area of inquiry as addressing the very broad question, "how one should live" Ethics can also refer to a common human ability to think about ethical problems that is not particular to philosophy. As bioethicist Larry Churchill has written: "Ethics, understood as the capacity to think critically about moral values and direct our actions in terms of such values, is a generic human capacity." Ethics can also be used to describe a particular person's own idiosyncratic principles or habits. For example: "Joe has strange ethics."

The English word ethics is derived from an Ancient Greek word _êthikos_, which means "relating to one's character". The Ancient Greek adjective _êthikos_ is itself derived from another Greek word, the noun _êthos_ meaning "character, disposition".

META-ETHICS

Main article: Meta-ethics

Meta-ethics asks how we understand, know about, and what we mean when we talk about what is right and what is wrong. An ethical question fixed on some particular practical question—such as, "Should I eat this particular piece of chocolate cake?"—cannot be a meta-ethical question. A meta-ethical question is abstract and relates to a wide range of more specific practical questions. For example, "Is it ever possible to have secure knowledge of what is right and wrong?" would be a meta-ethical question.

Meta-ethics has always accompanied philosophical ethics. For example, Aristotle implies that less precise knowledge is possible in ethics than in other spheres of inquiry, and he regards ethical knowledge as depending upon habit and acculturation in a way that makes it distinctive from other kinds of knowledge. Meta-ethics is also important in G.E. Moore 's _ Principia Ethica _ from 1903. In it he first wrote about what he called _the naturalistic fallacy _. Moore was seen to reject naturalism in ethics, in his Open Question Argument . This made thinkers look again at second order questions about ethics. Earlier, the Scottish philosopher David Hume had put forward a similar view on the difference between facts and values .

Studies of how we know in ethics divide into cognitivism and non-cognitivism ; this is similar to the contrast between descriptivists and non-descriptivists. Non-cognitivism is the claim that when we judge something as right or wrong, this is neither true nor false. We may for example be only expressing our emotional feelings about these things. Cognitivism can then be seen as the claim that when we talk about right and wrong, we are talking about matters of fact.

The ontology of ethics is about value -bearing things or properties, i.e. the kind of things or stuff referred to by ethical propositions. Non-descriptivists and non-cognitivists believe that ethics does not need a specific ontology, since ethical propositions do not refer. This is known as an anti-realist position. Realists on the other hand must explain what kind of entities, properties or states are relevant for ethics, how they have value, and why they guide and motivate our actions.

NORMATIVE ETHICS

Main article: Normative ethics

Normative ethics is the study of ethical action. It is the branch of ethics that investigates the set of questions that arise when considering how one ought to act, morally speaking. Normative ethics is distinct from meta-ethics because it examines standards for the rightness and wrongness of actions, while meta-ethics studies the meaning of moral language and the metaphysics of moral facts. Normative ethics is also distinct from descriptive ethics , as the latter is an empirical investigation of people's moral beliefs. To put it another way, descriptive ethics would be concerned with determining what proportion of people believe that killing is always wrong, while normative ethics is concerned with whether it is correct to hold such a belief. Hence, normative ethics is sometimes called prescriptive, rather than descriptive. However, on certain versions of the meta-ethical view called moral realism , moral facts are both descriptive and prescriptive at the same time.

Traditionally, normative ethics (also known as moral theory) was the study of what makes actions right and wrong. These theories offered an overarching moral principle one could appeal to in resolving difficult moral decisions.

At the turn of the 20th century, moral theories became more complex and are no longer concerned solely with rightness and wrongness, but are interested in many different kinds of moral status. During the middle of the century, the study of normative ethics declined as meta-ethics grew in prominence. This focus on meta-ethics was in part caused by an intense linguistic focus in analytic philosophy and by the popularity of logical positivism .

In 1971 John Rawls published _A Theory of Justice _, noteworthy in its pursuit of moral arguments and eschewing of meta-ethics.

VIRTUE ETHICS

Main article: Virtue ethics Socrates

Virtue ethics describes the character of a moral agent as a driving force for ethical behavior, and is used to describe the ethics of Socrates , Aristotle , and other early Greek philosophers. Socrates (469–399 BC) was one of the first Greek philosophers to encourage both scholars and the common citizen to turn their attention from the outside world to the condition of humankind. In this view, knowledge bearing on human life was placed highest, while all other knowledge were secondary. Self-knowledge was considered necessary for success and inherently an essential good. A self-aware person will act completely within his capabilities to his pinnacle, while an ignorant person will flounder and encounter difficulty. To Socrates, a person must become aware of every fact (and its context) relevant to his existence, if he wishes to attain self-knowledge. He posited that people will naturally do what is good, if they know what is right. Evil or bad actions are the result of ignorance. If a criminal was truly aware of the intellectual and spiritual consequences of his actions, he would neither commit nor even consider committing those actions. Any person who knows what is truly right will automatically do it, according to Socrates. While he correlated knowledge with virtue , he similarly equated virtue with joy . The truly wise man will know what is right, do what is good, and therefore be happy. :32–33

Aristotle (384–323 BC) posited an ethical system that may be termed "self-realizationism". In Aristotle's view, when a person acts in accordance with his nature and realizes his full potential, he will do good and be content. At birth, a baby is not a person, but a potential person. To become a "real" person, the child's inherent potential must be realized. Unhappiness and frustration are caused by the unrealized potential of a person, leading to failed goals and a poor life. Aristotle said, " Nature does nothing in vain." Therefore, it is imperative for people to act in accordance with their nature and develop their latent talents in order to be content and complete. Happiness was held to be the ultimate goal. All other things, such as civic life or wealth , are merely means to the end. Self-realization, the awareness of one's nature and the development of one's talents, is the surest path to happiness. :33–35

Aristotle asserted that man had three natures: body (physical/metabolism), animal (emotional/appetite) and rational (mental/conceptual). Physical nature can be assuaged through exercise and care, emotional nature through indulgence of instinct and urges, and mental through human reason and developed potential. Rational development was considered the most important, as essential to philosophical self-awareness and as uniquely human. Moderation was encouraged, with the extremes seen as degraded and immoral. For example, courage is the moderate virtue between the extremes of cowardice and recklessness . Man should not simply live, but live well with conduct governed by moderate virtue. This is regarded as difficult, as virtue denotes doing the right thing, to the right person, at the right time, to the proper extent, in the correct fashion, for the right reason. :35–37

Stoicism

Main article: Stoicism Epictetus

The Stoic philosopher Epictetus posited that the greatest good was contentment and serenity. Peace of mind, or Apatheia , was of the highest value ; self-mastery over one's desires and emotions leads to spiritual peace. The "unconquerable will" is central to this philosophy. The individual's will should be independent and inviolate. Allowing a person to disturb the mental equilibrium is in essence offering yourself in slavery. If a person is free to anger you at will, you have no control over your internal world, and therefore no freedom. Freedom from material attachments is also necessary. If a thing breaks, the person should not be upset, but realize it was a thing that could break. Similarly, if someone should die, those close to them should hold to their serenity because the loved one was made of flesh and blood destined to death. Stoic philosophy says to accept things that cannot be changed, resigning oneself to existence and enduring in a rational fashion. Death is not feared. People do not "lose" their life, but instead "return", for they are returning to God (who initially gave what the person is as a person). Epictetus said difficult problems in life should not be avoided, but rather embraced. They are spiritual exercises needed for the health of the spirit, just as physical exercise is required for the health of the body. He also stated that sex and sexual desire are to be avoided as the greatest threat to the integrity and equilibrium of a man's mind. Abstinence is highly desirable. Epictetus said remaining abstinent in the face of temptation was a victory for which a man could be proud. :38–41

Contemporary Virtue Ethics

Modern virtue ethics was popularized during the late 20th century in large part as a response to G. E. M. Anscombe 's "Modern Moral Philosophy ". Anscombe argues that consequentialist and deontological ethics are only feasible as universal theories if the two schools ground themselves in divine law. As a deeply devoted Christian herself, Anscombe proposed that either those who do not give ethical credence to notions of divine law take up virtue ethics, which does not necessitate universal laws as agents themselves are investigated for virtue or vice and held up to "universal standards", or that those who wish to be utilitarian or consequentialist ground their theories in religious conviction. Alasdair MacIntyre , who wrote the book _After Virtue _, was a key contributor and proponent of modern virtue ethics, although MacIntyre supports a relativistic account of virtue based on cultural norms , not objective standards. Martha Nussbaum , a contemporary virtue ethicist, objects to MacIntyre's relativism, among that of others, and responds to relativist objections to form an objective account in her work "Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach". _Complete Conduct Principles for the 21st Century_ blended the Eastern virtue ethics and the Western virtue ethics, with some modifications to suit the 21st Century, and formed a part of contemporary virtue ethics.

HEDONISM

Main article: Hedonism

Hedonism posits that the principal ethic is maximizing pleasure and minimizing pain . There are several schools of Hedonist thought ranging from those advocating the indulgence of even momentary desires to those teaching a pursuit of spiritual bliss. In their consideration of consequences, they range from those advocating self-gratification regardless of the pain and expense to others, to those stating that the most ethical pursuit maximizes pleasure and happiness for the most people. :37

Cyrenaic Hedonism

Founded by Aristippus of Cyrene, Cyrenaics supported immediate gratification or pleasure. "Eat, drink and be merry, for tomorrow we die." Even fleeting desires should be indulged, for fear the opportunity should be forever lost. There was little to no concern with the future, the present dominating in the pursuit for immediate pleasure. Cyrenaic hedonism encouraged the pursuit of enjoyment and indulgence without hesitation, believing pleasure to be the only good. :37

Epicureanism

Main article: Epicureanism

Epicurean ethics is a hedonist form of virtue ethics. Epicurus "presented a sustained argument that pleasure, correctly understood, will coincide with virtue". He rejected the extremism of the Cyrenaics , believing some pleasures and indulgences to be detrimental to human beings. Epicureans observed that indiscriminate indulgence sometimes resulted in negative consequences. Some experiences were therefore rejected out of hand, and some unpleasant experiences endured in the present to ensure a better life in the future. To Epicurus the _summum bonum_, or greatest good, was prudence, exercised through moderation and caution. Excessive indulgence can be destructive to pleasure and can even lead to pain. For example, eating one food too often will cause a person to lose taste for it. Eating too much food at once will lead to discomfort and ill-health. Pain and fear were to be avoided. Living was essentially good, barring pain and illness. Death was not to be feared. Fear was considered the source of most unhappiness. Conquering the fear of death would naturally lead to a happier life. Epicurus reasoned if there was an afterlife and immortality, the fear of death was irrational. If there was no life after death, then the person would not be alive to suffer, fear or worry; he would be non-existent in death. It is irrational to fret over circumstances that do not exist, such as one's state in death in the absence of an afterlife. :37–38

STATE CONSEQUENTIALISM

Main article: State consequentialism

State consequentialism , also known as Mohist consequentialism, is an ethical theory that evaluates the moral worth of an action based on how much it contributes to the basic goods of a state. The _Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy _ describes Mohist consequentialism, dating back to the 5th century BC, as "a remarkably sophisticated version based on a plurality of intrinsic goods taken as constitutive of human welfare". Unlike utilitarianism, which views pleasure as a moral good, "the basic goods in Mohist consequentialist thinking are ... order, material wealth, and increase in population". During Mozi 's era, war and famines were common, and population growth was seen as a moral necessity for a harmonious society. The "material wealth" of Mohist consequentialism refers to basic needs like shelter and clothing, and the "order" of Mohist consequentialism refers to Mozi's stance against warfare and violence, which he viewed as pointless and a threat to social stability.

Stanford sinologist David Shepherd Nivison , in _The Cambridge History of Ancient China _, writes that the moral goods of Mohism "are interrelated: more basic wealth, then more reproduction; more people, then more production and wealth ... if people have plenty, they would be good, filial, kind, and so on unproblematically." The Mohists believed that morality is based on "promoting the benefit of all under heaven and eliminating harm to all under heaven". In contrast to Bentham's views, state consequentialism is not utilitarian because it is not hedonistic or individualistic. The importance of outcomes that are good for the community outweigh the importance of individual pleasure and pain.

CONSEQUENTIALISM/TELEOLOGY

Main article: Consequentialism See also: Ethical egoism

Consequentialism refers to moral theories that hold that the consequences of a particular action form the basis for any valid moral judgment about that action (or create a structure for judgment, see rule consequentialism ). Thus, from a consequentialist standpoint, a morally right action is one that produces a good outcome, or consequence. This view is often expressed as the aphorism _"The ends justify the means"_.

The term "consequentialism" was coined by G. E. M. Anscombe in her essay "Modern Moral Philosophy " in 1958, to describe what she saw as the central error of certain moral theories, such as those propounded by Mill and Sidgwick . Since then, the term has become common in English-language ethical theory.

The defining feature of consequentialist moral theories is the weight given to the consequences in evaluating the rightness and wrongness of actions. In consequentialist theories, the consequences of an action or rule generally outweigh other considerations. Apart from this basic outline, there is little else that can be unequivocally said about consequentialism as such. However, there are some questions that many consequentialist theories address:

* What sort of consequences count as good consequences? * Who is the primary beneficiary of moral action? * How are the consequences judged and who judges them?

One way to divide various consequentialisms is by the types of consequences that are taken to matter most, that is, which consequences count as good states of affairs. According to utilitarianism , a good action is one that results in an increase in a positive effect, and the best action is one that results in that effect for the greatest number. Closely related is eudaimonic consequentialism, according to which a full, flourishing life, which may or may not be the same as enjoying a great deal of pleasure, is the ultimate aim. Similarly, one might adopt an aesthetic consequentialism, in which the ultimate aim is to produce beauty. However, one might fix on non-psychological goods as the relevant effect. Thus, one might pursue an increase in material equality or political liberty instead of something like the more ephemeral "pleasure". Other theories adopt a package of several goods, all to be promoted equally. Whether a particular consequentialist theory focuses on a single good or many, conflicts and tensions between different good states of affairs are to be expected and must be adjudicated.

Utilitarianism

Main article: Utilitarianism Jeremy Bentham John Stuart Mill

Utilitarianism is an ethical theory that argues the proper course of action is one that maximizes a positive effect, such as "happiness", "welfare", or the ability to live according to personal preferences. Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill are influential proponents of this school of thought. In _A Fragment on Government_ Bentham says 'it is the greatest happiness of the greatest number that is the measure of right and wrong' and describes this as a fundamental axiom . In _An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation_ he talks of 'the principle of utility' but later prefers "the greatest happiness principle".

Utilitarianism is the paradigmatic example of a consequentialist moral theory. This form of utilitarianism holds that the morally correct action is the one that produces the best outcome for all people affected by the action. John Stuart Mill , in his exposition of utilitarianism, proposed a hierarchy of pleasures, meaning that the pursuit of certain kinds of pleasure is more highly valued than the pursuit of other pleasures. Other noteworthy proponents of utilitarianism are neuroscientist Sam Harris , author of The Moral Landscape , and moral philosopher Peter Singer , author of, amongst other works, Practical Ethics .

There are two types of utilitarianism, act utilitarianism and rule utilitarianism . In act utilitarianism the principle of utility is applied directly to each alternative act in a situation of choice. The right act is then defined as the one which brings about the best results (or the least amount of bad results). In rule utilitarianism the principle of utility is used to determine the validity of rules of conduct (moral principles). A rule like promise-keeping is established by looking at the consequences of a world in which people broke promises at will and a world in which promises were binding. Right and wrong are then defined as the following or breaking of rules which are sanctioned by their utilitarian value.

DEONTOLOGY

Main article: Deontological ethics Immanuel Kant

Deontological ethics or deontology (from Greek δέον, _deon_, "obligation, duty"; and -λογία, _-logia _) is an approach to ethics that determines goodness or rightness from examining acts , or the rules and duties that the person doing the act strove to fulfill. This is in contrast to consequentialism , in which rightness is based on the consequences of an act, and not the act by itself. In deontology, an act may be considered right even if the act produces a bad consequence, if it follows the _rule_ that "one should do unto others as they would have done unto them", and even if the person who does the act lacks virtue and had a bad intention in doing the act. According to deontology, people have a _duty_ to act in a way that does those things that are inherently good as acts ("truth-telling" for example), or follow an objectively obligatory rule (as in rule utilitarianism ). For deontologists, the ends or consequences of people's actions are not important in and of themselves, and people's intentions are not important in and of themselves.

Immanuel Kant's theory of ethics is considered deontological for several different reasons. First, Kant argues that to act in the morally right way, people must act from duty (_deon_). Second, Kant argued that it was not the consequences of actions that make them right or wrong but the motives (maxime) of the person who carries out the action. Kant's argument that to act in the morally right way, one must act from duty, begins with an argument that the highest good must be both good in itself, and good without qualification. Something is 'good in itself' when it is intrinsically good , and 'good without qualification' when the addition of that thing never makes a situation ethically worse. Kant then argues that those things that are usually thought to be good, such as intelligence , perseverance and pleasure , fail to be either intrinsically good or good without qualification. Pleasure, for example, appears to not be good without qualification, because when people take pleasure in watching someone suffer, they make the situation ethically worse. He concludes that there is only one thing that is truly good:

Nothing in the world—indeed nothing even beyond the world—can possibly be conceived which could be called good without qualification except a _good will_.

PRAGMATIC ETHICS

Main article: Pragmatic ethics

Associated with the pragmatists , Charles Sanders Peirce , William James , and especially John Dewey , pragmatic ethics holds that moral correctness evolves similarly to scientific knowledge: socially over the course of many lifetimes. Thus, we should prioritize social reform over attempts to account for consequences, individual virtue or duty (although these may be worthwhile attempts, if social reform is provided for).

ETHICS OF CARE

Main article: Ethics of care

Care ethics contrasts with more well-known ethical models, such as consequentialist theories (e.g. utilitarianism) and deontological theories (e.g. Kantian ethics) in that it seeks to incorporate traditionally feminized virtues and values which, proponents of care ethics contend, are absent in such traditional models of ethics. These values include the importance of empathetic relationships and compassion.

Care-focused feminism is a branch of feminist thought, informed primarily by ethics of care as developed by Carol Gilligan and Nel Noddings . This body of theory is critical of how caring is socially assigned to women, and consequently devalued. “Care-focused feminists regard women’s capacity for care as a human strength” which can and should be taught to and expected of men as well as women. Noddings proposes that ethical caring has the potential to be a more concrete evaluative model of moral dilemma, than an ethic of justice. Noddings’ care-focused feminism requires practical application of relational ethics , predicated on an ethic of care.

ROLE ETHICS

Main article: Role ethics

Role ethics is an ethical theory based on family roles. Unlike virtue ethics , role ethics is not individualistic. Morality is derived from a person's relationship with their community. Confucian ethics is an example of role ethics though this is not straightforwardly uncontested. Confucian roles center around the concept of filial piety or _xiao_, a respect for family members. According to Roger Ames and Henry Rosemont, "Confucian normativity is defined by living one's family roles to maximum effect." Morality is determined through a person's fulfillment of a role, such as that of a parent or a child. Confucian roles are not rational , and originate through the _xin_, or human emotions.

ANARCHIST ETHICS

Main article: Anarchism

Anarchist ethics is an ethical theory based on the studies of anarchist thinkers. The biggest contributor to the anarchist ethics is the Russian zoologist, geographer, economist and political activist Peter Kropotkin . The anarchist ethics is a big and vague field which can depend upon different historical situations and different anarchist thinkers, but as Peter Kropotkin explains, "any “bourgeois” or “proletarian” ethics rests, after all, on the common basis, on the common ethnological foundation, which at times exerts a very strong influence on the principles of the class or group morality." Still, most of the anarchist ethics schools are based on three fundamental ideas, which are: "solidarity, equality and justice". Kropotkin argues that Ethics is evolutionary and is inherited as a sort of a social instinct through History, and by so, he rejects any religious and transcendental explanation of ethics. Kropotkin suggests that the principle of equality which lies at the basis of anarchism is the same as the Golden rule :

This principle of treating others as one wishes to be treated oneself, what is it but the very same principle as equality, the fundamental principle of anarchism? And how can any one manage to believe himself an anarchist unless he practices it? We do not wish to be ruled. And by this very fact, do we not declare that we ourselves wish to rule nobody? We do not wish to be deceived, we wish always to be told nothing but the truth. And by this very fact, do we not de- clare that we ourselves do not wish to deceive anybody, that we promise to always tell the truth, nothing but the truth, the whole truth? We do not wish to have the fruits of our labor stolen from us. And by that very fact, do we not declare that we respect the fruits of others' labor? By what right indeed can we demand that we should be treated in one fashion, reserving it to ourselves to treat others in a fashion entirely different? Our sense of equality revolts at such an idea.

POSTMODERN ETHICS

Main article: Postmodernism

_ This article or section POSSIBLY CONTAINS PREVIOUSLY UNPUBLISHED SYNTHESIS OF PUBLISHED MATERIAL THAT CONVEYS IDEAS NOT ATTRIBUTABLE TO THE ORIGINAL SOURCES. Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page . (July 2009)_ _(Learn how and when to remove this template message )_

The 20th century saw a remarkable expansion and evolution of critical theory, following on earlier Marxist Theory efforts to locate individuals within larger structural frameworks of ideology and action.

Antihumanists such as Louis Althusser and Michel Foucault and structuralists such as Roland Barthes challenged the possibilities of individual agency and the coherence of the notion of the 'individual' itself. As critical theory developed in the later 20th century, post-structuralism sought to problematize human relationships to knowledge and 'objective' reality. Jacques Derrida argued that access to meaning and the 'real' was always deferred, and sought to demonstrate via recourse to the linguistic realm that "there is nothing outside context" ("_il n'y a pas de hors-texte_" is often mistranslated as "there is nothing outside the text"); at the same time, Jean Baudrillard theorised that signs and symbols or simulacra mask reality (and eventually the absence of reality itself), particularly in the consumer world.

Post-structuralism and postmodernism argue that ethics must study the complex and relational conditions of actions. A simple alignment of ideas of right and particular acts is not possible. There will always be an ethical remainder that cannot be taken into account or often even recognized. Such theorists find narrative (or, following Nietzsche and Foucault, genealogy ) to be a helpful tool for understanding ethics because narrative is always about particular lived experiences in all their complexity rather than the assignment of an idea or norm to separate and individuated actions.

Zygmunt Bauman says postmodernity is best described as modernity without illusion, the illusion being the belief that humanity can be repaired by some ethic principle. Postmodernity can be seen in this light as accepting the messy nature of humanity as unchangeable.

David Couzens Hoy states that Emmanuel Levinas 's writings on the face of the Other and Derrida 's meditations on the relevance of death to ethics are signs of the "ethical turn" in Continental philosophy that occurred in the 1980s and 1990s. Hoy describes post-critique ethics as the "obligations that present themselves as necessarily to be fulfilled but are neither forced on one or are enforceable" (2004, p. 103).

Hoy's post-critique model uses the term _ethical resistance_. Examples of this would be an individual's resistance to consumerism in a retreat to a simpler but perhaps harder lifestyle, or an individual's resistance to a terminal illness. Hoy describes Levinas's account as "not the attempt to use power against itself, or to mobilize sectors of the population to exert their political power; the ethical resistance is instead the resistance of the powerless"(2004, p. 8).

Hoy concludes that

The ethical resistance of the powerless others to our capacity to exert power over them is therefore what imposes unenforceable obligations on us. The obligations are unenforceable precisely because of the other's lack of power. That actions are at once obligatory and at the same time unenforceable is what put them in the category of the ethical. Obligations that were enforced would, by the virtue of the force behind them, not be freely undertaken and would not be in the realm of the ethical. (2004, p.184)

In present-day terms the powerless may include the unborn, the terminally sick, the aged, the insane, and non-human animals. It is in these areas that ethical action in Hoy's sense will apply. Until legislation or the state apparatus enforces a moral order that addresses the causes of resistance these issues will remain in the ethical realm. For example, should animal experimentation become illegal in a society, it will no longer be an ethical issue on Hoy's definition. Likewise one hundred and fifty years ago, not having a black slave in America would have been an ethical choice. This later issue has been absorbed into the fabric of an enforceable social order and is therefore no longer an ethical issue in Hoy's sense.

APPLIED ETHICS

Main article: Applied ethics

Applied ethics is a discipline of philosophy that attempts to apply ethical theory to real-life situations. The discipline has many specialized fields, such as engineering ethics , bioethics , geoethics , public service ethics and business ethics .

SPECIFIC QUESTIONS

Applied ethics is used in some aspects of determining public policy, as well as by individuals facing difficult decisions. The sort of questions addressed by applied ethics include: "Is getting an abortion immoral?" "Is euthanasia immoral?" "Is affirmative action right or wrong?" "What are human rights, and how do we determine them?" "Do animals have rights as well?" and "Do individuals have the right of self determination?"

A more specific question could be: "If someone else can make better out of his/her life than I can, is it then moral to sacrifice myself for them if needed?" Without these questions there is no clear fulcrum on which to balance law, politics, and the practice of arbitration—in fact, no common assumptions of all participants—so the ability to formulate the questions are prior to rights balancing. But not all questions studied in applied ethics concern public policy. For example, making ethical judgments regarding questions such as, "Is lying always wrong?" and, "If not, when is it permissible?" is prior to any etiquette.

People in-general are more comfortable with dichotomies (two opposites). However, in ethics the issues are most often multifaceted and the best proposed actions address many different areas concurrently. In ethical decisions the answer is almost never a "yes or no", "right or wrong" statement. Many buttons are pushed so that the overall condition is improved and not to the benefit of any particular faction.

PARTICULAR FIELDS OF APPLICATION

Bioethics

Main article: Bioethics

Bioethics is the study of controversial ethics brought about by advances in biology and medicine . Bioethicists are concerned with the ethical questions that arise in the relationships among life sciences , biotechnology , medicine , politics , law , and philosophy . It also includes the study of the more commonplace questions of values ("the ethics of the ordinary" ) that arise in primary care and other branches of medicine.

Bioethics also needs to address emerging biotechnologies that affect basic biology and future humans. These developments include cloning , gene therapy , human genetic engineering , astroethics and life in space, and manipulation of basic biology through altered DNA, RNA and proteins,e.g.- "three parent baby,where baby is born from genetically modified embryos, would have DNA from a mother, a father and from a female donor. Correspondingly, new bioethics also need to address life at its core. For example, biotic ethics value organic gene/protein life itself and seek to propagate it. With such life-centered principles, ethics may secure a cosmological future for life.

Business Ethics

Main article: Business ethics

Business ethics (also corporate ethics) is a form of applied ethics or professional ethics that examines ethical principles and moral or ethical problems that arise in a business environment, including fields like medical ethics . It applies to all aspects of business conduct and is relevant to the conduct of individuals and entire organizations.

Business ethics has both normative and descriptive dimensions. As a corporate practice and a career specialization, the field is primarily normative. Academics attempting to understand business behavior employ descriptive methods. The range and quantity of business ethical issues reflects the interaction of profit-maximizing behavior with non-economic concerns. Interest in business ethics accelerated dramatically during the 1980s and 1990s, both within major corporations and within academia. For example, today most major corporations promote their commitment to non-economic values under headings such as ethics codes and social responsibility charters. Adam Smith said, "People of the same trade seldom meet together, even for merriment and diversion, but the conversation ends in a conspiracy against the public, or in some contrivance to raise prices." Governments use laws and regulations to point business behavior in what they perceive to be beneficial directions. Ethics implicitly regulates areas and details of behavior that lie beyond governmental control. The emergence of large corporations with limited relationships and sensitivity to the communities in which they operate accelerated the development of formal ethics regimes.

Machine Ethics

Main article: Machine ethics

In _Moral Machines: Teaching Robots Right from Wrong_, Wendell Wallach and Colin Allen conclude that issues in machine ethics will likely drive advancement in understanding of human ethics by forcing us to address gaps in modern normative theory and by providing a platform for experimental investigation. The effort to actually program a machine or artificial agent to behave as though instilled with a sense of ethics requires new specificity in our normative theories, especially regarding aspects customarily considered common-sense. For example, machines, unlike humans, can support a wide selection of learning algorithms , and controversy has arisen over the relative ethical merits of these options. This may reopen classic debates of normative ethics framed in new (highly technical) terms.

Military Ethics

See also: Geneva Conventions and Nuremberg Principles

Military ethics are concerned with questions regarding the application of force and the ethos of the soldier and are often understood as applied professional ethics. Just war theory is generally seen to set the background terms of military ethics. However individual countries and traditions have different fields of attention.

Military ethics involves multiple subareas, including the following among others:

* what, if any, should be the laws of war. * justification for the initiation of military force. * decisions about who may be targeted in warfare. * decisions on choice of weaponry, and what collateral effects such weaponry may have. * standards for handling military prisoners. * methods of dealing with violations of the laws of war.

Political Ethics

Main article: Political ethics

Political ethics (also known as political morality or public ethics) is the practice of making moral judgements about political action and political agents.

Public Sector Ethics

Main article: Public sector ethics

Public sector ethics is a set of principles that guide public officials in their service to their constituents, including their decision-making on behalf of their constituents. Fundamental to the concept of public sector ethics is the notion that decisions and actions are based on what best serves the public's interests, as opposed to the official's personal interests (including financial interests) or self-serving political interests.

Publication Ethics

Publication ethics is the set of principles that guide the writing and publishing process for all professional publications. In order to follow the set of principles, authors should verify that the publication does not contain plagiarism or publication bias . As a way to avoid misconduct in research these principles can also be applied to experiments which are referenced or analyzed in publications by ensuring the data is recorded, honestly and accurately.

Plagiarism is the failure to give credit to another author’s work or ideas, when it is used in the publication. It is the obligation of the editor of the journal to ensure the article does not contain any plagiarism before it is published. If a publication which has already been published is proven to contain plagiarism, then the editor of the journal can proceed to have the article retracted.

Publication bias occurs when the publication is one-sided or "prejudiced against results". In best practice, an author should try to include information from all parties involved, or affected by the topic. If an author is prejudiced against certain results, than it can "lead to erroneous conclusions being drawn".

Misconduct in research can occur when information from an experiment is falsely recorded or altered. Falsely recorded information occurs when the researcher "fakes" information or data, which was not used when conducting the actual experiment. By faking the data, the researcher can alter the results from the experiment to better fit the hypothesis they originally predicted. When conducting medical research, it is important to honor the healthcare rights of a patient by protecting their anonymity in the publication. Respect for autonomy – Is a principle which states that decision-making should concentrate on allowing individuals to be autonomous; they should be able to make decisions that apply to their own lives. This means that individuals should have control of their lives. Justice- is the principle that states that the decision makers need to focus on actions that are fair to those affected. Ethical decisions need to be consistent with the ethical theory. There are cases where the management has made decisions that seem to be unfair to the employees, shareholders, and other stakeholders (Solomon, 1992, pp49). Such decisions are unethical.

Relational Ethics

Relational ethics are related to an ethics of care . :62–63 They are used in qualitative research, especially ethnography and autoethnography. Researchers who employ relational ethics value and respect the connection between themselves and the people they study, and "between researchers and the communities in which they live and work" (Ellis, 2007, p. 4). Relational ethics also help researchers understand difficult issues such as conducting research on intimate others that have died and developing friendships with their participants. Relational ethics in close personal relationships form a central concept of contextual therapy .

Animal Ethics

Main article: Animal ethics

Animal ethics is a term used in academia to describe human-animal relationships and how animals ought to be treated. The subject matter includes animal rights , animal welfare , animal law , speciesism , animal cognition , wildlife conservation , the moral status of nonhuman animals, the concept of nonhuman personhood , human exceptionalism , the history of animal use, and theories of justice .

MORAL PSYCHOLOGY

Main article: Moral psychology

MORAL PSYCHOLOGY is a field of study that began as an issue in philosophy and that is now properly considered part of the discipline of psychology . Some use the term "moral psychology" relatively narrowly to refer to the study of moral development . However, others tend to use the term more broadly to include any topics at the intersection of ethics and psychology (and philosophy of mind ). Such topics are ones that involve the mind and are relevant to moral issues. Some of the main topics of the field are moral responsibility , moral development, moral character (especially as related to virtue ethics ), altruism , psychological egoism , moral luck , and moral disagreement.

EVOLUTIONARY ETHICS

Main article: Evolutionary ethics See also: Evolution of morality

Evolutionary ethics concerns approaches to ethics (morality) based on the role of evolution in shaping human psychology and behavior. Such approaches may be based in scientific fields such as evolutionary psychology or sociobiology , with a focus on understanding and explaining observed ethical preferences and choices.

DESCRIPTIVE ETHICS

Main article: Descriptive ethics

Descriptive ethics is on the less philosophical end of the spectrum, since it seeks to gather particular information about how people live and draw general conclusions based on observed patterns. Abstract and theoretical questions that are more clearly philosophical—such as, "Is ethical knowledge possible?"—are not central to descriptive ethics. Descriptive ethics offers a value-free approach to ethics, which defines it as a social science rather than a humanity . Its examination of ethics doesn't start with a preconceived theory, but rather investigates observations of actual choices made by moral agents in practice. Some philosophers rely on descriptive ethics and choices made and unchallenged by a society or culture to derive categories, which typically vary by context. This can lead to situational ethics and situated ethics . These philosophers often view aesthetics , etiquette , and arbitration as more fundamental, percolating "bottom up" to imply the existence of, rather than explicitly prescribe, theories of value or of conduct. The study of descriptive ethics may include examinations of the following:

* Ethical codes applied by various groups. Some consider aesthetics itself the basis of ethics—and a personal moral core developed through art and storytelling as very influential in one's later ethical choices. * Informal theories of etiquette that tend to be less rigorous and more situational. Some consider etiquette a simple negative ethics, i.e., where can one evade an uncomfortable truth without doing wrong? One notable advocate of this view is Judith Martin ("Miss Manners"). According to this view, ethics is more a summary of common sense social decisions. * Practices in arbitration and law , e.g., the claim that ethics itself is a matter of balancing "right versus right", i.e., putting priorities on two things that are both right, but that must be traded off carefully in each situation. * Observed choices made by ordinary people, without expert aid or advice, who vote , buy, and decide what is worth valuing. This is a major concern of sociology, political science , and economics .

SEE ALSO

* Ethics portal

* Contemporary ethics * Corporate social responsibility * Declaration of Geneva * Declaration of Helsinki * Deductive reasoning * Descriptive ethics * Dharma * Ethical movement * Ethics paper * Index of ethics articles —alphabetical list of ethics-related articles * Moral psychology * Outline of ethics —list of ethics-related articles, arranged by sub-topic * Practical philosophy * Science of morality * Theory of justification

NOTES

* ^ _A_ _B_ _C_ _Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy_ "Ethics" * ^ _ Random House Unabridged Dictionary _: Entry on Axiology. * ^ Kidder, Rushworth (2003). _How Good People Make Tough Choices: Resolving the Diliemmas of Ethical Living_. New York: Harper Collins . p. 63. ISBN 0-688-17590-2 . * ^ _A_ _B_ Paul, Richard; Elder, Linda (2006). _The Miniature Guide to Understanding the Foundations of Ethical Reasoning_. United States: Foundation for Critical Thinking Free Press. p. np. ISBN 0-944583-17-2 . * ^ John Deigh in Robert Audi (ed), _The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy_, 1995. * ^ "Definition of ethic by Merriam Webster". Merriam Webster. Retrieved October 4, 2015. * ^ Williams, Bernard. _ Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy_. p. 2.

* ^ Williams, Bernard. _ Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy_. p. 1.

* ^ "Are We Professionals? A Critical Look at the Social Role of Bioethicists.". _Daedalus_. 1999. pp. 253–274. * ^ David Tanguay (January 24, 2014). " Buddha and Socrates share Common ground". Soul of Wit. Archived from the original on July 22, 2014. Retrieved July 22, 2014. * ^ _An Intermediate Greek-English Lexicon_. 1889. * ^ _A_ _B_ _C_ "What is ethics?". BBC . Archived from the original on October 28, 2013. Retrieved July 22, 2014. * ^ http://www.iep.utm.edu/non-cogn/ * ^ Miller, C. (2009). The Conditions of Moral Realism. The Journal of Philosophical Research, 34, 123-155. * ^ Cavalier, Robert. "Meta-ethics, Normative Ethics, and Applied Ethics". _Online Guide to Ethics and Moral Philosophy_. Archived from the original on November 12, 2013. Retrieved February 26, 2014. * ^ _A_ _B_ _C_ _D_ _E_ _F_ _G_ William S. Sahakian; Mabel Lewis Sahakian (1966). _Ideas of the Great Philosophers_. Barnes & Noble. ISBN 978-1-56619-271-2 . * ^ _A_ _B_ Professor Michiel S. S. De De Vries; Professor Pan Suk Kim (October 28, 2011). _Value and Virtue in Public Administration: A Comparative Perspective_. Palgrave Macmillan. p. 42. ISBN 978-0-230-35709-9 . * ^ Nussbaum, Martha (1987). _Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach_. * ^ _A_ _B_ John Newton, Ph.D., _Complete Conduct Principles for the 21st Century_ (2000). ISBN 0-9673705-7-4 . * ^ Ancient Ethical Theory, _Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy _. * ^ _A_ _B_ Ivanhoe, P.J.; Van Norden, Bryan William (2005). _Readings in classical Chinese philosophy_. Hackett Publishing . p. 60. ISBN 978-0-87220-780-6 . he advocated a form of state consequentialism, which sought to maximize three basic goods: the wealth, order, and population of the state * ^ Fraser, Chris, "Mohism", _The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy _, Edward N. Zalta. * ^ _A_ _B_ Loewe, Michael; Shaughnessy, Edward L. (1999). _The Cambridge History of Ancient China _. Cambridge University Press . p. 761. ISBN 978-0-521-47030-8 . * ^ Van Norden, Bryan W. (2011). _Introduction to Classical Chinese Philosophy_. Hackett Publishing . p. 52. ISBN 978-1-60384-468-0 . * ^ Jay L. Garfield; William Edelglass (June 9, 2011). _The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy_. Oxford University Press. p. 62. ISBN 978-0-19-532899-8 . The goods that serve as criteria of morality are collective or public, in contrast, for instance, to individual happiness or well-being * ^ Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). "Modern Moral Philosophy". _ Philosophy _. 1958. 33 (124): 1–19. doi :10.1017/S0031819100037943 . * ^ Mackie, J. L. (1990) . _Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong_. London: Penguin. ISBN 0-14-013558-8 . * ^ Baqgini, Julian ; Fosl, Peter S. (2007). _The Ethics Toolkit: A Compendium of Ethical Concepts and Methods_. Malden: Blackwell. pp. 57–58. ISBN 978-1-4051-3230-5 . * ^ Bentham, Jeremy (2001). _The Works of Jeremy Bentham: Published under the Superintendence of His Executor, John Bowring. Volume 1_. Adamant Media Corporation. p. 18. ISBN 978-1-4021-6393-7 . * ^ Mill, John Stuart, Utilitarianism (Project Gutenberg online edition) * ^ Mill, John Stuart (1998). _Utilitarianism_. Oxford: Oxford University Press . ISBN 978-0-19-875163-2 . * ^ Department of Philosophy, CMU * ^ Stanford.edu * ^ Olson, Robert G. 1967. 'Deontological Ethics'. In Paul Edwards (ed.) _The Encyclopedia of Philosophy_. London: Collier Macmillan : 343. * ^ http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-virtue/ * ^ Orend, Brian. 2000. _War and International Justice: A Kantian Perspective_. West Waterloo, Ontario: Wilfrid Laurier University Press : 19. * ^ Kelly, Eugene. 2006. _The Basics of Western Philosophy_. Greenwood Press : 160. * ^ Kant, Immanuel. 1780. 'Preface'. In _The Metaphysical Elements of Ethics_. Translated by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott * ^ _A_ _B_ Kant, Immanuel. 1785. 'First Section: Transition from the Common Rational Knowledge of Morals to the Philosophical', Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals . * ^ Lafollette, Hugh, ed. (February 2000). _The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory_. Blackwell Philosophy Guides (1 ed.). Wiley-Blackwell . ISBN 978-0-631-20119-9 . * ^ Tong, Rosemarie; Williams, Nancy (May 4, 2009). "Feminist Ethics". _Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy_. The Metaphysics Research Lab. Retrieved January 6, 2017. * ^ Noddings, Nel: Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education, page 3-4. University of California Press, Berkeley, 1984. * ^ Noddings, Nel: Women and Evil, page 222. University of California Press, Berkeley, 1989. * ^ _A_ _B_ Roger T. Ames (April 30, 2011). _Confucian Role Ethics: A Vocabulary_. University of Hawaiʻi Press. ISBN 978-0-8248-3576-7 . * ^ _A_ _B_ Chris Fraser; Dan Robins; Timothy O'Leary (May 1, 2011). _ Ethics in Early China: An Anthology_. Hong Kong University Press. pp. 17–35. ISBN 978-988-8028-93-1 . * ^ Sim, May, 2015, “Why Confucius’ Ethics is a Virtue Ethics”, in Besser-Jones and Slote (2015), pp. 63–76 * ^ Wonsuk Chang; Leah Kalmanson (November 8, 2010). _Confucianism in Context: Classic Philosophy and Contemporary Issues, East Asia and Beyond_. SUNY Press . p. 68. ISBN 978-1-4384-3191-8 . * ^ "Ethics: Origin and Development" by Pëtr Kropotkin * ^ "Anarchist morality", chapter VI, Pëtr Kropotkin * ^ "Astroethics". Archived from the original on October 23, 2013. Retrieved December 21, 2005. * ^ Freemont, P. F.; Kitney, R. I. (2012). _Synthetic Biology_. New Jersey: World Scientific . ISBN 978-1-84816-862-6 . * ^ Mautner, Michael N. (2009). "Life-centered ethics, and the human future in space" (PDF). _ Bioethics _. 23: 433–440. PMID 19077128 . doi :10.1111/j.1467-8519.2008.00688.x . * ^ Mautner, Michael N. (2000). _Seeding the Universe with Life: Securing Our Cosmological Future_ (PDF ). Washington D. C.: Legacy Books (www.amazon.com). ISBN 0-476-00330-X . * ^ Smith, A (1776/1952). _An Inquiry Into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations_. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press, p. 55. * ^ Berle, A. A., & Means, G. C. (1932). The Modern Corporation and Private Property. New Jersey: Transaction Publishers. In this book, Berle and Means observe, "Corporations have ceased to be merely legal devices through which the private business transactions of individuals may be carried on. Though still much used for this purpose, the corporate form has acquired a much larger significance. The corporation has, in fact, become both a method of property tenure and a means of organizing economic life. Grown to tremendous proportions, there may be said to have evolved a 'corporate system'—as there once was a feudal system—which has attracted to itself a combination of attributes and powers, and has attained a degree of prominence entitling it to be dealt with as a major social institution. ... We are examining this institution probably before it has attained its zenith. Spectacular as its rise has been, every indication seems to be that the system will move forward to proportions which stagger imagination today ... They have placed the community in a position to demand that the modern corporation serve not only the owners ... but all society." p. 1. * ^ Jones, Parker Allen, Colin (November 2008). _Moral Machines: Teaching Robots Right from Wrong_. USA: Oxford University Press . ISBN 978-0-19-537404-9 . * ^ Cook, Martin L.; Syse, Henrik (2010). "What Should We Mean by 'Military Ethics'?". _Journal of Military Ethics_. 9 (2). p. 122. * ^ Goffi, Emmanuel (2011). _Les Armée Françaises Face à la Morale_ (in French). France: L'Harmattan. ISBN 978-2296542495 . * ^ Thompson, Dennis F. "Political Ethics". _International Encyclopedia of Ethics_, ed. Hugh LaFollette (Blackwell Publishing, 2012). * ^ See, for example, work of Institute for Local Government, at www.ca-ilg.org/trust. * ^ _A_ _B_ Morton, Neil (October 2009). "Publication ethics". _Pediatric Anesthesia_. 19 (10): 1011–1013. doi :10.1111/j.1460-9592.2009.03086.x . * ^ Wager, E; Fiack, S; Graf, C; Robinson, A; Rowlands, I (31 March 2009). "Science journal editors\' views on publication ethics: results of an international survey". _Journal of Medical Ethics_. 35: 348–353. doi :10.1136/jme.2008.028324 . * ^ Scollon, Ron (June 1999). "Plagiarism". _Journal of Linguistic Anthropology_. 9: 188–190. JSTOR 43102462 . doi :10.1525/jlin.1999.9.1-2.188 . * ^ Wager, Elizabeth; Williams, Peter (September 2011). "Why and how do journals retract articles? An analysis of Medline retractions 1988—2008". _Journal of Medical Ethics_. 37 (9): 567–570. JSTOR 23034717 . doi :10.1136/jme.2010.040964 . * ^ Sanjeev, Handa (2008). " Plagiarism and publication ethics: Dos and don\'ts". _Indian Journal of Dermatology Venereology and Leprology_. 74 (4): 301–303. * ^ Sigelman, Lee (2000). "Publication Bias Reconsidered". _Political Analysis_. 8 (2): 201–210. JSTOR 25791607 . doi :10.1093/oxfordjournals.pan.a029813 . * ^ Peters, Jamie L.; Sutton, Alex J.; Jones, David R.; Abrams, Keith R.; Rushton, Lesley; Moreno, Santiago G. (July 2010). "Assessing publication bias in meta-analysis in the presence of between-study heterogeneity". _Journal of the Royal Statistical Society. Series A (Statistics in Society)_. 173 (3): 575–591. doi :10.1111/j.1467-985x.2009.00629.x . * ^ _A_ _B_ Smith, Richard (July 26, 1997). "Misconduct in Research: Editors Respond: The Committee on Publication Ethics (COPE) Is Formed". _British Medical Journal_. 315 (7102): 201–202. JSTOR 25175246 . doi :10.1136/bmj.315.7102.201 . * ^ Carol GILLIGAN (June 30, 2009). _IN A DIFFERENT VOICE_. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03761-8 . * ^ Ellis, C. (2007). Telling secrets, revealing lives: Relational ethics in research with intimate others. _Qualitative Inquiry, 13,_ 3-29. * ^ Ellis, C. (1986). _Fisher folk. Two communities on Chesapeake Bay._ Lexington: University Press of Kentucky . * ^ Ellis, C. (1995)._Final negotiations: A story of love, loss, and chronic illness._ Philadelphia: Temple University Press . * ^ See, for example, Lapsley (2006) and "moral psychology" (2007). * ^ See, for example, Doris & Stich (2008) and Wallace (2007). Wallace writes: " Moral psychology is the study of morality in its psychological dimensions" (p. 86). * ^ See Doris & Stich (2008), §1. * ^ Doris Schroeder. "Evolutionary Ethics". Archived from the original on October 7, 2013. Retrieved January 5, 2010.

REFERENCES

* Hoy, D. (2005). _Critical Resistance from Poststructuralism to Postcritique_. Massachusetts Institute of Technology , Cambridge, Massachusetts. * Lyon, D. (1999). _Postmodernity_ (2nd ed.). Open University Press , Buckingham. * Singer, P. (2000). _Writings on an Ethical Life_. Harper Collins Publishers , London.

FURTHER READING

* Aristotle , _ Nicomachean Ethics _ * The London Philosophy Study Guide offers many suggestions on what to read, depending on the student's familiarity with the subject: Ethics * _ Encyclopedia of Ethics _. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, editors. Second edition in three volumes. New York: Routledge, 2002. A scholarly encyclopedia with over 500 signed, peer-reviewed articles, mostly on topics and figures of, or of special interest in, Western philosophy . * Azurmendi, J. 1998: "The violence and the search for new values" in _Euskal Herria krisian_, (Elkar, 1999), pp. 11–116. ISBN 84-8331-572-6 * Blackburn, S. (2001). _Being good: A short introduction to ethics_. Oxford: Oxford University Press. * De Finance, Joseph, _An Ethical Inquiry_, Rome, Editrice Pontificia Università Gregoriana, 1991. * De La Torre, Miguel A. , "Doing Christian Ethics from the Margins", Orbis Books, 2004. * Derrida, J. 1995, _The Gift of Death_, translated by David Wills, University of Chicago Press , Chicago. * Fagothey, Austin, _Right and Reason_, Tan Books & Publishers, Rockford, Illinois, 2000. * Levinas, E. 1969, _Totality and infinity, an essay on exteriority_, translated by Alphonso Lingis, Duquesne University Press , Pittsburgh. * Perle, Stephen (March 11, 2004). " Morality and Ethics: An Introduction". Retrieved February 13, 2007. , Butchvarov, Panayot . Skepticism in Ethics (1989). * Jadranka Skorin-Kapov , _The Intertwining of Aesthetics and Ethics: Exceeding of Expectations, Ecstasy, Sublimity_. Lexington Books, 2016. ISBN 978-1-4985-2456-8 * Solomon, R.C. , _ Morality and the Good Life: An Introduction to Ethics Through Classical Sources_, New York: McGraw-Hill Book Company , 1984. * Vendemiati, Aldo, _In the First Person, An Outline of General Ethics_, Rome, Urbaniana University Press, 2004. * John Paul II, Encyclical Letter _Veritatis Splendor_, August 6, 1993. * D'Urance, Michel, _Jalons pour une éthique rebelle_, Aléthéia, Paris, 2005. * John Newton, Ph.D. _Complete Conduct Principles for the 21st Century_, 2000. ISBN 0-9673705-7-4 . * Guy Cools padding:0.75em; background:#f9f9f9;"> Find more aboutETHICSat's sister projects

* Definitions from Wiktionary * Media from Commons * Quotations from Wikiquote * Texts from Wikisource * Textbooks from Wikibooks * Learning resources from Wikiversity * Data from Wikidata

Library resources about ETHICS -------------------------

* Resources in your library * Resources in other libraries

* Meta- Ethics at PhilPapers * Normative Ethics at PhilPapers * Applied Ethics at PhilPapers * Ethics at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project * "Ethics". _Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy _. * An Introduction to Ethics by Paul Newall, aimed at beginners. * _Ethics_, 2d ed., 1973. by William Frankena * Ethics Bites, Open University podcast series podcast exploring ethical dilemmas in everyday life. * National Reference Center for Bioethics Literature World's largest library for ethical issues in medicine and biomedical research * Ethics entry in Encyclopædia Britannica by Peter Singer * The Philosophy of Ethics on Philosophy Archive * Kirby Laing Institute for Christian Ethics Resources, events, and research on a range of ethical subjects from a Christian perspective. * Basic principle of ethics summary talk * International Association for Geoethics (IAGETH) * International Association for Promoting Geoethics (IAPG) * Markkula Center for Applied Ethics at Santa Clara University Resources for analyzing real-world ethical issues and tools to address them.

* v * t * e

Philosophy

BRANCHES

TRADITIONAL

* Metaphysics

* Ontology

* Epistemology * Logic * Ethics * Aesthetics

PHILOSOPHY OF

* Action

* Art

* Culture * Design * Music * Film

* Business * Color * Cosmos * Dialogue * Education * Environment * Futility * Happiness * Healthcare * History * Human nature * Humor * Feminism * Language * Life * Literature * Mathematics

* Mind

* Pain * Psychology

* Philosophy of psychiatry * Philosophy of perception * Philosophy * Religion

* Science

* Physics * Chemistry * Biology * Geography

* Sexuality

* Social science

* Culture * Economics * Justice * Law * Politics * Society

* Space and time * Sport

* Technology

* Artificial intelligence * Computer science * Engineering * Information

* War

SCHOOLS OF THOUGHT

BY ERA

* Ancient

* Western

* Medieval * Renaissance * Early modern * Modern * Contemporary

ANCIENT

CHINESE

* Agriculturalism * Confucianism * Legalism * Logicians * Mohism * Chinese naturalism * Neotaoism * Taoism * Yangism * Zen

GRECO- ROMAN

* Aristotelianism * Atomism * Cynicism * Cyrenaics * Eleatics * Eretrian school * Epicureanism * Hermeneutics

* Ionian

* Ephesian * Milesian

* Megarian school * Neoplatonism * Peripatetic * Platonism * Pluralism * Presocratic * Pyrrhonism * Pythagoreanism * Neopythagoreanism * Sophism * Stoicism

INDIAN

* Buddhist * Cārvāka * Hindu * Jain

PERSIAN

* Mazdakism * Zoroastrianism * Zurvanism

MEDIEVAL

EUROPEAN

* Christian philosophy * Scholasticism * Thomism * Renaissance humanism

EAST ASIAN

* Korean Confucianism * Edo Neo- Confucianism * Neo- Confucianism

INDIAN

* Dvaita * Navya-Nyāya * Vishishtadvaita

ISLAMIC

* Averroism * Avicennism * Illuminationism * _ʿIlm al-Kalām _ * Sufi

JEWISH

* Judeo-Islamic

MODERN

PEOPLE

* Cartesianism * Kantianism * Neo- Kantianism * Hegelianism * Marxism * Spinozism

0

* Anarchism * Classical Realism * Liberalism * Collectivism * Conservatism * Determinism * Dualism * Empiricism * Existentialism * Foundationalism * Historicism * Holism * Humanism

* Idealism

* Absolute * British * German * Objective * Subjective * Transcendental

* Individualism * Kokugaku * Materialism * Modernism * Monism * Naturalism * Natural law * Nihilism * New Confucianism * Neo- Scholasticism * Pragmatism * Phenomenology * Positivism * Reductionism * Rationalism * Social contract * Socialism * Transcendentalism * Utilitarianism

CONTEMPORARY

ANALYTIC

* Applied ethics * Analytic feminism * Analytical Marxism * Communitarianism * Consequentialism * Critical rationalism * Experimental philosophy * Falsificationism * Foundationalism / Coherentism * Generative linguistics * Internalism and Externalism * Logical positivism * Legal positivism * Normative ethics * Meta-ethics * Moral realism * Neo-Aristotelian * Quinean naturalism * Ordinary language philosophy * Postanalytic philosophy * Quietism * Rawlsian * Reformed epistemology * Systemics * Scientism * Scientific realism * Scientific skepticism * Contemporary utilitarianism * Vienna Circle * Wittgensteinian

CONTINENTAL

* Critical theory * Deconstruction * Existentialism * Feminist * Frankfurt School * New Historicism * Hermeneutics * Neo- Marxism * Phenomenology * Postmodernism * Post-structuralism * Social constructionism * Structuralism * Western Marxism

OTHER

* Kyoto School * Objectivism * Russian cosmism * _more... _

POSITIONS

AESTHETICS

* Formalism * Institutionalism * Aesthetic response

ETHICS

* Consequentialism * Deontology * Virtue

FREE WILL

* Compatibilism * Determinism * Libertarianism

METAPHYSICS

* Atomism * Dualism * Monism * Naturalism

EPISTEMOLOGY

* Constructivism * Empiricism * Idealism * Particularism * Fideism * Rationalism / Reasonism * Skepticism * Solipsism

MIND

* Behaviorism * Emergentism * Eliminativism * Epiphenomenalism * Functionalism * Objectivism * Subjectivism

NORMATIVITY

* Absolutism * Particularism * Relativism * Nihilism * Skepticism * Universalism

ONTOLOGY

* Action * Event * Process

REALITY

* Anti-realism * Conceptualism * Idealism * Materialism * Naturalism * Nominalism * Physicalism * Realism

* Philosophy by region * Philosophy-related lists * Miscellaneous

BY REGION

* African * Ethiopian * Aztec * Native America * Eastern * Chinese * Egyptian * Czech * Indian * Indonesian * Iranian * Japanese * Korean * Vietnam * Pakistani * Western * American * Australian * British * Danish * French * German * Greek * Italian * Polish * Romanian * Russian * Slovene * Spanish * Turkish

LISTS

* Outline * Index * Years * Problems * Schools * Glossary * Philosophers * Movements * Publications

MISCELLANEOUS

* Women in philosophy * Sage (philosophy)

* Portal * Category * Book

* v * t * e

Ethics

THEORIES

* Casuistry * Consequentialism

* Deontology

* Kantian ethics

* Ethics of care * Existentialist ethics * Meta-ethics * Particularism * Pragmatic ethics * Role ethics * Virtue ethics

CONCEPTS

* Autonomy * Axiology * Belief * Conscience * Consent * Equality * Care * Free will * Good and evil * Happiness * Ideal * Justice * Morality * Norm * Freedom * Principles * Suffering or Pain * Stewardship * Sympathy * Trust * Value * Virtue * Wrong * FULL INDEX...

PHILOSOPHERS

* Plato * Aristotle * Valluvar * Cicero * Confucius * Augustine of Hippo * Mencius * Mozi * Xunzi * Thomas Aquinas * Baruch Spinoza * David Hume * Immanuel Kant * Georg W. F. Hegel * Arthur Schopenhauer * Jeremy Bentham * John Stuart Mill * Søren Kierkegaard * Henry Sidgwick * Friedrich Nietzsche * G. E. Moore * Karl Barth * Paul Tillich * Dietrich Bonhoeffer * Philippa Foot * John Rawls * Bernard Williams * J. L. Mackie * G. E. M. Anscombe * William Frankena * Alasdair MacIntyre * R. M. Hare * Peter Singer * Derek Parfit * Thomas Nagel * Robert Merrihew Adams * Charles Taylor * Joxe Azurmendi * Christine Korsgaard * Martha Nussbaum * MORE...

APPLIED ETHICS

* Bioethics * Business ethics * Discourse ethics * Environmental ethics * Legal ethics * Medical ethics * Nursing ethics * Professional ethics * Sexual ethics * Ethics of eating meat * Ethics of technology

RELATED ARTICLES

* Christian ethics * Descriptive ethics * Ethics in religion * Evolutionary ethics * Feminist ethics * History of ethics * Ideology * Islamic ethics * Jewish ethics * Normative ethics * Philosophy of law * Political philosophy * Social philosophy

* Portal * Category

AUTHORITY CONTROL

* GND : 4015602-3 * NDL : 00569521

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title= Ethics additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy .® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc. , a non-profit organization.

* Privacy policy * About Wikipedia * Disclaimers * Contact Wikipedia * Developers * Cookie statement * Mobile view

* *

Links: ------ /wiki/Philosophy /wiki/Action_(philosophy) /#cite_note-iep.utm.edu-1 /wiki/Ancient_Greek_language /wiki/Ethos /wiki/Habit

.