Chittamatrin
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Yogachara ( sa, योगाचार, IAST: '; literally "yoga practice"; "one whose practice is yoga") is an influential tradition of Buddhist philosophy and psychology emphasizing the study of cognition, perception, and consciousness through the interior lens of meditative and yogic practices. It is also variously termed ''Vijñānavāda'' (the doctrine of consciousness), ''Vijñaptivāda'' (the doctrine of ideas or percepts) or ''Vijñaptimātratā-vāda'' (the doctrine of 'mere representation'), which is also the name given to its major epistemic theory. There are several interpretations of this main theory; while often regarded as a kind of Idealism, critical scholars argue that it is closer to a kind of Phenomenology (philosophy), phenomenology or representationalism, aimed at deconstructing the reification of our perceptions. According to Dan Lusthaus, this tradition developed "an elaborate psychological therapeutic system that mapped out the problems in cognition along with the antidotes to correct them, and an earnest Epistemology, epistemological endeavor that led to some of the most sophisticated work on perception and logic ever engaged in by Buddhists or Indians." The 4th-century Gandharan brothers, Asanga, Asaṅga and Vasubandhu, are considered the classic philosophers and systematizers of this school, along with its other founder, Maitreya-nātha, Maitreya.Siderits, Mark, ''Buddhism as philosophy'', 2017, p. 146. It was associated with Indian Mahayana, Mahayana Buddhism in about the fourth century, but also included non-Mahayana practitioners of the Sautrāntika school. Yogācāra continues to be influential in Tibetan Buddhism and East Asian Buddhism. However, the uniformity of a single assumed "Yogācāra school" has been put into question.


Doctrine

Yogācāra philosophy is primarily meant to aid in the practice of yoga and Buddhist meditation, meditation and thus it also sets forth a systematic analysis of the Mahayana path of Bhavana, mental training (see Bhūmi (Buddhism)#Five Paths, five paths ''pañcamārga''). Yogācārins made use of ideas from previous traditions, such as Prajñāpāramitā and the Sarvastivada, Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma, to develop a new schema for spiritual practice. According to Thomas Kochumuttom, Yogācāra is "meant to be an explanation of experience, rather than a system of ontology". For this reason, Yogācārins developed an Abhidharma literature set within a Mahāyāna framework. In its analysis, Yogācāra works like the ''Sandhinirmocana Sutra, Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra'' developed various core concepts such as ''vijñapti-mātra'', the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' (store consciousness), the turning of the basis (''āśraya-parāvṛtti),'' the three natures (''trisvabhāva''), and Śūnyatā#Yogācāra school, emptiness. They form a complex system, and each can be taken as a point of departure for understanding Yogācāra.Muller, A. Charles (2005; 2007). ''Wonhyo's Reliance on Huiyuan in his Exposition of the Two Hindrances.'' (Published in Reflecting Mirrors: Perspectives on Huayan Buddhism. Imre Hamar, ed., Harrassowitz Verlag, 2007, p. 281-295.) Source

(accessed: April 7, 2010)


The doctrine of ''Vijñapti-mātra''

One of the main features of Yogācāra philosophy is the concept of ''vijñapti-mātra''. It is often used interchangeably with the term ''citta-mātra'', but they have different meanings. The standard translation of both terms is "consciousness-only" or "mind-only." Several modern researchers object to this translation, and the accompanying label of "absolute idealism" or "idealistic monism". A better translation for ''vijñapti-mātra'' is ''representation-only'', while an alternative translation for ''citta'' (mind, thought) ''mātra'' (only, exclusively) has not been proposed.


Origins

According to Lambert Schmithausen, the earliest surviving appearance of this term is in chapter 8 of the ''Sandhinirmocana Sutra, Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra,'' which has only survived in Tibetan and Chinese translations that differ in syntax and meaning. The passage is depicted as a response by the Buddha to a question which asks "whether the images or replicas (''*pratibimba'') which are the object (''*gocara'') of meditative concentration (*''samadhi''), are different/separate (''*bhinna'') from the contemplating mind (''*citta'') or not." The Buddha says they are not different, "Because these images are ''vijñapti-mātra."'' The text goes on to affirm that the same is true for objects of ordinary perception. Regarding existing Sanskrit sources, the term appears in the first verse of Vasubandhu's Vimśatikāvijñaptimātratāsiddhi, ''Vimśatikā'', which is a ''locus classicus'' of the idea, it states:Siderits, Mark, ''Buddhism as philosophy'', 2017, p. 149.
''Vijñaptimātram evaitad asad arthāvabhāsanāt yathā taimirikasyāsat keśa candrādi darśanam.'' "This [world] is ''vijñaptimātra'', since it manifests itself as an unreal object (''artha''), just like the case of those with cataracts seeing unreal hairs in the moon and the like."
According to Mark Siderits, what Vasubandhu means here is that we are only ever aware of mental images or impressions which manifest themselves as external objects, but "there is actually no such thing outside the mind." The term also appears in Asanga, Asaṅga's classic Yogācāra work, the ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha'' (no Sanskrit original, trans. from Tibetan)'':''
These representations (''vijñapti'') are mere representations (''vijñapti-mātra''), because there is no [corresponding] thing/object (''artha'')...Just as in a dream there appear, even without a thing/object (''artha''), just in the mind alone, forms/images of all kinds of things/objects like visibles, sounds, smells, tastes, tangibles, houses, forests, land, and mountains, and yet there are no [such] things/objects at all in that [place]. ''MSg II.6''
The term is sometimes used as a synonym with ''citta-mātra'' (mere ''citta''), which is also used as a name for the school that suggests Idealism. Lambert Schmithausen, Schmithausen writes that the first appearance of this term is in the Pratyutpanna Samādhi Sūtra, ''Pratyupanna samadhi sutra'', which states:
This (or: whatever belongs to this) triple world (*''traidhātuka'') is nothing but mind (or thought: *''cittamatra''). Why? Because however I imagine things, that is how they appear.


Interpretations of ''vijñapti-mātra''


=Idealism

= According to Bruce Cameron Hall, the interpretation of this doctrine as a form of Subjective idealism, subjective or absolute idealism has been "the most common "outside" interpretation of ''Vijñānavāda'', not only by modern writers, but by its ancient opponents, both Hindu and Buddhist."Cameron Hall, Bruce, ''The Meaning of Vijnapti in Vasubandhu's Concept of Mind,'' JIABS Vol 9, 1986, Number 1, p. 7. Scholars such as Saam Trivedi argue that Yogācāra is similar to Idealism (closer to a Transcendental idealism, Kantian epistemic idealism), though they note that it is its own unique form and that it might be confusing to categorize it as such. Paul Williams, citing Griffiths, writes that it could be termed "dynamic idealism". Sean Butler argues for the idealistic nature of Yogācāra, noting that there are numerous similarities between Yogācāra and the systems of Immanuel Kant, Kant and George Berkeley, Berkeley. Jay L. Garfield, Jay Garfield also argues that Yogācāra is "akin to the idealisms defended by such Western philosophers as Berkeley, Kant and Arthur Schopenhauer, Schopenhauer." Jonathan Gold writes that the Yogācāra thinker Vasubandhu can be said to be an idealist (similar to Immanuel Kant, Kant), in the sense that for him, everything in experience as well as its causal support is mental, and thus he gives causal priority to the mental. At the same time however, this is only in the conventional realm, since "mind" is just another concept and true reality for Vasubandhu is ineffable, "an inconceivable 'thusness' (''Tathātā, tathatā'')." Indeed, the Vimśatikāvijñaptimātratāsiddhi, ''Vimśatikā'' states that the very idea of ''vijñapti-mātra'' must ''also'' be understood to be itself a self-less construction and thus ''vijñapti-mātra'' is not the ultimate truth (''Two truths doctrine, paramārtha-satya'') in Yogācāra. Thus according to Gold, while Vasubandhu's ''vijñapti-mātra'' can be said to be a “conventionalist idealism”, it is to be seen as unique and different from Western forms, especially Hegelianism, Hegelian Absolute idealism, Absolute Idealism.


=Mere representation

= Other scholars note that it is a mistake to conflate the two terms ''vijñapti-mātra'' and ''citta-mātra''. While the standard translations for both ''vijñapti-mātra'' and ''citta-matra'' are often "consciousness only" and "mind-only" (signifying an Idealism, Idealistic doctrine), objections are raised to this conflation, as well as to Idealism, Idealistic interpretation. Different alternative translations for ''vijñapti-mātra'' have been proposed, such as ''representation-only, ideation-only, impressions-only'' and ''perception-only''.Wayman, Alex, ''A Defense of Yogācāra Buddhism'', Philosophy East and West, Vol. 46, No. 4 (Oct., 1996), pp. 447-476. David Kalupahana argues that ''citta-mātra'' signifies a metaphysical reification of mind into an absolute, while ''vijñapti-mātra'' refers to a certain epistemological approach. According to Kalupahana, the term ''vijñapti-mātra'' replaced the "more metaphysical" term ''citta-mātra'' used in the ''Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra''. The ''Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra'' "appears to be one of the earliest attempts to provide a philosophical justification for the Absolutism that emerged in Mahayana in relation to the concept of Buddha". It uses the term ''citta-mātra'', which means properly "thought-only". By using this term it develops an ''ontology'', in contrast to the ''epistemology'' of the term vijñapti-mātra. The ''Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra'' equates ''citta'' and the absolute. According to Kochumuttom, this is not the way Yogacara uses the term vijñapti: According to Kochumuttom, "the absolute state is defined simply as emptiness, namely the emptiness of subject-object distinction. Once thus defined as emptiness (''sunyata''), it receives a number of synonyms, none of which betray idealism." According to Thomas Kochumuttom, Yogācāra is a ''realistic pluralism''. It does not deny the existence of individual beings; what it does deny is: ''Vijñapti-mātra'' then means "mere representation of consciousness": Alex Wayman notes that one's interpretation of Yogācāra will depend on how the qualifier ''mātra'' is to be understood in this context, and he objects to interpretations which claim that Yogācāra rejects the external world altogether, preferring translations such as "amounting to mind" or "mirroring mind" for ''citta-mātra''. For Wayman, what this doctrine means is that "the mind has only a report or representation of what the sense organ had sensed." The representationalist interpretation is also supported by Stefan Anacker and Thomas A. Kochumuttom, modern translators of Vasubandhu's works.


=Soterological phenomenology

= According to Dan Lusthaus, the ''vijñapti-mātra'' theory is closer in some ways to Western Phenomenology (philosophy), Phenomenological theories and Epistemological idealism, Epistemological Idealism or Transcendental idealism, but it is not an ontological idealism because Yogācāra rejects the construction of Metaphysics, metaphysical or Ontology, ontological theories.Lusthaus, Dan, What is and isn't Yogacara, http://www.acmuller.net/yogacara/articles/intro.html Moreover, Western idealism lacks any counterpart to karma, samsara or awakening, which are central for Yogācāra. Regarding ''vijñapti-mātra,'' Lusthaus translates it as "nothing but conscious construction" and states it is: Lusthaus further explains that this reification of cognitions aids in constructing the notion of a solid self, which can appropriate external 'things'. Yogacara then offers the analysis and meditative means to negate this reification, thereby also negating the notion of a solid self: Therefore, when Yogācāra discusses cognitive objects (''viṣaya''), they are analyzing cognition, and its constructions. While Yogācāra posits that cognitive objects are real, it denies "''arthas''" (objects of intentionality or "a telos toward which an act of consciousness intends") which are "outside the cognitive act in which it is that which is intended." So according to Lusthaus, "Yogacarins don't claim that nothing whatsoever exists outside the mind" and "Consciousness enjoys no transcendent status, nor does it serve as a metaphysical foundation. Consciousness is real by virtue of its facticity -- the fact that sentient beings experience cognitions -- and not because of an ontological primacy." In this way, instead of offering an ontological theory, Yogācāra focuses on understanding and eliminating the underlying tendencies (''anuśaya'') that lead to clinging to ontological constructions, which are just cognitive projections (''pratibimba'', ''parikalpita'').


Arguments in defense of ''vijñapti-mātra''

Yogācāra philosophers were aware of the objections that could be brought against their doctrine. Vasubandhu's Vimśatikāvijñaptimātratāsiddhi, ''Vimśatikā'' mentions three and refutes them: # The problem of spatio-temporal determination or non-arbitrariness in regard to place and time. There must be some external basis for our experiences since experiences of any particular object are not occurrent everywhere and at every time. Vasubandhu explains this by using the dream argument, which shows how a world created by mind can still ''seem'' to have spatio-temporal localization. # The problem of multiple minds experiencing the same object or inter-subjective agreement. Vasubandhu counters that mass hallucinations (such as those said to occur to hungry ghosts) caused by the fact they share similar karma, show that inter-subjective agreement is possible without positing real external objects. # Hallucinations have no pragmatic results, efficacy or causal functions and thus can be determined to be unreal, but entities we generally accept as being "real" have actual causal results that cannot be of the same class as hallucinations. Against this claim, Vasubandhu argues that waking life is the same as in a dream, where objects have pragmatic results within the very rules of the dream. He also uses the example of a wet dream to show that mental content can have causal efficacy outside of a dream. According to Mark Siderits, after disposing of these objections, Vasubandhu believes he has shown that ''vijñapti-mātra'' is just as good at explaining and predicting the relevant phenomena of experience as any theory of Philosophical realism, realism that posits external objects. Therefore, he then applies the Indian philosophical principle termed the "Principle of Lightness" (which is similar to Occam's razor, Occam's Razor) to rule out realism since ''vijñapti-mātra'' is the simpler and "lighter" theory, "that is, the theory that posits the least number of unobservable entities." Another objection that Vasubandhu answers is that of how one person can influence another's experiences, if everything arises from mental karmic seeds in one's mind stream. Vasubandhu argues that "impressions can also be caused in a mental stream by the occurrence of a distinct impression in another suitably linked mental stream."Siderits, Mark, ''Buddhism as philosophy'', 2017, p. 170. As Siderits notes, this account can explain how it is possible to influence or even totally disrupt (murder) another mind, even if there is no physical medium or object in existence, since a suitably strong enough intention in one mind stream can have effects on another mind stream. From the ''vijñapti-mātra'' position, it is easier to posit a mind to mind causation than to have to explain mind to body causation, which the realist must do. However, Siderits then goes on to question whether Vasubandhu's position is indeed "lighter" since he must make use of multiple interactions between different minds to take into account an intentionally created artifact, like a pot. Since we can be aware of a pot even when we are not "linked" to the potter's intentions (even after the potter is dead), a more complex series of mental interactions must be posited. In disproving the possibility of external objects, Vasubandhu's Vimśatikāvijñaptimātratāsiddhi, ''Vimśatikā'' also attacks Atomism#Indian atomism, Indian theories of atomism and Physical property, property particulars as incoherent on Mereology, mereological grounds.Gold, Jonathan C., "Vasubandhu", ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/vasubandhu/ Vasubandhu also explains why it is Soteriology, soteriologically important to get rid of the idea of really existing external objects. According to Siderits, this is because:
When we wrongly imagine there to be external objects we are led to think in terms of the duality of 'grasped and grasper', of what is 'out there' and what is ' in here' - in short, of external world and self. Coming to see that there is no external world is a means, Vasubandhu thinks, of overcoming a very subtle way of believing in an 'I'... once we see why physical objects can't exist we will lose all temptation to think there is a true ' me' within. There are really just impressions, but we superimpose on these the false constructions of object and subject. Seeing this will free us from the false conception of an 'I'.Siderits, Mark, ''Buddhism as philosophy'', 2017, p. 175.
Siderits notes how Immanuel Kant, Kant had a similar notion, that is, without the idea of an objective mind independent world, one cannot derive the concept of a subjective "I". But Kant drew the opposite conclusion to Vasubandhu, since he held that we must believe in an enduring subject, and thus, also believe in external objects.


Analysis of Consciousness

Yogācāra gives a detailed explanation of the workings of the mind and the way it constructs the reality we experience.


Eight consciousnesses

According to Lusthaus, "the most famous innovation of the Yogācāra school was the doctrine of eight consciousnesses." These "eight bodies of consciousnesses" (''aṣṭa vijñānakāyāḥ'') are: the five sense-consciousnesses, ''citta'' (mentality), Manas-vijnana, ''manas'' (self-consciousness), and the storehouse or substratum consciousness (Sanskrit, Skt: ''ālayavijñāna'').Williams, Paul (2008). ''Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations'', Routledge, p. 97. Traditional Buddhist descriptions of consciousness taught just the first six ''vijñānas'', each corresponding to a sense base (''ayatana'') and having their own sense objects. Standard Buddhist doctrine held that these Skandha#Eighteen Dhātus and Four Paramatthas, eighteen ''"dhatus"'' or components of experience, "exhaust the full extent of everything in the universe, or more accurately, the sensorium." These six consciousnesses are also not substantial entities, but a series of events, arising and vanishing, stretching back from beginningless (''anadi'') time. Buddhist Abhidharma expanded and developed this basic model and Yogācāra responded by rearranging these into their own schema which had three novel forms of consciousness. The sixth consciousness, ''mano-vijñāna,'' was seen as the surveyor of the content of the five senses as well as of mental content like thoughts and ideas. The seventh consciousness developed from the early Buddhist concept of ''Manas (early Buddhism), manas,'' and was seen as the defiled mentation (''kliṣṭa-manas'') which is obsessed with notions of "self". According to Paul Williams (Buddhist studies scholar), Paul Williams, this consciousness "takes the substratum consciousness as its object and mistakenly considers the substratum consciousness to be a true Self."


''Ālaya-vijñāna''

The eighth consciousness, ''ālaya-vijñāna'' (storehouse or repository consciousness), was defined as the storehouse of all karmic seeds, where they gradually matured until ripe, at which point they manifested as karmic consequences. Because of this, it is also called the "mind which has all the seeds" (''sarvabījakam cittam''), as well as the "basic consciousness" (''mūla-vijñāna'') and the "appropriating consciousness" (''ādānavijñāna''). According to the ''Sandhinirmocana Sutra, Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra,'' this kind of consciousness ''underlies'' and ''supports'' the six types of manifest awareness, all of which occur simultaneously with the ''ālaya.''Waldron, William S. The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the context of Indian Buddhist Thought. Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism, 2003, pp 94-95. William S. Waldron sees this "simultaneity of all the modes of cognitive awareness" as the most significant departure of Yogācāra theory from traditional Buddhist models of ''vijñāna,'' which were "thought to occur solely in conjunction with their respective sense bases and epistemic objects." As noted by Lambert Schmithausen, Schmithausen, the ''ālaya-vijñāna,'' being a kind of vijñāna, has an object as well (as all vijñāna has intentionality). That object is the sentient being's surrounding world, that is to say, the "receptable" or "container" (''bhājana'') world. This is stated in the 8th chapter of the ''Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra,'' which states that the ''ādānavijñāna'' is characterized by "an unconscious (or not fully conscious?) steady perception (or "representation") of the Receptacle (''*asaṃvidita-sthira-bhājana-vijñapti'')." The ''ālaya-vijñāna'' is also what experiences Rebirth (Buddhism), rebirth into future lives and what descents into the womb to appropriate the fetal material. Therefore, the ''ālaya-vijñāna's'' holding on to the body's sense faculties and "profuse imaginings" (''Conceptual proliferation, prapañca'') are the two appropriations which make up the "kindling" or "fuel" (lit. ''upādāna'') that Saṃsāra, samsaric existence depends upon. Yogācāra thought thus holds that being unaware of the processes going on in the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' is an important element of ignorance (''Avidyā (Buddhism), avidya''). The ''ālaya'' is also individual, so that each person has their own ''ālaya-vijñāna,'' which is an ever changing process and therefore not a permanent self. According to Williams, this consciousness "seen as a defiled form of consciousness (or perhaps sub- or unconsciousness), is personal, individual, continually changing and yet serving to give a degree of personal identity and to explain why it is that certain karmic results pertain to this particular individual. The seeds are momentary, but they give rise to a perfumed series which eventually culminates in the result including, from seeds of a particular type, the whole ‘inter-subjective’ phenomenal world." Also, Asanga and Vasubandhu write that the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' ‘ceases’ at awakening, becoming transformed into a pure consciousness. According to Waldron, while there were various similar concepts in other Buddhist Abhidharma schools which sought to explain karmic continuity, the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' is the most comprehensive and systematic. Waldron notes that the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' concept was probably influenced by these theories, particularly the Sautrāntika, Sautrantika theory of seeds and Vasumitra (Buddhism), Vasumitra's theory of a subtle form of mind ''(suksma-citta)''.


Transformations of consciousness

For David Kalupahana, Kalupahana, this classification of ''ālayavijñāna'' and ''manas'' as an eighth and seventh category of consciousness is based on a misunderstanding of Vasubandhu's ''Triṃśikaikā-kārikā'' by later adherents. According to scholar Roger R. Jackson, a "'fundamental unconstructed awareness' (''mūla-nirvikalpa-jñāna'')" is "described [...] frequently in Yogacara literature.", According to Kalupahana, instead of positing additional consciousnesses, the Triṃśikaikā-kārikā describes the ''transformations'' of this consciousness: These transformations are threefold according to Kalupahana. The first is the ''ālaya'' and its seeds, which is the flow or stream of consciousness, without any of the usual projections on top of it. The second transformation is ''manana'', self-consciousness or "Self-view, self-confusion, self-esteem and self-love". It is "thinking" about the various perceptions occurring in the stream of consciousness". The ''ālaya'' is defiled by this self-interest. The third transformation is ''visaya-vijñapti'', the "''concept'' of the object". In this transformation the ''concept'' of objects is created. By creating these concepts human beings become "susceptible to grasping after the object" as if it were a real object (''sad artha'') even though it is just a conception (''vijñapti''). A similar perspective which emphasizes Yogācāra's continuity with Early Buddhist schools, early Buddhism is given by Walpola Rahula. According to Rahula, all the elements of this theory of consciousness with its three layers of ''Vijñāna'' are already found in the Pāli Canon:


The Three Natures and Emptiness

Yogācāra works often define three basic modes or "natures" (''Svabhava, svabhāva'') of experience. Jonathan Gold explains that "the three natures are all one reality viewed from three distinct angles. They are the appearance, the process, and the emptiness of that same apparent entity." According to Paul Williams (Buddhist studies scholar), Paul Williams, "all things which can be known can be subsumed under these Three Natures." Since this schema is Yogācāra's systematic explanation of the Buddhist doctrine of emptiness (''śūnyatā''), each of the three natures are also explained as having a lack of own-nature (''niḥsvabhāvatā'')." Vasubandhu's ''Trisvabhāva-nirdeśa'' gives a brief definition of these three natures:
"What appears is the dependent. How it appears is the fabricated. Because of being dependent on conditions. Because of being only fabrication. The eternal non-existence of the appearance as it is appears: That is known to be the perfected nature, because of being always the same. What appears there? The unreal fabrication. How does it appear? As a dual self. What is its nonexistence? That by which the nondual reality is there."
In detail, three natures (''trisvabhāva'') are:Williams (2008), p. 90. #''Parikalpita-svabhāva'' (the "fully conceptualized" nature). This is the "imaginary" or "constructed" nature, wherein things are incorrectly comprehended based on conceptual construction, through the activity of language and through attachment and erroneous discrimination which attributes intrinsic existence to things. According to the ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha'', it also refers to the appearance of things in terms of subject-object dualism (literally "grasper" and "grasped"). The conceptualized nature is the world of everyday unenlightened people, i.e. Saṃsāra, samsara, and it is false and empty, it does not really exist (see ''Triṃśikā'' v. 20). According to Xuanzang, Xuanzang's ''Cheng Weishi Lun'', "there is the ''absence of an existential nature by its very defining characteristic"'' (''lakṣana-niḥsvabhāvatā''). Because these conceptualized natures and distinct characteristics (''lakṣana'') are wrongly imputed not truly real, "they are like mirages and blossoms in the sky." #''Paratantra-svabhāva'' (literally, "other dependent"), which is the dependently originated nature of dharmas, or the causal flow of phenomena which is erroneously confused into the conceptualized nature. According to Williams, it is "''the basis'' for the erroneous partition into supposedly intrinsically existing subjects and objects which marks the conceptualized nature." Jonathan Gold writes that it is "the causal ''process'' of the thing’s fabrication, the causal story that brings about the thing’s apparent nature." This basis is considered to be an ultimately existing (''Paramārtha-satya, paramārtha'') basis in classical Yogācāra (see ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha,'' 2:25).Williams (2008), pp. 90-91. However, as Xuanzang notes, this nature is also empty in that there is an "''absence of an existential nature in conditions that arise and perish"'' (''utpatti-niḥsvabhāvatā''). That is, the events in this causal flow, while "seeming to have real existence of their own" are actually like magical illusions since "they are said to only be hypothetical and not really exist on their own." As Siderits writes "to the extent that we are thinking of it at all - even if only as the non-dual flow of impressions-only - we are still conceptualizing it." #''Pariniṣpanna-svabhāva'' (literally, "fully accomplished"): the "consummated nature" or the true nature of things, the experience of Suchness or Thatness (''Tathātā'') discovered in meditation unaffected by conceptualization or language. It is defined as "''the complete absence'', in the dependent nature, of objects – that is, the objects of the conceptualized nature" (see ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha,'' 2:4). What this refers to is that empty non-dual experience which has been stripped of the duality of the constructed nature through yogic praxis. According to Williams, this is "''what has to be known'' for enlightenment" and Siderits defines it as "just pure seeing without any attempt at conceptualization or interpretation. Now this is also empty, but only of itself as an interpretation. That is, this mode of cognition is devoid of all concepts, and so is empty of being of the nature of the perfected. About it nothing can be said or thought, it is just pure immediacy." According to Xuanzang, it has the "''absence of any existential nature of ultimate meaning"'' (''paramārtha-niḥsvabhāvatā'') since it is "completely free from any clinging to entirely imagined speculations about its identity or purpose. Because of this, it is conventionally said that it does not exist. However, it is also not entirely without a real existence." The central meaning of emptiness in Yogācāra is a twofold "absence of duality." The first element of this is the unreality of any ''conceptual duality'' such as "physical" and "non-physical", "self" and "other". To define something conceptually is to divide the world into what it is and what it is not, but the world is a causal flux that does not accord with conceptual constructs. The second element of this is a ''perceptual duality'' between the sensorium and its objects, between what is "external" and "internal", between subject (''grāhaka,'' literally "grasper") and object (''grāhya,'' "grasped"). This is also an unreal superimposition, since there is really no such separation of inner and outer, but an interconnected causal stream of mentality which is falsely divided up. An important difference between the Yogācāra conception of emptiness and the Madhyamaka conception is that in classical Yogācāra, emptiness ''does exist'' and so does consciousness, while Madhyamaka refuses to endorse such existential statements. The ''Madhyanta-vibhaga-karika, Madhyāntavibhāga'' for example, states "there exists the imagination of the unreal (''abhūta-parikalpa''), there is no duality, but there is emptiness, even in this there is that," which indicates that even though the dualistic imagination is unreal and empty, it does exist.King, Richard, Early Yogācāra and its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School, Philosophy East & West Volume 44, Number 4 October 1994 pp. 659-683. Contra Madhyamaka, which was criticized by Vasubandhu and Asanga, Asaṅga for being nihilistic (see ''Vimśatikāvijñaptimātratāsiddhi, Vimśatikā'' v. 10'')'', the Yogācāra position is that there is something that exists (the ''paratantra-svabhāva'' that is mere ''vijñapti''), and that it is empty. The ''Yogacarabhumi-sastra, Bodhisattvabhūmi'' likewise argues that it is only logical to speak of emptiness if there is ''something'' (i.e. ''dharmatā'') that is empty. Thus Asanga, Asaṅga speaks of emptiness as "the non-existence of the self, and the existence of the no-self." The Yogācāra school also gave special significance to the ''Lesser Discourse on Emptiness'' of the ''Āgama (Buddhism), Āgamas''. It is often quoted in later Yogācāra texts as a true definition of emptiness.


Karma

An explanation of the Buddhist doctrine of Karma in Buddhism, karma (action) is central to Yogācāra, and the school sought to explain important questions such as how moral actions can have effects on individuals long after that action was done, that is, how karmic causality works across temporal distances. Previous Abhidharma Buddhist schools like the Sautrāntika, Sautrantika had developed theories of karma based on the notion of "seeds" (''Bīja, bījā'') in the mind stream, which are unseen karmic habits (good and bad) which remain until they meet with the necessary conditions to manifest. Yogācāra adopts and expanded this theory. Yogācāra then posited the "storehouse consciousness" (Sanskrit: ''ālayavijñāna''), also known as the basal, or eighth consciousness, as the container of the seeds. It simultaneously acts as a storage place for karmic latencies and as a fertile matrix of predispositions that bring karma to a state of fruition. In the Yogācāra system, all experience without exception is said to result from karma or mental intention (Cetanā, ''cetana''), either arising from one's own subliminal seeds or from other minds. For Yogācāra, the seemingly external or dualistic world is merely a "by-product" (''adhipati-phala'') of karma. The term ''vāsanā'' ("perfuming") is also used when explaining karma, and Yogācārins were divided on the issue of whether vāsāna and bija were essentially the same, whether the seeds were the effect of the perfuming, or whether the perfuming simply affected the seeds. The type, quantity, quality and strength of the seeds determine where and how a sentient being will be reborn: one's race, sex, social status, proclivities, bodily appearance and so forth. The conditioning of the mind resulting from karma is called ''Saṅkhāra, saṃskāra''. Vasubandhu's ''Treatise on Action'' (''Karmasiddhiprakaraṇa''), treats the subject of karma in detail from the Yogācāra perspective.


Meditation and awakening

As the name of the school suggests, meditation practice is central to the Yogācāra tradition. Practice manuals prescribe the practice of mindfulness of body, feelings, thoughts and dharmas in oneself and others, out of which a revolutionary and radically transformative understanding of the non-duality of self and other is said to arise. This process is referred to as ''āśraya-parāvṛtti'', "overturning the Cognitive Basis", or "revolution of the basis", which refers to "overturning the conceptual projections and imaginings which act as the base of our cognitive actions." This event is seen as the transformation of the basic mode of cognition into ''Jnana, jñāna'' (knowledge, direct knowing), which is seen as a non-dual knowledge that is non-conceptual (''nirvikalpa''), i.e., "devoid of interpretive overlay". When this occurs, the eight consciousnesses come to an end and are replaced by direct knowings. According to Lusthaus:
Overturning the Basis turns the five sense consciousnesses into immediate cognitions that accomplish what needs to be done (''kṛtyānuṣṭhāna-jñāna''). The sixth consciousness becomes immediate cognitive mastery (''pratyavekṣaṇa-jñāna''), in which the general and particular characteristics of things are discerned just as they are. This discernment is considered nonconceptual (''nirvikalpa-jñāna''). ''Manas'' becomes the immediate cognition of equality (''samatā-jñāna''), equalizing self and other. When the Warehouse Consciousness finally ceases it is replaced by the Great Mirror Cognition (''Mahādarśa-jñāna'') that sees and reflects things just as they are, impartially, without exclusion, prejudice, anticipation, attachment, or distortion. The grasper-grasped relation has ceased. ..."purified" cognitions all engage the world in immediate and effective ways by removing the self-bias, prejudice, and obstructions that had prevented one previously from perceiving beyond one's own narcissistic consciousness. When consciousness ends, true knowledge begins. Since enlightened cognition is nonconceptual its objects cannot be described.


Five Categories of Beings

One of the more controversial teachings espoused by the Yogacara school was an extension of the teachings on seeds and store-conscious. Based on the ''Sandhinirmocana Sutra, Saṃdhinirmocana Sūtra'' and the ''Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra'', the Yogacara school posited that sentient beings had innate seeds that would make them capable of achieving a particular state of enlightenment and no other. Thus, beings were categorized in 5 ways: # Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to achieve full Buddhahood (i.e. Bodhisattva path). # Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to achieve the state of a pratyekabuddha (private Buddha). # Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to achieve the state of an arhat. # Beings whose innate seeds had an indeterminate nature, and could potentially be any of the above. # Beings whose innate seeds were incapable of achieving enlightenment ever because they lacked any wholesome seeds. The fifth class of beings, the Icchantika, were described in various Mahayana sutras as being incapable of achieving Enlightenment, unless in some cases through the aid of a Buddha or Bodhisattva. Nevertheless, the notion was highly criticized by adherents of the Lotus Sutra (e.g. the Tiantai school) and its teaching of universal Buddhahood. This tension appears in East Asian Buddhist history.


Alikākāravāda and Satyākāravāda

An important debate about the reality of mental appearances within Yogācāra led to its later subdivision into two systems of Alikākāravāda (Tibetic languages, Tib. ''rnam rdzun pa'', False Aspectarians) and Satyākāravāda (''rnam bden pa'', True Aspectarians) or "Aspectarians" (''ākāra'') and "Non-Aspectarians" (''anākāra''). The core issue is whether appearances or “aspects” (''rnam pa, ākāra'') of objects in the mind are treated as true (''bden pa, satya'') or false (''rdzun pa, alika''). While this division did not exist in the works of the early Yogācāra philosophers, tendencies similar to these views can be discerned in the works of Yogacara thinkers like Dharmapala of Nalanda, Dharmapala (c. 530–561?) and Sthiramati (c. 510–570?). According to Yaroslav Komarovski the distinction is:
Although Yogācāras in general do not accept the existence of an external material world, according to Satyākāravāda its appearances or “aspects” (''rnam pa, ākāra'') reflected in consciousness have a real existence, because they are of one nature with the really existent consciousness, their creator. According to Alikākāravāda, neither external phenomena nor their appearances and/in the minds that reflect them really exist. What exists in reality is only primordial mind (''ye shes, jñāna''), described as self-cognition (''rang rig, Svasaṃvedana, svasamvedana/ svasamvitti'') or individually self-cognizing primordial mind (''so so(r) rang gis rig pa’i ye shes'').


Practice

The main source for the yogic and meditative practices of the Yogācāra school is the encyclopedic ''Yogacarabhumi-sastra, Yogācārabhūmi-Śāstra (''YBh'', Shastra, Treatise on the Foundation for Yoga Practitioners).'' The YBh presents a structured exposition of the Mahāyāna Buddhist path of ''yoga'' (here referring to spiritual practice in general) from a Yogācāra perspective and relies in both Āgama (Buddhism), Āgama/Nikāya texts and Mahayana sutras, Mahāyāna sūtras while also being influenced by Vaibhāṣika Abhidharma. According to some scholars, this text can be traced to communities of ''Yogācāras,'' which initially referred not to a philosophical school, but to groups of meditation specialists whose main focus was Buddhist yoga. Other Yogācāra texts which also discuss meditation and spiritual practice (and show some relationship with the YBh) include the ''Sandhinirmocana Sutra, Saṃdhinirmocanasūtra,'' the ''Madhyanta-vibhaga-karika, Madhyāntavibhāga'', ''Mahayana-sutra-alamkara-karika, Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra, Dharma-dharmata-vibhaga, Dharmadharmatāvibhāga'' and Asanga's ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha''. The main or basic section of the YBh is structured around seventeen ''bhūmis'' (explained in fourteen books), which are "foundations" or "groundings" of meditation, referring to "a field of knowledge that the Yogācāra acolyte ought to master in order to be successful in his or her yoga practice." Some of these are doctrinal topics such as the five ''vijñānas'' (book 1), the ''Eight Consciousnesses, ālayavijñāna'', afflictive cognition ''(kliṣṭaṃ manaḥ),'' the 51 Mental factors (Buddhism), mental factors (book 2)'','' and the defilements (''Kleshas (Buddhism), saṃkleśa,'' book 3). Other books discuss meditation practice proper (books 4, 9, 10, and 12).Timme Kragh 2013 pp. 51, 60–230 The YBh discusses numerous classic Buddhist topics dealing with the spiritual practice of both Śrāvakayāna and Mahāyāna. Some of the main topics are the eight different forms of Dhyāna in Buddhism, dhyāna (meditative absorptions), the three Samadhi, ''samādhis'', different types of liberation (Moksha, ''vimokṣa''), meditative attainments (''samāpatti'') such as ''Dhyāna in Buddhism#Nirodha-Samapatti, nirodhasamāpatti'', the five hindrances (''Five hindrances, nivaraṇa''), the various types of foci (''ālambana'') or 'images' (''nimitta'') used in meditation, the various types of meditation used as antidotes (''pratipakṣa'') against the afflictions (like Maraṇasati, contemplating death, Patikulamanasikara, unattractiveness, impermanence, and suffering), the practice of ''śamatha'' through Samatha, "the nine aspects of resting the mind" (''navākārā cittasthitiḥ''), the practice of insight (''Vipassanā, vipaśyanā''), mindfulness of breathing Anapanasati, (''ānāpānasmṛti''), how to understand the Four Noble Truths, four noble truths, the Bodhipakkhiyādhammā, thirty-seven factors of Awakening (''saptatriṃśad bodhipakṣyā dharmāḥ''), the Brahmavihara, four immeasurables (''apramāṇa''), and how to practice the six Pāramitā, perfections (''pāramitā'').


Bodhisattva practice

The YBh's ''Bodhisattvabhūmi'' section discusses the Yogācāra school's specifically Mahāyāna forms of practice which are tailored to bodhisattvas. These figures are seen as spiritual virtuosos who are working on attaining full Buddhahood through a process that can take hundreds of aeons of spiritual development (and countless rebirths). Unlike other books in the YBh (such as the ''Śrāvakabhūmi'') which are more influenced by Śrāvakayāna texts, the ''Bodhisattvabhūmi'' is strongly influenced by Mahāyāna works, including the ''Prajnaparamita, Prajñāpāramitā'' literature. The aim of the bodhisattva's practice in the ''Bodhisattvabhūmi'' is the wisdom (''Prajnaparamita, prajñā'') which realizes of the inexpressible Ultimate Reality (''tathata'') or the 'thing-in-itself (''vastumatra''), which is essenceless and beyond the duality (''Nondualism, advaya'') of existence (''bhāva'') and non-existence (''abhāva''). The ''Bodhisattvabhūmi'' outlines several practices of bodhisattvas, including the Pāramitā, six perfections (''pāramitā''), the Bodhipakkhiyādhammā, thirty-seven factors of Awakening, and the Brahmavihara, four immeasurables. Two key practices which are unique to bodhisattvas in this text are the four investigations (''paryeṣaṇā'') and the four correct cognitions (''yathābhūtaparijñāna'').


The four investigations

The four investigations and the corresponding four correct cognitions or knowledges which arise from them are: # The investigation of the names [of things] (''nāmaparyeṣaṇā''), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of names just for what they are, which is "just names" (''nāmamātra''). # The investigation of things (''vastuparyeṣaṇā''), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of things. One sees things just for what they are, namely a mere presence or a thing-in-itself (''vastumātra''). One understands that this is apart from all labels and is inexpressible (''nirabhilāpya''). # The investigation of verbal designations suggesting and portraying Svabhava, an intrinsic nature (''svabhāva-prajñapti-paryeṣaṇā''), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of such designations. One sees the designations just for what they are, namely as mere designations (''Prajñaptivāda, prajñaptimātratā''). Thus, one sees the idea of intrinsic nature to be illusory like a hallucination or a dream. # The investigation of verbal designations expressing individuation and differences (''viśeṣaprajñaptiparyeṣaṇā''), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of such designations. One sees the designations just for what they are, namely as mere designations. For example, a thing may be designated as existing or non-existing, but such designations do not apply to true reality or the thing-in-itself. The practice which leads to the realization of the true nature of things is based on the elimination of all Conceptual proliferation, conceptual proliferations (''prapañca'') and ideations (''saṃjñā'') that one superimposes on true reality''.'' This elimination of concepts and ideas is the basic framework applied by the bodhisattva to all meditative practices. The YBh states:
The path of practice shall be correctly followed in order to eliminate that ideation. Through understanding, thoroughly exercised upon all objects of knowledge, [and] by keeping in mind only the ideation that the ideations of all phenomena [are nothing but] adventitious, you should thus repeatedly remove any ideation conducive to the proliferation directed at all phenomena and should consistently dwell on the thing-in-itself by a non-conceptualizing mental state which is focused on grasping only the object perceived without any characteristics. Thus you will obtain the concentration stemming from the lineage of those practicing the pure contemplation of the Tathagata's Supreme Cognition. Even when you practice the meditation on the impurity, you should not relinquish this mental orientation. Likewise when you practice the meditation on friendliness, dependent origination, analysis of elements, mindfulness of breathing, the first absorption and so on up to the station of neither ideation nor non-ideation as well as the bodhisattva's countless meditations, supernatural faculties, contemplations, and attainments, you should not relinquish precisely this mental orientation.
The three ''samādhis'' (meditative absorption and unity) are likewise adapted into this new framework. These three are the emptiness (''śūnyatā''), wishlessness (''Aimlessness (Buddhism), apraṇihita''), and imagelessness (''ānimitta'') ''samādhis.''


The bodhisattva abodes

Another original contribution of the YBh regarding the bodhisattva's practice is the doctrine of the thirteen (or sometimes twelve) abodes or dwellings (''vihāra''). This framework of the bodhisattva's path to awakening is as follows: # The abode of the predisposition (''gotravihāra''). This refers to someone with the predisposition for being a bodhisattva who has not given rise to the resolve for awakening. # The abode of practicing with ascertainment (''adhimukticaryā-vihāra''). This is when a bodhisattva has given rise to the resolve for Awakening and begins to practice, but they have an impure conviction and unstable meditation. # The abode of joy (''pramuditavihāra''). This is when a bodhisattva has pure conviction due to having their first glimpse of direct realization. Their meditation is now vast, uninterrupted, and certain. # The abode higher discipline (''adhiśīlavihāra'') is when discipline is cultivated on the basis of pure conviction. # The abode of higher mind (''adhicittavihāra'') is when one practices all stages of mundane meditation on the basis of higher discipline. # The abode of higher insight associated with the factors of Awakening (''bodhipakṣyapratisaṃyukto 'dhiprajñavihāra'') is the level of analyzing the thirty-seven factors of Awakening in order to realize the truths, beginning with the four foundations of mindfulness. # The abode of higher insight associated with the truths (''satyapratisaṃyukto 'dhiprajñavihāra'') is the level of fully realizing the truths as they are on the basis of having analyzed the factors of Awakening. # The abode of higher insight associated with the arising and ceasing of dependent arising (''pratītyasamutpādapravṛttinivṛttipratisaṃyukto 'dhiprajñavihāra'') is the level wherein the practitioner after having mastered the truths sees how suffering arises when the existential facts are not understood and how suffering comes to an end when the existential facts are understood (through the process of dependent origination). # The abode free from conceptual characteristics where the path is steadily followed intentionally and with effort (''sābhisaṃskāraḥ sābhogo niśchidra-mārgavāhano nirnimitto vihāraḥ''). One constantly cultivates non-conceptual insight into the reality of all phenomena, while applying intention and effort. # The abode free from conceptual characteristics where the path is automatically followed spontaneously and effortlessly (''anabhisaṃskāro 'anābhoga-mārgavāhano nirnimitta eva vihāraḥ''). On this level, the bodhisattva is able to walk the path spontaneously and effortlessly. # The abode of analytical knowledge (''pratisaṃvidvihāra)'' is when the bodhisattva uses their mastery of insight and meditation to teach the Dharma to others using all terms, their meanings, their derivative analyses, and subdivisions. # The highest and perfected bodhisattva abode (''paramaḥ pariniṣ-panno bodhisattvavihāraḥ'') is the culmination of the path, where the highest and complete Awakening is achieved. This life is their final rebirth or their penultimate rebirth before entering nirvāṇa. # The abode of a Tathāgata (''tathāgato vihāraḥ'') is when a bodhisattva becomes a buddha, and performs all the various deeds of a buddha.


History

The Yogācāra, along with the Madhyamaka, is one of the two principal philosophical schools of Indian Mahayana, Mahāyāna Buddhism,Jones, Lindsay (Ed. in Chief)(2005). ''Encyclopedia of Religion''. (2nd Ed.) Volume 14; Masaaki, Hattori (Ed.)(1987 & 2005)"''Yogācāra''": p.9897. USA: Macmillan Reference. (v.14) while the Tathāgatagarbha-thought was also influential.


Origination

One of the earliest texts of this tradition is the Sandhinirmocana Sutra, ''Saṃdhinirmocana Sūtra'' which might be as early as the first or second century CE. It includes new theories such as the basis-consciousness (Eight Consciousnesses, ''ālaya-vijñāna''), and the doctrine of representation-only (''vijñapti-mātra'') and the "three natures" (''trisvabhāva''). However, these theories were not completely new, as they have predecessors in older theories held by previous Buddhist schools, such as the Sautrāntika theory of seeds (''bīja'') and the Sthavira nikāya's Abhidharma theory of the bhavanga. Richard King has also noted the similarity of the Sautantrika representationalism and the Yogacara: The ''Saṃdhinirmocana Sūtra'', as the doctrinal trailblazer of the Yogācāra, inaugurated the paradigm of the Three Turnings of the Wheel of Dharma, with its own tenets in the "third turning". Yogācāra texts are generally considered part of the third turning along with the relevant sutra. (Some traditions categorize this teaching as within the "fourth turning" of the wheel of Dharma.) Moreover, Yogācāra discourse surveys and synthesizes all three turnings and considers itself as the final definitive explanation of Buddhism. The early layers of the ''Yogacarabhumi-sastra, Yogācārabhūmi-śāstra'' also contains very early Yogācāra material, perhaps earlier than the ''Saṃdhinirmocana''. This work is strongly influenced by Sarvastivada, Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma. According to Dan Lusthaus, the orientation of the Yogācāra school is largely consistent with the thinking of the Pāli nikāyas. It frequently treats later developments in a way that realigns them with earlier versions of Buddhist doctrines. One of the agendas of the Yogācāra school was to reorient the complexity of later refinements in Buddhist philosophy to accord with early Buddhist doctrine. However, according to Y. Karunadasa, the exact opposite is true, and the Pali Nikaya's are firmly realist texts that confirm the existence of matter, and the external world:
If we base ourselves on the Pali Nikayas, then we should be compelled to conclude that Buddhism is realistic. There is no explicit denial anywhere of the external world. Nor is there any positive evidence to show that the world is mind-made or simply a projection of subjective thoughts. That Buddhism recognizes the extra-mental existence of matter and the external world is clearly suggested by the texts. Throughout the discourses it is the language of realism that one encounters. The whole Buddhist practical doctrine and discipline, which has the attainment of Nibbana as its final goal, is based on the recognition of the material world and the conscious living beings living therein.


Asaṅga and Vasubandhu

Yogācāra philosophy's systematic exposition owes much to Asanga, Asaṅga (4th c. CE) and Vasubandhu (4th-5th c. CE). Little is known of these figures, but traditional hagiographies state that Asaṅga received Yogācāra teachings from the bodhisattva and future Buddha, Maitreya. Accounts of this are given in the writings of Paramartha, Paramārtha (6th century) and Xuanzang, who reports that important texts like the ''Mahayana-sutra-alamkara-karika, Mahāyāna-sūtra-alaṃkāra'' and the Madhyanta-vibhaga-karika, ''Madhyanta-vibhaga'' are divinely revealed from Maitreya. Asaṅga went on to write many of the key Yogācāra treatises such as the ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha'' and the ''Abhidharma-samuccaya'' as well as other works, although there are discrepancies between the Chinese and Tibetan traditions concerning which works are attributed to him and which to Maitreya. Asaṅga also went on to convert his brother Vasubandhu into the Mahayana, Mahāyāna Yogācāra fold. Vasubandhu had been a top scholar of Sarvastivada#Orthodox Vaibhāṣika doctrines, Sarvāstivāda-Vaibhāṣika and Sautrāntika Abhidharma thought, and the ''Abhidharmakośakārikā'' is his main work which discusses the doctrines of these traditions. Vasubandhu also went on to write important Yogācāra works after his conversion, explaining and defending key Yogācāra doctrines.


Development in India

The Yogācāra school held a prominent position in Indian Buddhism for centuries after the time of the two brothers. According to Dan Lusthaus, after Asaṅga and Vasubandhu, two distinct "wings" of the school developed: # A Buddhist logico-epistemology, logico-epistemic tradition focusing on issues of epistemology and logic, exemplified by such thinkers as Dignāga, Dharmakirti, Dharmakīrti, Śāntarakṣita, and Ratnakīrti; # an Abhidharma, Abhidharmic psychology which refined and elaborated Yogācāra Abhidharma, exemplified by such thinkers as Sthiramati, Dharmapala of Nalanda, Dharmapāla, Śīlabhadra, Xuanzang (Hsüan-tsang), and Vinītadeva. However, the doctrines of the Abhidharmic wing came under increased attack by other Buddhists, especially the notion of ''ālaya-vijñāna'', which was seen as close to the Hindu ideas of ''Ātman (Hinduism), ātman'' and ''prakṛti.'' Because of this, the logical tradition shifted over time to using the term ''citta-santāna'' instead of ''ālaya-vijñāna,'' since it was easier to defend a "stream" ''(santāna)'' of thoughts as a doctrine that did not contradict Anatta, not-self. By the end of the eighth century, the Abhidharma wing had mostly become eclipsed by the logical tradition as well as by a new hybrid school that "combined basic Yogācāra doctrines with ''Buddha-nature, Tathāgatagarbha'' thought." According to Lusthaus:
the ''tathāgatagarbha'' hybrid school was no stranger to the charge of smuggling notions of selfhood into its doctrines, since, for example, it explicitly defined ''tathāgatagarbha'' as "permanent, pleasurable, ''self'', and pure (''nitya, sukha, ātman, śuddha'')." Many ''tathāgatagarbha'' texts, in fact, argue for the acceptance of selfhood (''ātman'') as a sign of higher accomplishment. The hybrid school attempted to conflate ''tathāgatagarbha'' with the ''ālaya-vijñāna''. Key works of the hybrid school include the ''Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra'', ''Ratnagotravibhāga'' (''Uttaratantra''), and in China the ''Awakening of Faith in the Mahayana, Awakening of Faith.''
This syncretic form of Yogācāra-Tathāgatagarbha became extremely influential in both East Asia and Tibet. During the sixth and seventh centuries, various forms of Yogācāra dominated the Chinese Buddhist landscape such as orthodox forms and hybrid Buddha-nature, Tathāgatagarbha forms. There were feuds between these two approaches. The translator Bodhiruci (6th century CE) for example, took an orthodox approach while the Ratnamati was attracted to Buddha-nature, Tathāgatagarbha thought and sought to translate texts like the Ten Stages Sutra, Dasabhumika sutra in conformity with his understanding. Their disagreement on this issue led to the end of their collaboration as co-translators. The translator Paramartha, Paramārtha is another example of a hybrid thinker. He promoted a new theory that said there was a ninth form of consciousness, the ''amala-vijñāna'' (a pure ''vijñāna''), which is revealed once the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' is eliminated. He also associated his theory with Tathāgatagarbha ideas. According to Lusthaus, Xuanzang's travels to India and his composition of the ''Cheng Weishi Lun'' was an attempt to return to a more "orthodox" and "authentic" Indian Yogācāra and thus put to rest the debates and confusions in the Chinese Yogācāra of his time. The ''Cheng Weishi Lun'' returns to the use of the theory of seeds instead of the ''tathāgatagarbha'' to explain the phenomena that ''tathāgatagarbha'' is supposed to explain (that is, the potentiality for Buddhahood).Lusthaus, Dan, ''Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih Lun,'' Routledge, 2014, pp. 8-10. However, Lusthaus writes that in the eighth century, this 'schism' was finally settled "in favor of a hybrid version, which became definitive for all subsequent forms of East Asian Buddhism." Later Chinese thinkers like Fazang, Fa-Tsang would thus criticize Xuanzang for failing to teach the ''tathāgatagarbha'' in his system. Karl Brunnhölzl notes that this syncretic tendency also existed in India, but that:
it seems that Yogācāra masters generally adopted the notion of ''tathāgatagarbha'' in accordance with the Ratnagotravibhāga, Uttaratantra only later, when Vajrayana, Buddhist tantra with its very similar notions of ground tantra and all beings’ primordially being buddhas was flourishing. Examples of such Yogācāras include Jñanasrimitra, Jñānaśrīmitra, Ratnākaraśānti, and the authors of several commentaries on the Prajnaparamita, ''prajñaparamita'' from a Yogācāra perspective.


Yogācāra and Madhyamaka

According to Tibetan sources, this school was in protracted Dialectic#Buddhist dialectic, dialectic with the Madhyamaka tradition. However, there is disagreement among contemporary Western and traditional Buddhist scholars about the degree to which they were opposed, if at all. The main difference deals with issues of existence and the nature of emptiness. While Madhyamaka works state that asserting the existence or non-existence of anything was inappropriate (including Śūnyatā, emptiness), Yogācāra treatises often assert that the dependent nature (''paratantra-svabhāva'') really exists and that Śūnyatā#Yogācāra school, emptiness is an ''actual absence'' that also exists. For example, the ''Madhyanta-vibhaga-karika, Madhyāntavibhāga'' clearly asserts that "the imagination of the nonexistent [''abhūta-parikalpa''] exists. In it duality does not exist. Emptiness, however, exists in it." Classical Yogācāra thinkers like Asaṅga and Vasubandhu critiqued Madhyamikas who "adhere to non-existence" (''nāstikas, vaināśkas'') because they saw them as straying into nihilism (''ucchedavāda'').King, Richard, Early Yogācāra and its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School, Philosophy East & West Volume 44, Number 4 October 1994 PP.659-683. They held that there was really something which could be said to "exist", that is, ''vijñapti,'' and that was what is described as being "empty" their system. The position that Yogācāra and Madhyamaka were in dialectic was expounded by Xuanzang in the 7th century. After a suite of debates with exponents of the Madhyamaka school in India, Xuanzang composed in Sanskrit the no longer extant three-thousand verse treatise ''The Non-difference of Madhyamaka and Yogācāra''.Lusthaus, Dan (undated). ''Xuanzang (Hsüan-tsang)''. Source: (accessed: December 12, 2007) Yogācāra and Madhyamaka philosophers demonstrated two opposing tendencies throughout the history of Buddhist philosophy in India, one which worked to separate and distance the two systems and one tendency which worked towards harmonizing them.Komarovski, Yaroslav'', Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden’s New Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka''. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2011, p. 74. The harmonizing tendency can be seen in the work of philosophers like Jñānagarbha (8th century), his student Śāntarakṣita (8th century) and also in the work of the Yogācāra thinker Ratnākaraśānti, Ratnakaraksanti (c. 1000). These thinkers also saw the Yogācāra ''Alikākāravāda'' ("false aspectarian", those Yogācāras who believe that mental appearances are false or don't ultimately exist) view as the highest. Śāntarakṣita (8th century), whose view was later called "Yogācāra-Svatantrika-Madhyamaka" by the Tibetan tradition, saw the Mādhyamika position as ultimately true and at the same time saw the Yogācāra view as a useful way to relate to conventionalities and progress students more skillfully toward the ultimate.Shantarakshita & Ju Mipham (2005) pp.117-122 This synthesized view between the two positions, and also incorporated the views of valid cognition (''pramana'') from Dignāga and Dharmakirti, Dharmakīrti. Later Tibetan Buddhist thinkers like Sakya Chokden, Shakya Chokden would also work to show the compatibility of the Alikākāravāda sub-school with Madhyamaka, arguing that it is in fact a form of Madhyamaka. Likewise, the Chödrak Gyatso, 7th Karmapa Lama, Seventh Karmapa Chödrak Gyamtso has a similar view which holds that the "profound important points and intents" of the two systems are one. Jamgon Ju Mipham Gyatso, Ju Mipham is also another Tibetan philosopher whose project is aimed as showing the harmony between Yogacara and Madhyamaka, arguing that there is only a very subtle difference between them, being a subtle clinging by Yogacaras to the existence of an "inexpressible, naturally luminous cognition" (''rig pa rang bzhin gyis ’od gsal ba'').


Yogācāra in East Asia

Translations of Indian Yogācāra texts were first introduced to China in the early 5th century CE. Among these was Guṇabhadra's translation of the ''Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra'' in four fascicles, which would also become important in the early history of Chan Buddhism. During the sixth century, the Indian monk and translator Paramartha, Paramārtha (真諦 ; 499–569) widely propagated Yogācāra teachings in China, among monks and laypersons.Paul, Diana. ''Philosophy of Mind in Sixth-Century China: Paramartha's Evolution of Consciousness.'' 1984. pp. 32-33 His translations include the ''Sandhinirmocana Sutra, Saṃdhinirmocana Sūtra'', the ''Madhyanta-vibhaga-karika, Madhyāntavibhāga-kārikā'', the ''Triṃśikā-vijñaptimātratā'', and the ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha''. Xuanzang (fl. c. 602 – 664) is often seen as the most important founder of East Asian Yogācāra. At the age of 33, Xuanzang made a dangerous journey to India in order to study Buddhism and procure texts for later translation.Liu, JeeLoo. ''An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy: From Ancient Philosophy to Chinese Buddhism.'' 2006. p. 220 Dan Lusthaus writes that Xuanzang had come to the conclusion that issues of dispute in Chinese Buddhism could be resolved with the availability of important texts like the ''Yogacarabhumi-sastra, Yogācārabhūmi Śāstra''. Xuanzang spent over ten years in India traveling and studying under various Buddhist masters. Lusthaus writes that during this time, Xuanzang discovered that the manner in which Buddhists understood and interpreted texts was much richer and more varied than the Chinese materials had previously indicated, and drew meaning from a broad cultural context. Xuanzang's teachers included Śīlabhadra, the abbot of Nalanda, Nālandā, who was then 106 years old and who tutored him for 10 years. Upon his return from India, Xuanzang brought with him 657 Buddhist texts, including important Yogācāra works such as the ''Yogācārabhūmi''. He was given government support and many assistants for the purpose of translating these texts into Chinese. As an important contribution to East Asian Yogācāra, Xuanzang composed the ''Cheng Weishi Lun'', or "Discourse on the Establishment of Consciousness Only."Liu, JeeLoo. ''An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy: From Ancient Philosophy to Chinese Buddhism.'' 2006. p. 221 This work is framed around Vasubandhu's ''Triṃśikā-vijñaptimātratā'', or "Thirty Verses on Consciousness Only." In his commentary, Xuanzang upheld Dharmapala of Nalanda, Dharmapāla's commentary on this work as being the correct one, and provided his own explanations of these as well as other views. This work was composed at the behest of Xuanzang's disciple Kuiji, Kuījī (632–682), and became a central work of East Asian Yogācāra. Xuanzang also promoted devotional meditative practices toward Maitreya. Xuanzang's disciple Kuiji wrote a number of important commentaries on Yogācāra texts and further developed the influence of this doctrine in China. He was recognized by later adherents as the first true patriarch of the school. The tradition was also brought to Korea (where it is known as ''Beopsang'') and Japan (where it is known as ''Hossō''). Principal exponents of Yogācāra in Korea include Daehyeon (大賢), Sinhaeng (神行 ; 704–779), Woncheuk (圓測 ; 631–696) and Wonhyo (元曉 ; 원효 ; 617 - 686), while in Japan they include Chitsū (智通) and Chidatsu (智達) of the Kusha-shū school, Dōshō, Dosho (道昭), Jōkei (monk), Jokei (貞慶), :ja:善珠, Zenju (善珠), Tokuitsu (徳一).


Yogācāra in Tibet

Yogācāra was first transmitted to Tibet by Śāntarakṣita, Kamalaśīla and Atiśa and Yogācāra thought is an integral part of the history of Tibetan Buddhism. Yogācāra is studied in all schools of Tibetan Buddhism, though it receives different emphasis in each. Like the Chinese tradition, the Tibetan Nyingma school and its Dzogchen teachings promote a hybrid form of Yogācāra-Buddha-nature, Tathāgatagarbha. The Jonang school meanwhile developed its own systematic view which they termed Rangtong-Shentong, ''shentong'' ("other-voidness" ), which included elements from Yogācāra, Madhyamaka and Buddha-nature, Tathāgatagarbha. They considered this view to be definitive, in contrast to the ''rangtong'' ("self-voidness" or Svatantrika-Prasaṅgika distinction, prasaṅgika, ), comprising both Svatantrika and Prasaṅgika Madhyamaka. Although Je Tsongkhapa (whose reforms to Atiśa's Kadam (Tibetan Buddhism), Kadam tradition are generally considered the beginnings of the Gelug school) argued in favour of Yogācāra views (specifically regarding the existence and functioning of Eight Consciousnesses, eight consciousnesses) early in his career, the prevailing Gelug view eventually came to hold Yogācāra views as a matter of interpretable meaning, therefore distinct from Madhyamaka which was held to be of definitive meaning. Current discussions between Tibetan scholars regarding the Rangtong-Shentong, differences between shentong and rangtong views may therefore appear similar to historical debates between Yogācāra and Madhyamaka, but the specific distinctions have, in fact, evolved much further. Although later Tibetan views may be said to have evolved from the earlier Indian positions, the distinctions between the views have become increasingly subtle and complex, especially as Tibetan Yogācāra has evolved to incorporate Madhyamaka and Buddha-nature, Tathāgatagarbha philosophies. Jamgon Ju Mipham Gyatso, the 19th-century Rimé movement commentator, wrote in his commentary on Śāntarakṣita's synthesis, that the ultimate view in both schools is the same, and that each path leads to the same ultimate state of abiding.


Textual corpus


Sūtras

The ''Sandhinirmocana Sutra, Saṃdhinirmocana Sūtra'' ("Sūtra of the Explanation of the Profound Secrets"; 2nd century CE), was the seminal Yogācāra sutra and continued to be a primary referent for the tradition. Another text, the ''Mahāyānābhidharmasūtra'' is often quoted in Yogacarabhumi-sastra, Yogācāra works and is assumed to also be an early Yogacarabhumi-sastra, Yogācāra sutra''.'' The ''Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra'' also later assumed considerable importance in East Asia, and portions of this text were considered by Étienne Lamotte as being contemporaneous with the ''Saṃdhinirmocana''. This text equates the Yogācāra theory of ''ālayavijñāna'' with the Buddha-nature, ''Tathāgatagarbha'' and thus seems to be part of the tradition which sought to merge Yogācāra with Buddha-nature, ''Tathāgatagarbha'' thought.


Asaṅga, Vasubandhu and early Śāstras

Some of the earliest Yogācāra material can be found in the ''Yogacarabhumi-sastra, Yogācārabhūmi-śāstra,'' such as the doctrines of ''ālayavijñāna and āśrayaparāvṛtti.'' This text, a massive encyclopedic work on yogic praxis, is traditionally attributed to Asaṅga (4th century) or Maitreya, but most scholars (such as Lambert Schmithausen, Schmithausen and Aramaki) believe it contains the work of many authors, and its components reflect various stages of historical development. Most of its material is non-Mahayana and according to Lusthaus, it draws extensively from on the Āgama (Buddhism), Āgamas.Kritzer (2005), p. xvii, xix. Nevertheless, Asaṅga may still have influenced its development.Lugli, Ligeia
Asaṅga, oxfordbibliographies.com
LAST MODIFIED: 25 NOVEMBER 2014, DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195393521-0205.
Authorship of several major Yogācāra treatises or Shastra, śāstras are ascribed to Asaṅga, a major doctrinal systematizer of the school. Among them are his magnum opus, the ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha'' and also a compendium of Yogācāra Abhidharma, the ''Abhidharma-samuccaya''. Asaṅga's brother Vasubandhu is also considered to be an important Yogācāra figure. He wrote various important śāstras'','' including the ''Trisvabhāva-nirdeśa'' (Treatise on the Three Natures), ''Viṃśaṭikā-kārikā'' (Treatise in Twenty Stanzas), ''Triṃśikā-kārikā'' (Treatise in Thirty Stanzas), ''Vyākhyāyukti'' ("Proper Mode of Exposition"), ''Karmasiddhiprakarana'' ("A Treatise on Karma"), and the ''Pañcaskandhaprakaraṇa'' (Explanation of the Five Aggregates). According to Jay L. Garfield, Jay Garfield, the ''Trisvabhāva-nirdeśa'' is "arguably one of the most philosophically detailed and comprehensive" work on the three natures by Vasubandhu. Vasubandhu also wrote a large systematic work on Abhidharma, the ''Abhidharmakośakārikā, Abhidharmakośa-bhāṣya,'' which remains influential in Tibet and East Asia. According to Robert Kritzer, though this work is traditionally seen as being based on Sarvastivada and Sautrāntika, Sautrantika Abhidharma, it also contains Yogācāra influences drawn from the ''Yogācārabhūmi.''Kritzer (2005), p. xii.


Other figures and texts

According to Williams, there is a fairly early Yogācāra work surviving in Sanskrit called the ''Alokamala'' (‘Garland of Light’) of Kambala (c. 450–525), which "gives of a form of Yogācāra just prior to the vigorous critical Madhyamaka, Madhyamika response to it represented by the works of Bhāviveka, Bhavaviveka." Williams also notes that this work "tries to harmonize where possible the Madhyamika position with that of Yogācāra."Williams (2008), pp. 87-88. Important commentaries on various Yogācāra texts were written by Sthiramati (6th century) and Dharmapala of Nalanda (6th century), who represent different subschools of the tradition. The Indian Buddhist logico-epistemology, Buddhist logician Dignāga (c. 480– 540 CE) wrote an important Yogācāra work, the ''Alambanapariksa'' and its ''vrtti'' (commentary). The work of Dharmakirti also shows Yogācāra influence. The Chinese figure of Xuanzang (602-664) wrote a commentary (''Ch' eng wei shih lun'', Sanskrit, Skt. reconstruction: ''Vijñaptimātratāsiddhi*'') on the ''Trimsikā'' of Vasubandhu, for which he used numerous Indian commentaries, favoring the work of Dharmapala of Nalanda, Dharmapala. In the East Asian Yogācāra tradition, this is the central work on Yogācāra philosophy. Besides the works of Asaṅga and Vasubandhu outlined above, the Yogācāra tradition as it is understood in Tibetan Buddhism is also based on a series of texts called the ''Asanga#Attributed works of unsure authorship, Five Dharmas of Maitreya''. These are the ''Mahayana-sutra-alamkara-karika, Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra, Dharma-dharmata-vibhaga, Dharmadharmatāvibhāga, Madhyanta-vibhaga-karika, Madhyāntavibhāgakārikā, Abhisamayalankara'' and the Ratnagotravibhāga, ''Ratnagotravibhaga.'' These texts are traditionally said to have been related to Asaṅga by the Bodhisattva Maitreya from Tusita Heaven. According to D.S. Ruegg, the "five works of Maitreya" are mentioned in Sanskrit sources from only the 11th century onwards. As noted by Shenpen Hookham, S.K. Hookham and Paul Williams, their attribution to a single author has been questioned by modern scholars, especially the ''Abhisamayalankara'' and the Ratnagotravibhāga, ''Ratnagotravibhaga'' (which focuses on Buddha-nature, ''tathāgatagarbha''). There are also various commentaries on these texts from Indian and Tibetan authors that are important in the Tibetan scholastic tradition. According to Karl Brunnholzl, the Chinese tradition also speaks of five Maitreya texts (first mentioned in Dunlun's ''Yujia lunji''), "but considers them as consisting of the ''Yogacarabhumi-sastra, Yogācārabhūmi, *Yogavibhāga'' [now lost]'', Mahayana-sutra-alamkara-karika, Mahāyānasūtrālamkārakā, Madhyanta-vibhaga-karika, Madhyāntavibhāga'' and the ''Vajracchedikākāvyākhyā."''Brunnholzl, Karl'', When the Clouds Part: The Uttaratantra and Its Meditative Tradition as a Bridge between Sutra and Tantra,'' Shambhala Publications, 2015, p. 81.


Contemporary scholarship

According to Dan Lusthaus, Lusthaus, Étienne Lamotte, a famous student of Louis de La Vallée-Poussin, "...profoundly advanced Yogācāra studies, and his efforts remain unrivaled among Western scholars."


Philosophical dialogue: Yogācāra, idealism and phenomenology

Yogācāra has also been identified in the western philosophical tradition as idealism, or more specifically subjective idealism. This equation was standard until recently, when it began to be challenged by scholars such as Kochumuttom, Anacker, Kalupahana, Dunne, Lusthaus,Dan Lusthaus, ''What is and isn't Yogacara.'

Powers, and Wayman. Buddhist scholar Jay Garfield continues to uphold the equation of Yogācāra and idealism, however.Garfield, Jay L. (2002). ''Empty words : Buddhist philosophy and cross-cultural interpretation'' ([Online-Ausg.]. ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. . To the same effect, Nobuyoshi Yamabe states that "Dignāga also clearly inherited the idealistic system of Yogācāra."Yamabe, Nobuyoshi (2004), "Consciousness, Theories of", in Buswell, Jr., Robert E., Macmillan Encyclopedia of Buddhism, USA: Macmillan Reference USA, pp. 177, Like many contemporary scholars, Yamabe is aware that the texts considered to be Yogācāra treatises reflect various stages in addressing the issue of mind and matter. Yogācāra has also been aligned with phenomenalism. In modern western philosophical discourse, Edmund Husserl and Maurice Merleau-Ponty have approached what western scholarship generally concedes to be a standard Yogācāra position.


Legacy

There are two important aspects of the Yogācāra schemata that are of special interest to modern-day practitioners. One is that virtually all schools of Mahāyāna Buddhism came to rely on these Yogācāra explanations as they created their own doctrinal systems, including the Zen schools. For example, the early Zen tradition in China was sometimes referred to simply as the " school" (Ch. 楞伽宗, ''Léngqié Zōng''), due to their strong association with the '. This sūtra draws heavily upon Yogācāra theories of the eight consciousnesses, especially the '. Accounts recording the history of this early period are preserved in ''Records of the Masters'' (Ch. 楞伽師資記, ''Léngqié Shīzī Jì''). That the scriptural tradition of Yogācāra is not yet well known among the community of western practitioners is perhaps attributable to the fact that most of the initial transmission of Buddhism to the west has been directly concerned with meditation and basic doctrines. However, within Tibetan Buddhism more and more western students are becoming acquainted with this school. Very little research in English has been carried out on the Chinese Yogācāra traditions.


See also

* ''Cheng Weishi Lun'' (''Discourse on the Perfection of Consciousness-only'') * Lambert Schmithausen * ''Triṃśikā-vijñaptimātratā'' (''Thirty Verses on Consciousness Only'') * ''Vimśatikāvijñaptimātratāsiddhi'' (''Twenty Verses on Consciousness Only'')


Notes


References


Sources

* Bayer, Achim (2012)
''Addenda and Corrigenda to The Theory of Karman in the Abhidharmasamuccaya, 2012''
Hamburg: Zentrum für Buddhismuskunde. * * Keenan, John P. (1993). ''Yogācarā''. pp. 203–212 published in Yoshinori, Takeuchi; with Van Bragt, Jan; Heisig, James W.; O'Leary, Joseph S.; Swanson, Paul L.(1993). ''Buddhist Spirituality: Indian, Southeast Asian, Tibetan, and Early Chinese.'' New York City: The Crossroad Publishing Company. * * * Namkhai Norbu, Norbu, Namkhai (2001), ''The Precious Vase: Instructions on the Base of Santi Maha Sangha''. Shang Shung Edizioni. Second revised edition. (Translated from the Tibetan, edited and annotated by Adriano Clemente with the help of the author. Translated from Italian into English by Andy Lukianowicz.) * * Shantarakshita & Ju Mipham (2005). ''The Adornment of the Middle Way'' Padmakara Translation of Ju Mipham's commentary on Shantarakshita's root versus on his synthesis. * Sponberg, Alan (1979)
Dynamic Liberation in Yogacara Buddhism
Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 2(1), pp. 44–64. * Stcherbatsky, Theodore (1936).
Mathyanta-Vibhanga, "Discourse on Discrimination between Middle and Extremes"
ascribed to Bodhisattva Maiteya and commented by Vasubhandu and Sthiramathi, translated from the sanscrit, Academy of Sciences USSR Press, Moscow/Leningrad. * Timme Kragh, Ulrich (editor) 2013, ''The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners'': ''The Buddhist Yogācārabhūmi Treatise and Its Adaptation in India, East Asia, and Tibet, Volume 1'' Harvard University, Department of South Asian studies. * Zim, Robert (1995). ''Basic ideas of Yogacara Buddhism.'' San Francisco State University. Source

(accessed: October 18, 2007).


External links



Surendranath Dasgupta, 1940

Richard King, ''Philosophy East & West'', vol. 44 no. 4, October 1994, pp. 659–683
"The mind-only teaching of Ching-ying Hui-Yuan"
(subtitle) "An early interpretation of Yogaacaara thought in China", Ming-Wood Liu, ''Philosophy East & West'', vol. 35 no. 4, October 1985, pp. 351–375
Yogacara Buddhism Research Association
articles, bibliographies, and links to other relevant sites. {{Consciousness Vajrayana Idealism Buddhist movements Buddhist philosophy Nondualism Yogacara, Buddhism in the Nara period Buddhist meditation