Czesław Lejewski
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Czesław Lejewski (Minsk 1913–Doncaster 2001) was a Polish philosopher and
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premise ...
ian, and a member of the Lwow-Warsaw School of Logic. He studied under
Jan Łukasiewicz Jan Łukasiewicz (; 21 December 1878 – 13 February 1956) was a Polish logician and philosopher who is best known for Polish notation and Łukasiewicz logic His work centred on philosophical logic, mathematical logic and history of logic. ...
and Karl Popper in the
London School of Economics The London School of Economics and Political Science (LSE) is a public university, public research university located in London, England and a constituent college of the federal University of London. Founded in 1895 by Fabian Society members Sidn ...
, and
W. V. O. Quine W. may refer to: * SoHo (Australian TV channel) (previously W.), an Australian pay television channel * ''W.'' (film), a 2008 American biographical drama film based on the life of George W. Bush * "W.", the fifth track from Codeine's 1992 EP ''Bar ...
.


"Logic and Existence"

In his paper "Logic and Existence" (1954–55) Lejewski presented a version of free logic. He began by presenting the problem of non-referring nouns, and commended Quine for resisting the temptation to solve the problem by saying that non-referring names are meaningless. Quine's solution, however, was that we must first decide whether our name refers before we know how to treat it logically. Lejewski found this unsatisfactory because there should be a formal distinction between referring and non-referring names. He went on to write, "This state of affairs does not seem to be very satisfactory. The idea that some of our rules of inference should depend on empirical information, which may not be forthcoming, is so foreign to the character of logical inquiry that a thorough re-examination of the two inferences (existential generalization and universal instantiation) may prove worth our while." (parenthesis not Lejewski's). He then elaborates a very creative formal language: Take a domain consisting of a and b, and two signs 'a' and 'b' which refer to these elements. There is one predicate, ''Fx''. There is no need for universal or existential quantification, in the style of Quine in his ''Methods of Logic''. The only possible atomic statements are Fa and Fb. We now introduce new signs but no new elements in the domain. 'c' refers to neither element and 'd' refers to either. Thus, (Fa \lor Fb) \leftrightarrow Fd is true. We now introduce the predicate ''Dx'' which is true for d. We have no reason, here, to contend that (x=c) \land (x\text), and thus to claim that there is something which does not exist. We simply do not have good reason to make existential claims about the referent of every sign, since that would assume that every sign refers. Instead, we should remain agnostic until we have better information. By the stipulations given here, however, we have downright good reason to be atheists about c, and have good reason to still claim \forall x(x\text) to boot. Lejewski calls this account the ''unrestricted'' interpretation. The ''restricted'' interpretation is then the language which does not distinguish between signs and elements, and so is forced to claim \exists x\,(x\text) is true. It is obvious that everything expressible in the unrestricted interpretation is expressible in the restricted interpretation. A generalization to infinite domains and infinite signs is easy. A generalization to infinite predicates needs no explanation. A convenient fact is that this logic can also accommodate the domain of the null set, as quantificational claims will not need to assume an element in the domain. For example, \forall x\,Fx \rightarrow (\exists x\,Fx) will be true on an empty domain using the unrestricted interpretation, where 'c' still does not refer. The proof is that, assuming the antecedent true, we must understand the quantifiers to make no claims about the elements of the domain but only about the signs. He thus suggests that we abandon the interpretation of existential quantification as "there exists an x" and replace it with "for some (sign) x" (parenthesis not Lejewski's). He also suggests that the inference corresponding to existential generalization be termed "particular generalization". Where it is correct to apply the predicate ''Fx'' to every sign in the domain, it is correct to apply the predicate to a given sign in the domain. Thus the conditional is true. (Hence the treatment above that distinguishes existential quantification and the meta-linguistic statement 'x exists'.) Using the restricted interpretation, we see that the claim becomes \forall x(x\text \rightarrow Fx) \rightarrow \exists x\,(x\textFx) which is false. The main antecedent is vacuously true. This is because nothing exists and so, for every sign, the inner antecedent is false, and so vacuously true. The consequent is false, because where the antecedent is true the consequent tells us that something exists. In the null set, this is always false. Quine's response to the problem of the empty set had been that it was a problem never faced in reality, which Lejewski found unsatisfying. Lejewski then goes on to extend this interpretation to the language of inclusion, and presents an axiomatization of an unrestricted logic. This logic was later developed more fully by
Karel Lambert Karel Lambert (born 1928) is an American philosopher and logician at the University of California, Irvine and the University of Salzburg. He has written extensively on the subject of free logic, a term which he coined. Lambert's law Lambert's l ...
, who called the unrestricted interpretation "free logic". Instead of the meta-linguistic 'x exists', Lambert adopted the symbolization E!x, which can be axiomatized without existential quantification."Free Logic and the Concept of Existence" by Karel Lambert, ''Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic'', V.III, numbers 1 and 2, April 1967


Selected works

* "Logic and Existence". ''British Journal for the Philosophy of Science'' 5 (1954-5), pp. 104–119. * "On Leśniewski's Ontology", ''Ratio'' 1 (1958), pp. 150–176. * "On Implicational Definitions", ''Studia Logica'' 8 (1958), pp. 189–205. * "A Re-Examination of the Russellian Theory of Descriptions", ''Philosophy'' 35 (1960), pp. 14–29. * "On Prosleptic Syllogisms", ''Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic'' 2 (1961), pp. 158–176. * "Aristotle's syllogistic and its extensions",''Synthese'' 15 (1963), pp. 125–154. * "Ancient Logic", section in Prior, A. N., "Logic, History of, " '' The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', 1967, vol. 4, pp. 513–520. * "Jan Łukasiewicz", section in ''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', 1967, Vol. 5, pp. 104–107. * "On Prosleptic Premisses", ''Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic'' 17 (1976), pp. 1–18. * "Accommodating the informal notion of class within the framework of Lesniewski's Ontology", ''Dialectica'' 39 (1985), pp, 217-241. * "Formalization of functionally complete propositional calculus with the functor of implication as the only primitive term", ''Studia Logica'' 48 (1989), pp. 479–494.


References


External links


Czesław Lejewski Collection
University of Leeds {{DEFAULTSORT:Lejewski, Czeslaw 1913 births 2001 deaths Polish logicians 20th-century Polish philosophers Academics of the Victoria University of Manchester