HOME
The Info List - Epicurus


--- Advertisement ---



Epicurus
Epicurus
(/ˌɛpɪˈkjʊərəs, ˌɛpɪˈkjɔːrəs/;[2] Greek: Ἐπίκουρος, Epíkouros, "ally, comrade"; 341–270 BC) was an ancient Greek philosopher who founded a school of philosophy now called Epicureanism. Only a few fragments and letters of Epicurus's 300 written works remain. Much of what is known about Epicurean philosophy derives from later followers and commentators. For Epicurus, the purpose of philosophy was to attain the happy, tranquil life, characterized by ataraxia—peace and freedom from fear—and aponia—the absence of pain—and by living a self-sufficient life surrounded by friends. He taught that the root of all human neurosis was death denial, and the tendency for human beings to assume that death will be horrific and painful, which he claimed causes unnecessary anxiety, selfish self-protective behaviors, and hypocrisy. According to Epicurus, death is the end of both the body and the soul and therefore should not be feared. He also taught that the gods neither reward nor punish humans; that the universe is infinite and eternal; and that occurrences in the natural world are ultimately the result of atoms moving and interacting in empty space.

Contents

1 Biography 2 The school 3 Teachings

3.1 Prefiguring science and ethics 3.2 Pleasure
Pleasure
as absence of suffering 3.3 Epicurean paradox 3.4 Epistemology 3.5 Politics

4 Works 5 Legacy 6 In literature and popular media 7 Epicurus
Epicurus
and Epikoros 8 See also 9 Notes 10 References 11 Further reading 12 External links

Biography[edit]

Part of a series on

Hedonism

Thinkers

Ajita Kesakambali Jeremy Bentham Julien Offray de La Mettrie Aristippus Epicurus Fred Feldman Theodorus the Atheist Michel Onfray Aristippus
Aristippus
the Younger Hermarchus Lucretius Pierre Gassendi Metrodorus of Lampsacus David Pearce Zeno of Sidon Yang Zhu Torbjörn Tännsjö Esperanza Guisán

Schools of hedonism

Cārvāka Cyrenaics Epicureanism Christian hedonism Utilitarianism Yangism

Key concepts

Aponia Ataraxia Eudaimonia Happiness Hedone Pain Pleasure Sensation Suffering Tetrapharmakos

Related articles

Paradox of hedonism Hedonic treadmill

v t e

His parents, Neocles and Chaerestrate, both Athenian-born, and his father a citizen, had emigrated to the Athenian settlement on the Aegean island of Samos
Samos
about ten years before Epicurus's birth in February 341 BC.[3] As a boy, he studied philosophy for four years under the Platonist teacher Pamphilus. At the age of eighteen, he went to Athens
Athens
for his two-year term of military service. The playwright Menander
Menander
served in the same age-class of the ephebes as Epicurus. After the death of Alexander the Great, Perdiccas
Perdiccas
expelled the Athenian settlers on Samos
Samos
to Colophon, on the coast of what is now Turkey. After the completion of his military service, Epicurus
Epicurus
joined his family there. He studied under Nausiphanes, who followed the teachings of Democritus. In 311/310 BC Epicurus
Epicurus
taught in Mytilene
Mytilene
but caused strife and was forced to leave. He then founded a school in Lampsacus
Lampsacus
before returning to Athens
Athens
in 306 BC where he remained until his death.[4] There he founded The Garden (κῆπος), a school named for the garden he owned that served as the school's meeting place, about halfway between the locations of two other schools of philosophy, the Stoa and the Academy. Epicurus's teachings were heavily influenced by those of earlier philosophers, particularly Democritus. Nonetheless, Epicurus
Epicurus
differed from his predecessors on several key points of determinism and vehemently denied having been influenced by any previous philosophers, whom he denounced as "confused". Instead, he insisted that he had been "self-taught".[5] Epicurus
Epicurus
never married and had no known children. He was most likely a vegetarian.[6][7] He suffered from kidney stones,[8] to which he finally succumbed in 270 BC[9] at the age of seventy-two, and despite the prolonged pain involved, he wrote to Idomeneus:

I have written this letter to you on a happy day to me, which is also the last day of my life. For I have been attacked by a painful inability to urinate, and also dysentery, so violent that nothing can be added to the violence of my sufferings. But the cheerfulness of my mind, which comes from the recollection of all my philosophical contemplation, counterbalances all these afflictions. And I beg you to take care of the children of Metrodorus, in a manner worthy of the devotion shown by the young man to me, and to philosophy.[10]

Three Epicurus
Epicurus
bronze busts were recovered from the Villa of the Papyri, as well as text fragments.[11] Konstan from the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
notes "Short citations of Epicurus' works appear in other writers (e.g., Plutarch, Sextus Empiricus, and the Greek commentators on Aristotle), often taken out of context or presented in a polemical and distorted fashion. [..] The school tended to be conservative and later thinkers embellished rather than altered Epicurus' own teachings."[12] The school[edit] In Mytilene, the capital of the island Lesbos, and then in Lampsacus Epicurus
Epicurus
taught and gained followers. In Athens
Athens
Epicurus
Epicurus
bought a property for his school called "Garden", later the name of Epicurus school.[12] The primary members were Hermarchus, the financier Idomeneus, Leonteus and his wife Themista, the satirist Colotes, the mathematician Polyaenus of Lampsacus, Leontion, and Metrodorus of Lampsacus, the most famous popularizer of Epicureanism. His school was the first of the ancient Greek philosophical schools to admit women as a rule rather than an exception.[note 1] An inscription on the gate to The Garden is recorded by Seneca the Younger
Seneca the Younger
in epistle XXI of Epistulae morales ad Lucilium:[13]

Stranger, here you will do well to tarry; here our highest good is pleasure.

Epicurus
Epicurus
emphasised friendship as an important ingredient of happiness, and the school resembled in many ways a community of friends living together. However, he also instituted a hierarchical system of levels among his followers, and had them swear an oath on his core tenets. According to Diskin Clay, Epicurus
Epicurus
himself established a custom of celebrating his birthday annually with common meals, befitting his stature as heros ktistes ("founding hero") of the Garden. He ordained in his will annual memorial feasts for himself on the same date (10th of Gamelion month).[14] Epicurean communities continued this tradition,[15] referring to Epicurus
Epicurus
as their "saviour" (soter) and celebrating him as hero. Lucretius
Lucretius
apotheosized Epicurus
Epicurus
as the main character of his epic poem De rerum natura. The hero cult of Epicurus may have operated as a Garden variety civic religion.[16] However, clear evidence of an Epicurean hero cult, as well as the cult itself, seems buried by the weight of posthumous philosophical interpretation.[17] Epicurus' cheerful demeanour, as he continued to work despite dying from a painful stone blockage of his urinary tract lasting a fortnight, according to his successor Hermarchus and reported by his biographer Diogenes
Diogenes
Laërtius, further enhanced his status among his followers.[8] Teachings[edit] Main article: Epicureanism

Small bronze bust of Epicurus
Epicurus
from Herculaneum. Illustration from Baumeister, 1885

Prefiguring science and ethics[edit] Epicurus
Epicurus
is a key figure in the development of science and scientific methodology because of his insistence that nothing should be believed, except that which was tested through direct observation and logical deduction. He was a key figure in the Axial Age, the period from 800 BC to 200 BC, during which, according to Karl Jaspers, similar thinking appeared in China, India, Iran, the Near East, and Ancient Greece. His statement of the Ethic of Reciprocity
Ethic of Reciprocity
as the foundation of ethics is the earliest in Ancient Greece, and he differs from the formulation of utilitarianism by Jeremy Bentham
Jeremy Bentham
and John Stuart Mill by emphasising the minimisation of harm to oneself and others as the way to maximise happiness. Epicurus's teachings represented a departure from the other major Greek thinkers of his period, and before, but was nevertheless founded on many of the same principles as Democritus. Like Democritus, he was an atomist, believing that the fundamental constituents of the world were indivisible little bits of matter (atoms; Greek: ἄτομος atom os, "indivisible") flying through empty space (Greek: κενόν kenon). Everything that occurs is the result of the atoms colliding, rebounding, and becoming entangled with one another. His theory differs from the earlier atomism of Democritus
Democritus
because he admits that atoms do not always follow straight lines but their direction of motion may occasionally exhibit a "swerve" (Greek: παρέγκλισις parenklisis; Latin: clinamen). This allowed him to avoid the determinism implicit in the earlier atomism and to affirm free will.[18] He regularly admitted women and slaves into his school and was one of the first Greeks to break from the god-fearing and god-worshipping tradition common at the time, even while affirming that religious activities are useful as a way to contemplate the gods and to use them as an example of the pleasant life. Epicurus
Epicurus
participated in the activities of traditional Greek religion, but taught that one should avoid holding false opinions about the gods. The gods are immortal and blessed and men who ascribe any additional qualities that are alien to immortality and blessedness are, according to Epicurus, impious. The gods do not punish the bad and reward the good as the common man believes. The opinion of the crowd is, Epicurus
Epicurus
claims, that the gods "send great evils to the wicked and great blessings to the righteous who model themselves after the gods," whereas Epicurus
Epicurus
believes the gods, in reality, do not concern themselves at all with human beings.

It is not the man who denies the gods worshipped by the multitude, who is impious, but he who affirms of the gods what the multitude believes about them.[19]

Pleasure
Pleasure
as absence of suffering[edit] Epicurus' philosophy is based on the theory that all good and bad derive from the sensations of what he defined as pleasure and pain: What is good is what is pleasurable, and what is bad is what is painful. His ideas of pleasure and pain were ultimately, for Epicurus, the basis for the moral distinction between good and evil. If pain is chosen over pleasure in some cases it is only because it leads to a greater pleasure. Although Epicurus
Epicurus
has been commonly misunderstood to advocate the rampant pursuit of pleasure, his teachings were more about striving for an absence of pain and suffering, both physical and mental, and a state of satiation and tranquillity that was free of the fear of death and the retribution of the gods. Epicurus
Epicurus
argued that when we do not suffer pain, we are no longer in need of pleasure, and we enter a state of ataraxia, "tranquillity of soul" or "imperturbability".[20][21] Epicurus
Epicurus
distinguishes between two different types of pleasure: "moving" pleasures (κατὰ κίνησιν ἡδοναί) and "static" pleasures (καταστηματικαὶ ἡδοναί).[22][23] "Moving" pleasures occur when one is in the process of satisfying a desire and involve an active titillation of the senses.[22] After one's desires have been satisfied, (e.g., when one is full after eating), the state of satiety is a "static" pleasure.[22] For Epicurus, static pleasures are the best pleasures.[22] Epicurus' teachings were introduced into medical philosophy and practice by the Epicurean doctor Asclepiades of Bithynia, who was the first physician who introduced Greek medicine in Rome. Asclepiades introduced the friendly, sympathetic, pleasing and painless treatment of patients. He advocated humane treatment of mental disorders, had insane persons freed from confinement and treated them with natural therapy, such as diet and massages. His teachings are surprisingly modern, therefore Asclepiades is considered to be a pioneer physician in psychotherapy, physical therapy and molecular medicine.[24] Epicurus
Epicurus
explicitly warned against overindulgence because it often leads to pain. For instance, Epicurus
Epicurus
warned against pursuing love too ardently. He defended friendships as ramparts for pleasure and denied them any inherent worth.[25] He also believed, contrary to Aristotle,[26] that death was not to be feared. When a man dies, he does not feel the pain of death because he no longer is and therefore feels nothing. Therefore, as Epicurus
Epicurus
famously said, "death is nothing to us." When we exist, death is not; and when death exists, we are not. All sensation and consciousness ends with death and therefore in death there is neither pleasure nor pain. The fear of death arises from the belief that in death, there is awareness. From this doctrine arose the Epicurean epitaph: Non fui, fui, non sum, non curo ("I was not; I was; I am not; I do not care"), which is inscribed on the gravestones of his followers and seen on many ancient gravestones of the Roman Empire. This quotation is often used today at humanist funerals.[27] As an ethical guideline, Epicurus
Epicurus
emphasised minimising harm and maximising happiness of oneself and others:

It is impossible to live a pleasant life without living wisely and well and justly, and it is impossible to live wisely and well and justly without living pleasantly.

("justly" meaning to prevent a "person from harming or being harmed by another")[28]

Epicurean paradox[edit] The "Epicurean paradox" or "Riddle of Epicurus" is a version of the problem of evil. Lactantius
Lactantius
attributes this trilemma to Epicurus
Epicurus
in De Ira Dei:

God, he says, either wishes to take away evils, and is unable; or He is able, and is unwilling; or He is neither willing nor able, or He is both willing and able. If He is willing and is unable, He is feeble, which is not in accordance with the character of God; if He is able and unwilling, He is envious, which is equally at variance with God; if He is neither willing nor able, He is both envious and feeble, and therefore not God; if He is both willing and able, which alone is suitable to God, from what source then are evils? Or why does He not remove them?

In Dialogues concerning Natural Religion (1779), David Hume
David Hume
also attributes the argument to Epicurus:

Epicurus’s old questions are yet unanswered. Is he willing to prevent evil, but not able? then is he impotent. Is he able, but not willing? then is he malevolent. Is he both able and willing? whence then is evil?

No extant writings of Epicurus
Epicurus
contain this argument and it is possible that it has been misattributed to him.[citation needed] Cicero's character Cotta, an Academician, rehearses this argument in de Natura deorum, a dialogue with an Epicurean and a Stoic.[29]

Either God
God
wishes to remove evils and cannot, or he can do so and is unwilling, or he has neither the will nor the power, or he has both the will and the power. If he has the will but not the power, he is a weakling, and this is not characteristic of God. If he has the power but not the will, he is grudging, and this is a trait equally foreign to God. If he has neither the will nor the power, he is both grudging and weak, and is therefore not divine. If he has both the will and the power (and this is the sole circumstance appropriate to God), what is the source of evils, or why does God
God
not dispel them? (3.65, 133, trans. P.G. Walsh)

Another early expression of this trilemma appears in the writings of the sceptic Sextus Empiricus
Sextus Empiricus
(160–210 AD),who wrote in his Outlines of Pyrrhonism:

Further, this too should be said. Anyone who asserts that god exists either says that god takes care of the things in the cosmos or that he does not, and, if he does take care, that it is either of all things or of some. Now if he takes care of everything, there would be no particular evil thing and no evil in general in the cosmos; but the Dogmatists say that everything is full of evil; therefore god shall not be said to take care of everything. On the other hand, if he takes care of only some things, why does he take care of these and not of those? For either he wishes but is not able, or he is able but does not wish, or he neither wishes nor is able. If he both wished and was able, he would have taken care of everything; but, for the reasons stated above, he does not take care of everything; therefore, it is not the case that he both wishes and is able to take care of everything. But if he wishes and is not able, he is weaker than the cause on account of which he is not able to take care of the things of which he does not take care; but it is contrary to the concept of god that he should be weaker than anything. Again, if he is able to take care of everything but does not wish to do so, he will be considered malevolent, and if he neither wishes nor is able, he is both malevolent and weak; but to say that about god is impious. Therefore, god does not take care of the things in the cosmos.

Epistemology[edit] Epicurus
Epicurus
emphasised the senses in his epistemology, and his Principle of Multiple Explanations ("if several theories are consistent with the observed data, retain them all") is an early contribution to the philosophy of science.

There are also some things for which it is not enough to state a single cause, but several, of which one, however, is the case. Just as if you were to see the lifeless corpse of a man lying far away, it would be fitting to list all the causes of death in order to make sure that the single cause of this death may be stated. For you would not be able to establish conclusively that he died by the sword or of cold or of illness or perhaps by poison, but we know that there is something of this kind that happened to him.[30][31]

Politics[edit] In contrast to the Stoics, Epicureans showed little interest in participating in the politics of the day, since doing so leads to trouble. He instead advocated seclusion. This principle is epitomised by the phrase lathe biōsas (λάθε βιώσας), meaning "live in obscurity", "get through life without drawing attention to yourself", i.e., live without pursuing glory or wealth or power, but anonymously, enjoying little things like food, the company of friends, etc. Plutarch
Plutarch
elaborated on this theme in his essay Is the Saying "Live in Obscurity" Right? (Εἰ καλῶς εἴρηται τὸ λάθε βιώσας, An recte dictum sit latenter esse vivendum) 1128c; cf. Flavius Philostratus, Vita Apollonii 8.28.12. But the Epicureans did have an innovative theory of justice as a social contract. Justice, Epicurus
Epicurus
said, is an agreement neither to harm nor be harmed, and we need to have such a contract in order to enjoy fully the benefits of living together in a well-ordered society. Laws and punishments are needed to keep misguided fools in line who would otherwise break the contract. But the wise person sees the usefulness of justice, and because of his limited desires, he has no need to engage in the conduct prohibited by the laws in any case. Laws that are useful for promoting happiness are just, but those that are not useful are not just. (Principal Doctrines 31–40) Works[edit]

Epicurus, Nuremberg Chronicle

The only surviving complete works by Epicurus
Epicurus
are three letters, which are to be found in book X of Diogenes
Diogenes
Laërtius' Lives of Eminent Philosophers, and two groups of quotes: the Principal Doctrines (Κύριαι Δόξαι), reported as well in Diogenes' book X, and the Vatican Sayings, preserved in a manuscript from the Vatican Library. Numerous fragments of his thirty-seven volume treatise On Nature have been found among the charred papyrus fragments at the Villa of the Papyri at Herculaneum. In addition, other Epicurean writings found at Herculaneum
Herculaneum
contain important quotations from his other works. Moreover, numerous fragments and testimonies are found throughout ancient Greek and Roman literature, a collection of which can be found in Usener's Epicurea. According to Diogenes Laertius
Diogenes Laertius
(10.27-9), the major works of Epicurus include:

On Nature, in 37 books On Atoms and the Void On Love Abridgment of the Arguments employed against the Natural Philosophers Against the Megarians Problems Fundamental Propositions (Kyriai Doxai) On Choice and Avoidance On the Chief Good On the Criterion (the Canon) Chaeridemus, On the Gods On Piety Hegesianax Four essays on Lives Essay on Just Dealing Neocles Essay addressed to Themista The Banquet (Symposium) Eurylochus Essay addressed to Metrodorus Essay on Seeing Essay on the Angle in an Atom Essay on Touch Essay on Fate Opinions on the Passions Treatise addressed to Timocrates Prognostics Exhortations On Images On Perceptions Aristobulus Essay on Music (i.e., on music, poetry, and dance) On Justice and the other Virtues On Gifts and Gratitude Polymedes Timocrates (three books) Metrodorus (five books) Antidorus (two books) Opinions about Diseases and Death, addressed to Mithras Callistolas Essay on Kingly Power Anaximenes Letters

Legacy[edit]

Bust of Epicurus
Epicurus
leaning against his disciple Metrodorus in the Louvre Museum

Elements of Epicurean philosophy have resonated and resurfaced in various diverse thinkers and movements throughout Western intellectual history. The atomic poems (such as 'All Things are Governed by Atoms') and the philosophy of naturalism espoused by Margaret Cavendish
Margaret Cavendish
were influenced by Epicurus. His emphasis on minimising harm and maximising happiness in his formulation of the Ethic of Reciprocity
Ethic of Reciprocity
was later picked up by the democratic thinkers of the French Revolution, and others, like John Locke, who wrote that people had a right to "life, liberty, and property."[32] To Locke, one's own body was part of one's property, and thus one's right to property would theoretically guarantee safety for one's person, as well as one's possessions. This triad, as well as the egalitarianism of Epicurus, was carried forward into the American freedom movement and Declaration of Independence, by the American founding father, Thomas Jefferson, as "all men are created equal" and endowed with certain "unalienable rights," such as "life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness." Jefferson considered himself an Epicurean.[33] In An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, David Hume
David Hume
uses Epicurus as a character for explaining the impossibility of our knowing God
God
to be any greater or better than his creation proves him to be. Karl Marx's doctoral thesis was on The Difference Between the Democritean and Epicurean Philosophy of Nature. Epicurus
Epicurus
was first to assert human freedom as coming from a fundamental indeterminism in the motion of atoms. This has led some philosophers to think that for Epicurus
Epicurus
free will was caused directly by chance. In his On the Nature of Things (De rerum natura), Lucretius
Lucretius
appears to suggest this in the best-known passage on Epicurus' position.[34] But in his Letter to Menoeceus, Epicurus
Epicurus
follows Aristotle
Aristotle
and clearly identifies three possible causes - "some things happen of necessity, others by chance, others through our own agency." Aristotle
Aristotle
said some things "depend on us" (eph'hemin). Epicurus
Epicurus
agreed, and said it is to these last things that praise and blame naturally attach. For Epicurus, the "swerve" (or clinamen) of the atoms simply defeated determinism to leave room for autonomous agency.[35] Epicurus
Epicurus
was also a significant source of inspiration and interest for both Arthur Schopenhauer, having particular influence on the famous pessimist's views on suffering and death, as well as one of Schopenhauer's successors: Friedrich Nietzsche. Nietzsche cites his affinities to Epicurus
Epicurus
in a number of his works, including The Gay Science, Beyond Good and Evil, and his private letters to Peter Gast. Nietzsche was attracted to, among other things, Epicurus' ability to maintain a cheerful philosophical outlook in the face of painful physical ailments. Nietzsche also suffered from a number of sicknesses during his lifetime. However, he thought that Epicurus' conception of happiness as freedom from anxiety was too passive and negative. In Greece, in February of every year since 2011 a two-day Panhellenic Symposium of Epicurean Philosophy is held.[36] In literature and popular media[edit] Paul the Apostle
Paul the Apostle
encountered Epicurean and Stoic philosophers as he was ministering in Athens.[37] Horace
Horace
describes himself as Epicuri de grege porcum "a swine from Epicurus's herd" in his Epistles.[38] In Canto X Circle 6 ("Where the heretics lie") of Dante's Inferno, Epicurus
Epicurus
and his followers are criticised for supporting a materialistic ideal when they are mentioned to have been condemned to the Circle of Heresy. Chaucer's Frankeleyn, in the General Prologue of his Canterbury Tales, is described as an Epicurean: "Wel loved he by the morwe a sop in wyn; / To lyven in delit was evre his wone, / For he was Epicurus
Epicurus
owene sone, / That heeld opinioun that pleyn delit / Was verray felicitee parfit" (344-38). [He well loved bread soaked in wine for breakfast; / To live in pleasure was ever his custom, / For he was a son of Epicurus, / Who was of the opinion that pure pleasure / Was true perfect happiness.] Epicurus the Sage
Epicurus the Sage
is a two-part comic book by William Messner-Loebs and Sam Kieth portraying Epicurus
Epicurus
as "the only sane philosopher" by anachronistically bringing him together with many other well-known Greek philosophers. It was republished as graphic novel by the Wildstorm branch of DC Comics. Epicurus
Epicurus
and Epikoros[edit] Main article: Epikoros (Judaism) In Rabbinic literature the term Epikoros is used, without a specific reference to Epicurus, yet it seems apparent that the term was derived from his name.[39] Epicurus's apparent hedonistic views (as Epicurus' ethics was hedonistic) and philosophical teachings, though opposed to the Hedonists of his time, countered Jewish scripture, the strictly monotheistic conception of God in Judaism
God in Judaism
and the Jewish belief in the afterlife and the world to come. The Talmudic interpretation is that the Aramaic
Aramaic
word is derived from the root-word פק"ר (PKR; lit. licentious), hence disrespect. The Christian censorship of the Jewish Talmud
Talmud
in the aftermath of the Disputation of Barcelona and during the Spanish Inquisition
Spanish Inquisition
and Roman Inquisition, let the term spread within the Jewish classical texts, since Roman Catholic Church censors replaced terms like Minim ("sectarians", coined on the Christians) with the term Epikorsim or Epicursim, meaning heretics.[citation needed] See also[edit]

Epikoros (Judaism) Philosophy of happiness Separation of church and state

Notes[edit]

^ Two women, Axiothea and Lastheneia, were known to have been admitted by Plato. See Hadot, Pierre. Qu'est-ce que la philosophie antique?, page 99, Gillimard 1995. Pythagoras
Pythagoras
is also believed to have inducted one woman, Theano, into his order.

^ Bunnin & Yu (2004). The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.  ^ Jones, Daniel (2006). Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary. 17th edition. Cambridge UP.  ^ Apollodorus of Athens
Athens
(reported by Diogenes
Diogenes
Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 10.14–15) gives his birth on the fourth day of the month February in the third year of the 109th Olympiad, in the archonship of Sosigenes ^ " Epicurus
Epicurus
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy".  ^ "Epicurus' Attitude to Democritus" JSTOR ^ "The Hidden History of Greco-Roman Vegetarianism".  ^ Dombrowski, Daniel A. (1984). The Philosophy of Vegetarianism. ISBN 0870234315.  ^ a b Bitsori, Maria; Galanakis, Emmanouil (2004). "Epicurus' death". World Journal of Urology. 22 (6): 466–469. doi:10.1007/s00345-004-0448-2. PMID 15372192.  ^ In the second year of the 127th Olympiad, in the archonship of Pytharatus, according to Diogenes
Diogenes
Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 10.15 ^ Diogenes
Diogenes
Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 10.22 (trans. C.D. Yonge). ^ Sheila Dillon (2006). " Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek
Portrait Sculpture: Contexts, Subjects, and Styles". Cambridge University Press. p. 45 – via Google Books.  ^ a b David Konstan. "Epicurus". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  ^ "Epistulae morales ad Lucilium".  ^ D. Smith, Nicholas. Reason and religion in Socratic philosophy. p. 160. ISBN 0-19-513322-6.  ^ Glad, Clarence E. Paul and Philodemus: adaptability in Epicurean and early Christian psychology. p. 176. ISBN 90-04-10067-9.  ^ Nussbaum, Martha Craven. The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics. p. 119. ISBN 0-691-14131-2.  ^ Clay, Diskin. Paradosis and survival: three chapters in the history of Epicurean philosophy. p. 76. ISBN 0-472-10896-4.  ^ The only fragment in Greek about this central notion is from the Oenoanda inscription (fr. 54 in Smith's edition). The best known reference is in Lucretius's On the nature of things, [1]. ^ letter by Epicurus
Epicurus
to Menoeceus; see Diogenes Laërtius
Diogenes Laërtius
de clarorum philosophorum vitis, dogmatibus et apophthegmatibus libri decem (X, 123) ^ Folse, Henry (2005). How Epicurean Metaphysics
Metaphysics
leads to Epicurean Ethics. Department of Philosophy, Loyola University, New Orleans, LA.  ^ Konstan, David. Epicurus, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition). forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/epicurus/> ^ a b c d Epicurus
Epicurus
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy ^ Diogenes
Diogenes
Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, X:136. ^ C, Yapijakis (2009). " Hippocrates
Hippocrates
of Kos, the father of clinical medicine, and Asclepiades of Bithynia, the father of molecular medicine. Review". In Vivo. 23 (4): 507–14. PMID 19567383.  ^ Cicero, Marcus Tullius. "II.82". De finibus bonorum et malorum. ISBN 3-519-01219-7.  ^ Rosenbaum, Stephen. Appraising Death In Human Life: Two Modes Of Valuation, in French, Peter, and Wettstein, Howard (editors), Life And Death: Metaphysics
Metaphysics
And Ethics, Midwest Studies In Philosophy, volume XXIV. Blackwell Publishers, Inc., 2000, p.153 ( Aristotle
Aristotle
'seems to have believed [in] fearing death ... . [But] his conclusion should be understood to be [merely] that the fact that a person dies is bad [because] nothing is any longer good or bad for him or her.') Books.Google.com (accessed 2011-Feb-04) ^ " Epicurus
Epicurus
(c 341-270 BC)". British Humanist Association.  ^ " Epicurus
Epicurus
Principal Doctrines 5 and 31 transl. by Robert Drew Hicks". 1925.  ^ Cicero, Marcus Tullius. The Nature of the Gods.  ^ Lucretius.[full citation needed] ^ The poem version can be found in: Carus, Titus Lucretius
Lucretius
(Jul 2008). Of The Nature of Things. Project Gutenberg EBook. 785. William Ellery Leonard (translator). Project Gutenberg.  Book VI, Section Extraordinary and Paradoxical Telluric Phenomena, Line 9549–9560 ^ John Locke
John Locke
(1689) "Two Treatises of Government#Property" ^ Jefferson considered himself an Epicurean (1819): "Letter, Thomas Jefferson to William Short" ^ 2.251-262 "On the Nature of Things, 289-293" Check url= value (help) – via Perseus Project.  ^ " Epicurus
Epicurus
page on Information Philosopher; cf. Letter to Menoeceus, §134".  ^ http://epicuros.gr/pages/en.htm ^ The Holy Bible, Acts 17:18 – via Biblegateway.com  ^ Horace, Epistles Bk I, ep. 4 v. 16. uah.edu ^ "Epikoros". encyclopedia.com. 

References[edit]

 Laërtius, Diogenes
Diogenes
(1925). "Epicurus". Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. 2:10. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.  Diogenes
Diogenes
Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, X:136

Further reading[edit]

Texts

Epicurus
Epicurus
(1994). Inwood, Brad; Gerson, Lloyd P., eds. The Epicurus Reader. Selected Writings and Testimonia. Indianapolis: Hackett. ISBN 0-87220-242-9.  Epicurus
Epicurus
(1993). The essential Epicurus : letters, principal doctrines, Vatican sayings, and fragments. Eugene O'Connor, trans. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books. ISBN 0-87975-810-4.  Epicurus
Epicurus
(1964). Letters, principal doctrines, and Vatican sayings. Russel M. Geer, trans. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.  Laertius, Diogenes
Diogenes
(1969). Caponigri, A. Robert, ed. Lives of the Philosophers. Chicago: Henry Regnery Co.  Lucretius
Lucretius
Carus, Titus (1976). On the nature of the universe. R. E. Latham, trans. London: Penguin Books. ISBN 0-14-044018-6.  Körte, Alfred (1987). Epicureanism : two collections of fragments and studies (in Greek). New York: Garland. ISBN 0-8240-6915-3.  Oates, Whitney J. (1940). The Stoic and Epicurean philosophers, The Complete Extant Writings of Epicurus, Epictetus, Lucretius
Lucretius
and Marcus Aurelius. New York: Modern Library. Diogenes
Diogenes
of Oinoanda (1993). The Epicurean inscription. Martin Ferguson Smith, trans. Napoli: Bibliopolis. ISBN 88-7088-270-5. 

Studies

Asmis, Elizabeth (1984). Epicurus' Scientific Method. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-08014-1465-7.  Bailey C. (1928). The Greek Atomists and Epicurus, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Bakalis, Nikolaos (2005). Handbook of Greek Philosophy from Thales
Thales
to the Stoics. Analysis and fragments. Victoria: Trafford. ISBN 1-4120-4843-5.  Gordon, Pamela (1996). Epicurus
Epicurus
in Lycia. The Second-Century World of Diogenes
Diogenes
of Oenoanda. Ann Arbor: Univ. of Michigan Press. ISBN 0-472-10461-6.  Gottlieb, Anthony (2000). The Dream of Reason. A History of Western Philosophy from the Greeks to the Renaissance. New York: W.W. Norton. ISBN 0-393-04951-5.  Hibler, Richard W. (1984). Happiness
Happiness
Through Tranquillity. The school of Epicurus. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. ISBN 0-8191-3861-4.  Hicks, R. D. (1910). Stoic and Epicurean. New York: Scribner.  Jones, Howard (1989). The Epicurean Tradition. London: Routledge. ISBN 0-415-02069-7.  O'Keefe, Tim (2009). Epicureanism. University of California Press.  Panichas, George Andrew (1967). Epicurus. New York: Twayne Publishers.  Rist, J.M. (1972). Epicurus. An introduction. London: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-08426-1.  Warren, James (2009). The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-05218-7347-5.  William Wallace. Epicureanism. SPCK (1880)

External links[edit]

Wikisource
Wikisource
has original works written by or about: Epicurus

Wikimedia Commons has media related to Epicurus.

Wikiquote has quotations related to: Epicurus

 Greek Wikisource
Wikisource
has original text related to this article: Κύριαι Δόξαι  Greek Wikisource
Wikisource
has original text related to this article: Ἐπιστολὴ πρὸς Μενοικέα Society of Friends of Epicurus
Epicurus
– Epicurean community Konstan, David. "Epicurus". In Zalta, Edward N. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  O'Keefe, Tim. "Epicurus". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  Stoic And Epicurean by Robert Drew Hicks (1910) (Internet Archive) Epicurus.net – Epicurus
Epicurus
and Epicurean Philosophy Epicurus
Epicurus
and Lucretius
Lucretius
– small article by "P. Dionysius Mus" The Difference Between the Democritean and Epicurean Philosophy of Nature – Karl Marx's doctoral thesis Epicurus
Epicurus
on Free Will The Garden of Epicurus
Epicurus
– useful summary of the teachings of Epicurus Philosophy of Happiness
Happiness
(PDF) Epicurea, Hermann Usener
Hermann Usener
- full text Works by or about Epicurus
Epicurus
at Internet Archive Works by Epicurus
Epicurus
at LibriVox
LibriVox
(public domain audiobooks)

Portrait

Discussion, bibliography, 3D models of the lost portrait

Primary sources

Principal Doctrines – unidentified translation Principal Doctrines – the original Greek, two English translations, and a parallel mode Vatican Sayings – unidentified translation Vatican Sayings – the original Greek with an English translation Letter to Herodotus Letter to Pythocles Letter to Menoeceus Epicurus: Fragments - Usener's compilation in English translation

v t e

Epicureanism

Philosophers

Greek era

Epicurus Polyaenus Metrodorus Batis Leontion Carneiscus Idomeneus Hermarchus Colotes Themista Leonteus Polystratus Dionysius of Lamptrai Basilides Philonides Diogenes
Diogenes
of Tarsus Alcaeus and Philiscus Apollodorus Demetrius Lacon Zeno of Sidon

Roman era

Amafinius Rabirius Titus Albucius Phaedrus Philodemus Lucretius Patro Catius Siro Diogenes
Diogenes
of Oenoanda

Philosophy

Epicureanism
Epicureanism
(cf. Hedonism) Tetrapharmakos

Concepts

Aponia Ataraxia Clinamen Eudaimonia Hedone Metakosmia

Works

On the Nature of Things List of English translations of De rerum natura

v t e

Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek
schools of philosophy

Pre-Socratic

Schools

Atomism Eleatics Ionian

Ephesian Milesian

Pluralism Pythagoreanism Sophistic

Philosophers

Anaxagoras Anaximander Anaximenes Democritus Empedocles Heraclitus Leucippus Melissus Parmenides Protagoras Pythagoras Thales Zeno of Elea

Socratic

Schools

Cynicism Cyrenaics Eretrian school Megarian school Peripateticism Platonism

Philosophers

Antisthenes Aristippus Aristotle Diogenes
Diogenes
of Sinope Euclid
Euclid
of Megara Phaedo of Elis Plato Socrates

Hellenistic

Schools

Epicureanism Neoplatonism Neopythagoreanism Pyrrhonism Stoicism

Philosophers

Apollonius of Tyana Augustine Epictetus Epicurus John Philoponus Lucretius Plotinus Proclus Pyrrho Sextus Empiricus Zeno of Citium

v t e

Ancient Greece

Outline Timeline

History Geography

Periods

Cycladic civilization Minoan civilization Mycenaean civilization Greek Dark Ages Archaic period Classical Greece Hellenistic Greece Roman Greece

Geography

Aegean Sea Aeolis Alexandria Antioch Cappadocia Crete Cyprus Doris Ephesus Epirus Hellespont Ionia Ionian Sea Macedonia Magna Graecia Miletus Peloponnesus Pergamon Pontus Taurica Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek
colonies

City states Politics Military

City states

Argos Athens Byzantion Chalcis Corinth Eretria Kerkyra Larissa Megalopolis Megara Rhodes Samos Sparta Syracuse Thebes

Politics

Boeotarch Boule Koinon Proxeny Strategos Tagus Tyrant Amphictyonic League

Athenian

Agora Areopagus Ecclesia Graphē paranómōn Heliaia Ostracism

Spartan

Apella Ephor Gerousia Harmost

Macedon

Synedrion Koinon

Military

Wars Athenian military Antigonid Macedonian army Army of Macedon Ballista Cretan archers Hellenistic armies Hippeis Hoplite Hetairoi Macedonian phalanx Phalanx Peltast Pezhetairos Sarissa Sacred Band of Thebes Sciritae Seleucid army Spartan army Toxotai Xiphos Xyston

People

List of ancient Greeks

Rulers

Kings of Argos Archons of Athens Kings of Athens Kings of Commagene Diadochi Kings of Lydia Kings of Macedonia Kings of Paionia Attalid kings of Pergamon Kings of Pontus Kings of Sparta Tyrants of Syracuse

Philosophers

Anaxagoras Anaximander Anaximenes Antisthenes Aristotle Democritus Diogenes
Diogenes
of Sinope Empedocles Epicurus Gorgias Heraclitus Hypatia Leucippus Parmenides Plato Protagoras Pythagoras Socrates Thales Zeno

Authors

Aeschylus Aesop Alcaeus Archilochus Aristophanes Bacchylides Euripides Herodotus Hesiod Hipponax Homer Ibycus Lucian Menander Mimnermus Panyassis Philocles Pindar Plutarch Polybius Sappho Simonides Sophocles Stesichorus Theognis Thucydides Timocreon Tyrtaeus Xenophon

Others

Agesilaus II Agis II Alcibiades Alexander the Great Aratus Archimedes Aspasia Demosthenes Epaminondas Euclid Hipparchus Hippocrates Leonidas Lycurgus Lysander Milo of Croton Miltiades Pausanias Pericles Philip of Macedon Philopoemen Praxiteles Ptolemy Pyrrhus Solon Themistocles

Groups

Philosophers Playwrights Poets Tyrants

By culture

Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek
tribes Thracian Greeks Ancient Macedonians

Society Culture

Society

Agriculture Calendar Clothing Coinage Cuisine Economy Education Festivals Funeral and burial practices Homosexuality Law Olympic Games Pederasty Philosophy Prostitution Religion Slavery Warfare Wedding customs Wine

Arts and science

Architecture

Greek Revival architecture

Astronomy Literature Mathematics Medicine Music

Musical system

Pottery Sculpture Technology Theatre

Religion

Funeral and burial practices Mythology

mythological figures

Temple Twelve Olympians Underworld

Sacred places

Eleusis Delphi Delos Dodona Mount Olympus Olympia

Structures

Athenian Treasury Lion Gate Long Walls Philippeion Theatre of Dionysus Tunnel of Eupalinos

Temples

Aphaea Artemis Athena Nike Erechtheion Hephaestus Hera, Olympia Parthenon Samothrace Zeus, Olympia

Language

Proto-Greek Mycenaean Homeric Dialects

Aeolic Arcadocypriot Attic Doric Ionic Locrian Macedonian Pamphylian

Koine

Writing

Linear A Linear B Cypriot syllabary Greek alphabet Greek numerals Attic numerals

Lists

Cities

in Epirus

People Place names Stoae Temples Theatres

Category Portal

v t e

Criticism of religion

By religion

Bahá'í Faith Buddhism Christianity

Catholic

Opus Dei

Jehovah's Witnesses Latter Day Saint movement Protestantism Seventh-day Adventist Unification Church Westboro Baptist Church

Hinduism Islam

Islamism Twelver Shia Islam Wahhabism

Jainism Judaism Monotheism New religious movement Scientology Sikhism Yazdânism Zoroastrianism

Religious texts

Bible Quran Hadiths Mormon sacred texts

Book of Mormon

Talmud

Religious figures

Aisha Charles Taze Russell Ellen White Jesus Moses Muhammad Mirza Ghulam Ahmad Saul

Religious violence

Buddhism Christianity

Mormonism

Judaism Islam Terrorism

Christian Hindu Islamic Jewish

Persecution

Christian thought on persecution and tolerance

War

In Islam In Judaism

Sectarian violence By country

India

Anti-Christian violence In Odisha

Nigeria Pakistan

Books

Atheist Manifesto Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon Christianity Unveiled God
God
in the Age of Science? God
God
Is Not Great God: The Failed Hypothesis Letter to a Christian Nation The Age of Reason The Blind Watchmaker The Caged Virgin The End of Faith The God
God
Delusion The Rage Against God Why I Am Not a Christian Why I Am Not a Muslim Books critical of Christianity Books critical of Islam

Movements

Agnosticism Antitheism Atheism Criticism of atheism Cārvāka New Atheism Nontheistic religions Parody religion

v t e

Philosophy of science

Concepts

Analysis Analytic–synthetic distinction A priori and a posteriori Causality Commensurability Consilience Construct Creative synthesis Demarcation problem Empirical evidence Explanatory power Fact Falsifiability Feminist method Ignoramus et ignorabimus Inductive reasoning Intertheoretic reduction Inquiry Nature Objectivity Observation Paradigm Problem of induction Scientific law Scientific method Scientific revolution Scientific theory Testability Theory choice Theory-ladenness Underdetermination Unity of science

Metatheory of science

Coherentism Confirmation holism Constructive empiricism Constructive realism Constructivist epistemology Contextualism Conventionalism Deductive-nomological model Hypothetico-deductive model Inductionism Epistemological anarchism Evolutionism Fallibilism Foundationalism Instrumentalism Pragmatism Model-dependent realism Naturalism Physicalism Positivism / Reductionism / Determinism Rationalism / Empiricism Received view / Semantic view of theories Scientific realism / Anti-realism Scientific essentialism Scientific formalism Scientific skepticism Scientism Structuralism Uniformitarianism Vitalism

Philosophy of

Physics

thermal and statistical Motion

Chemistry Biology Environment Geography Social science Technology

Engineering Artificial intelligence Computer science

Information Mind Psychiatry Psychology Perception Space and time

Related topics

Alchemy Criticism of science Epistemology Faith and rationality History and philosophy of science History of science History of evolutionary thought Logic Metaphysics Pseudoscience Relationship between religion and science Rhetoric of science Sociology of scientific knowledge Sociology of scientific ignorance

Philosophers of science by era

Ancient

Plato Aristotle Stoicism Epicureans

Medieval

Averroes Avicenna Roger Bacon William of Ockham Hugh of Saint Victor Dominicus Gundissalinus Robert Kilwardby

Early modern

Francis Bacon Thomas Hobbes René Descartes Galileo Galilei Pierre Gassendi Isaac Newton David Hume

Classical modern

Immanuel Kant Friedrich Schelling William Whewell Auguste Comte John Stuart Mill Herbert Spencer Wilhelm Wundt Charles Sanders Peirce Wilhelm Windelband Henri Poincaré Pierre Duhem Rudolf Steiner Karl Pearson

Late modern

Alfred North Whitehead Bertrand Russell Albert Einstein Otto Neurath C. D. Broad Michael Polanyi Hans Reichenbach Rudolf Carnap Karl Popper Carl Gustav Hempel W. V. O. Quine Thomas Kuhn Imre Lakatos Paul Feyerabend Jürgen Habermas Ian Hacking Bas van Fraassen Larry Laudan Daniel Dennett

Portal Category

Authority control

WorldCat Identities VIAF: 64141756 LCCN: n79121664 ISNI: 0000 0001 2136 6309 GND: 118530585 SELIBR: 185287 SUDOC: 026851849 BNF: cb13091438g (data) ULAN: 500258979 NLA: 35066534 NDL: 00620634 NKC: jn19990210193 BNE: XX1022

.