
Logic is the study of correct
reasoning. It includes both
formal and
informal logic
Informal logic encompasses the principles of logic and logical thought outside of a formal setting (characterized by the usage of particular statements). However, the precise definition of "informal logic" is a matter of some dispute. Ralph H ...
. Formal logic is the science of
deductively valid inferences or of
logical truth
Logical truth is one of the most fundamental concepts in logic. Broadly speaking, a logical truth is a statement which is true regardless of the truth or falsity of its constituent propositions. In other words, a logical truth is a statement wh ...
s. It is a
formal science
Formal science is a branch of science studying disciplines concerned with abstract structures described by formal systems, such as logic, mathematics, statistics, theoretical computer science, artificial intelligence, information theory, ga ...
investigating how conclusions follow from
premise
A premise or premiss is a true or false statement that helps form the body of an argument, which logically leads to a true or false conclusion. A premise makes a declarative statement about its subject matter which enables a reader to either agre ...
s in a topic-neutral way. When used as a countable noun, the term "a logic" refers to a logical
formal system that articulates a
proof system. Formal logic contrasts with informal logic, which is associated with
informal fallacies,
critical thinking
Critical thinking is the analysis of available facts, evidence, observations, and arguments to form a judgement. The subject is complex; several different definitions exist, which generally include the rational, skeptical, and unbiased analys ...
, and
argumentation theory. While there is no general agreement on how formal and informal logic are to be distinguished, one prominent approach associates their difference with whether the studied
arguments are expressed in
formal or
informal languages. Logic plays a central role in multiple fields, such as
philosophy,
mathematics
Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
,
computer science, and
linguistics.
Logic studies arguments, which consist of a set of premises together with a conclusion. Premises and conclusions are usually understood either as
sentences or as
proposition
In logic and linguistics, a proposition is the meaning of a declarative sentence. In philosophy, " meaning" is understood to be a non-linguistic entity which is shared by all sentences with the same meaning. Equivalently, a proposition is the ...
s and are characterized by their internal structure; complex propositions are made up of simpler propositions linked to each other by
propositional connectives like
(and) or
(if...then). The truth of a proposition usually depends on the
denotations of its constituents. Logically true propositions constitute a special case since their truth depends only on the logical vocabulary used in them and not on the denotations of other terms.
Arguments can be either correct or incorrect. An argument is correct if its premises support its conclusion. The strongest form of support is found in
deductive arguments: it is impossible for their premises to be true and their conclusion to be false. Deductive arguments contrast with
ampliative arguments, which may arrive in their conclusion at new information that is not present in the premises. However, it is possible for all their premises to be true while their conclusion is still false. Many arguments found in everyday discourse and the sciences are ampliative arguments, sometimes divided into
inductive and
abductive arguments. Inductive arguments usually take the form of
statistical generalizations while abductive arguments are ''
inferences to the best explanation''. Arguments that fall short of the standards of correct reasoning are called
fallacies.
Systems of logic are theoretical frameworks for assessing the correctness of reasoning and arguments. Logic has been studied since
Antiquity; early approaches include
Aristotelian logic,
Stoic logic,
Anviksiki, and the
mohists. Modern formal logic has its roots in the work of late 19th-century mathematicians such as
Gottlob Frege. While Aristotelian logic focuses on reasoning in the form of
syllogisms, in the modern era its traditional dominance was replaced by
classical logic, a set of fundamental logical intuitions shared by most logicians. It consists of
propositional logic, which only considers the logical relations on the level of propositions, and
first-order logic
First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quant ...
, which also articulates the internal structure of propositions using various linguistic devices, such as predicates and
quantifiers. Extended logics accept the basic intuitions behind classical logic and extend it to other fields, such as
metaphysics,
ethics, and
epistemology. Deviant logics, on the other hand, reject certain classical intuitions and provide alternative accounts of the fundamental laws of logic.
Definition
The word "logic" originates from the Greek word "logos", which has a variety of translations, such as
reason,
discourse
Discourse is a generalization of the notion of a conversation to any form of communication. Discourse is a major topic in social theory, with work spanning fields such as sociology, anthropology, continental philosophy, and discourse analysis ...
, or
language. Logic is traditionally defined as the study of the
laws of thought or correct
reasoning,
and is usually understood in terms of
inferences or
arguments. Reasoning may be seen as the activity of drawing inferences whose outward expression is given in arguments.
An inference or an argument is a set of premises together with a conclusion. Logic is interested in whether arguments are good or inferences are valid, i.e. whether the premises support their conclusions.
These general characterizations apply to logic in the widest sense since they are true both for formal and informal logic,
but many definitions of logic focus on the more paradigmatic formal logic. In this narrower sense, logic is a formal science that studies how conclusions follow from premises in a topic-neutral way.
In this regard, logic is sometimes contrasted with the theory of
rationality, which is wider since it covers all forms of good reasoning.

As a
formal science
Formal science is a branch of science studying disciplines concerned with abstract structures described by formal systems, such as logic, mathematics, statistics, theoretical computer science, artificial intelligence, information theory, ga ...
, logic contrasts with both the
natural and
social science
Social science is one of the branches of science, devoted to the study of societies and the relationships among individuals within those societies. The term was formerly used to refer to the field of sociology, the original "science of soc ...
s in that it tries to characterize the inferential relations between premises and conclusions based on their structure alone.
This means that the actual content of these propositions, i.e. their specific topic, is not important for whether the inference is valid or not.
Valid inferences are characterized by the fact that the truth of their premises ensures the truth of their conclusion: it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false.
The general logical structures characterizing valid inferences are called
rules of inference
In the philosophy of logic, a rule of inference, inference rule or transformation rule is a logical form consisting of a function which takes premises, analyzes their syntax, and returns a conclusion (or conclusions). For example, the rule of ...
. In this sense, logic is often defined as the study of valid inference.
This contrasts with another prominent characterization of logic as the science of
logical truth
Logical truth is one of the most fundamental concepts in logic. Broadly speaking, a logical truth is a statement which is true regardless of the truth or falsity of its constituent propositions. In other words, a logical truth is a statement wh ...
s. A proposition is logically true if its truth depends only on the logical vocabulary used in it. This means that it is true in all
possible worlds and under all
interpretations of its non-logical terms.
These two characterizations of logic are closely related to each other: an inference is valid if the
material conditional from its premises to its conclusion is logically true.
The term "logic" can also be used in a slightly different sense as a countable noun. In this sense, ''a logic'' is a logical
formal system. Different logics differ from each other concerning the
formal languages
In logic, mathematics, computer science, and linguistics, a formal language consists of words whose letters are taken from an alphabet and are well-formed according to a specific set of rules.
The alphabet of a formal language consists of ...
used to express them and, most importantly, concerning the rules of inference they accept as valid.
Starting in the 20th century, many new formal systems have been proposed. There are various disagreements concerning what makes a formal system a logic.
For example, it has been suggested that only
logically complete systems qualify as logics. For such reasons, some theorists deny that
higher-order logics and
fuzzy logic
Fuzzy logic is a form of many-valued logic in which the truth value of variables may be any real number between 0 and 1. It is employed to handle the concept of partial truth, where the truth value may range between completely true and completel ...
are logics in the strict sense.
Formal and informal logic
Logic encompasses both formal and
informal logic
Informal logic encompasses the principles of logic and logical thought outside of a formal setting (characterized by the usage of particular statements). However, the precise definition of "informal logic" is a matter of some dispute. Ralph H ...
.
Formal logic is the traditionally dominant field,
but applying its insights to actual everyday arguments has prompted modern developments of informal logic,
which considers problems that formal logic on its own is unable to address.
Both provide criteria for assessing the correctness of arguments and distinguishing them from fallacies.
Various suggestions have been made concerning how to draw the distinction between the two but there is no universally accepted answer.

The most literal approach sees the terms "formal" and "informal" as applying to the language used to express arguments.
On this view, formal logic studies arguments expressed in formal languages while informal logic studies arguments expressed in informal or
natural languages.
This means that the inference from the formulas and to the conclusion is studied by formal logic. The inference from the
English sentences "Al lit a cigarette" and "Bill stormed out of the room" to the sentence "Al lit a cigarette and Bill stormed out of the room", on the other hand, belongs to informal logic. Formal languages are characterized by their precision and simplicity.
They normally contain a very limited vocabulary and exact rules on how their symbols can be used to construct sentences, usually referred to as
well-formed formulas.
This simplicity and exactness of formal logic make it capable of formulating precise rules of inference that determine whether a given argument is valid.
This approach brings with it the need to translate natural language arguments into the formal language before their validity can be assessed, a procedure that comes with various problems of its own.
Informal logic avoids some of these problems by analyzing natural language arguments in their original form without the need of translation.
But it faces problems associated with the
ambiguity,
vagueness, and context-dependence of natural language expressions.
A closely related approach applies the terms "formal" and "informal" not just to the language used, but more generally to the standards, criteria, and procedures of argumentation.
Another approach draws the distinction according to the different types of inferences analyzed.
This perspective understands formal logic as the study of
deductive inferences in contrast to informal logic as the study of non-deductive inferences, like
inductive or
abductive inferences.
The characteristic of deductive inferences is that the truth of their premises ensures the truth of their conclusion. This means that if all the premises are true, it is impossible for the conclusion to be false.
For this reason, deductive inferences are in a sense trivial or uninteresting since they do not provide the thinker with any new information not already found in the premises.
Non-deductive inferences, on the other hand, are
ampliative: they help the thinker learn something above and beyond what is already stated in the premises. They achieve this at the cost of certainty: even if all premises are true, the conclusion of an ampliative argument may still be false.
One more approach tries to link the difference between formal and informal logic to the distinction between
formal and
informal fallacies.
This distinction is often drawn in relation to the ''
form
Form is the shape, visual appearance, or configuration of an object. In a wider sense, the form is the way something happens.
Form also refers to:
*Form (document), a document (printed or electronic) with spaces in which to write or enter data
...
'', ''content'', and ''
context'' of arguments. In the case of formal fallacies, the error is found on the level of the argument's form, whereas for informal fallacies, the content and context of the argument are responsible.
Formal logic abstracts away from the argument's content and is only interested in its form, specifically whether it follows a valid rule of inference.
In this regard, it is not important for the validity of a formal argument whether its premises are true or false. Informal logic, on the other hand, also takes the content and context of an argument into consideration.
A
false dilemma
A false dilemma, also referred to as false dichotomy or false binary, is an informal fallacy based on a premise that erroneously limits what options are available. The source of the fallacy lies not in an invalid form of inference but in a false ...
, for example, involves an error of content by excluding viable options, as in "you are either with us or against us; you are not with us; therefore, you are against us".
For the
strawman fallacy, on the other hand, the error is found on the level of context: a weak position is first described and then defeated, even though the opponent does not hold this position. But in another context, against an opponent that actually defends the strawman position, the argument is correct.
Other accounts draw the distinction based on investigating general forms of arguments in contrast to particular instances or on the study of
logical constant In logic, a logical constant of a language \mathcal is a symbol that has the same semantic value under every interpretation of \mathcal. Two important types of logical constants are logical connectives and quantifiers. The equality predicate ...
s instead of substantive
concepts. A further approach focuses on the discussion of logical topics with or without formal devices or on the role of
epistemology for the assessment of arguments.
Fundamental concepts
Premises, conclusions, and truth
Premises and conclusions
''Premises'' and ''conclusions'' are the basic parts of inferences or arguments and therefore play a central role in logic. In the case of a valid inference or a correct argument, the conclusion follows from the premises, or in other words, the premises support the conclusion.
For instance, the premises "Mars is red" and "Mars is a planet" support the conclusion "Mars is a red planet". It is generally accepted that premises and conclusions have to be
truth-bearers.
[Though see imperative logic, dynamic semantics, and inquisitive semantics for logical systems which narrow or generalize the notion of valid inference to other kinds of objects.] This means that they have a
truth value
In logic and mathematics, a truth value, sometimes called a logical value, is a value indicating the relation of a proposition to truth, which in classical logic has only two possible values ('' true'' or '' false'').
Computing
In some pr ...
: they are either true or false. Thus contemporary philosophy generally sees them either as ''
proposition
In logic and linguistics, a proposition is the meaning of a declarative sentence. In philosophy, " meaning" is understood to be a non-linguistic entity which is shared by all sentences with the same meaning. Equivalently, a proposition is the ...
s'' or as ''
sentences''.
Propositions are the
denotations of sentences and are usually understood as
abstract object
In metaphysics, the distinction between abstract and concrete refers to a divide between two types of entities. Many philosophers hold that this difference has fundamental metaphysical significance. Examples of concrete objects include plants, ...
s.
Propositional theories of premises and conclusions are often criticized because of the difficulties involved in specifying the identity criteria of abstract objects or because of
naturalist considerations.
These objections are avoided by seeing premises and conclusions not as propositions but as sentences, i.e. as concrete linguistic objects like the symbols displayed on a page of a book. But this approach comes with new problems of its own: sentences are often context-dependent and
ambiguous, meaning an argument's validity would not only depend on its parts but also on its context and on how it is interpreted.
In earlier work, premises and conclusions were understood in psychological terms as thoughts or judgments, in an approach known as "
psychologism". This position was heavily criticized around the turn of the 20th century.
Internal structure
Premises and conclusions have internal structure. As propositions or sentences, they can be either simple or complex.
A complex proposition has other propositions as its constituents, which are linked to each other through
propositional connectives like "and" or "if...then". Simple propositions, on the other hand, do not have propositional parts. But they can also be conceived as having an internal structure: they are made up of subpropositional parts, like
singular term A singular term is a paradigmatic referring device in a language. Singular terms are of philosophical importance for philosophers of language, because they ''refer'' to things in the world, and the ability of words to refer calls for scrutiny.
Over ...
s and
predicates.
For example, the simple proposition "Mars is red" can be formed by applying the predicate "red" to the singular term "Mars".
In contrast, the complex proposition "Mars is red and Venus is white" is made up of two simple propositions connected by the propositional connective "and".
Whether a proposition is true depends, at least in part, on its constituents.
For complex propositions formed using
truth-functional propositional connectives, their truth only depends on the truth values of their parts.
But this relation is more complicated in the case of simple propositions and their subpropositional parts. These subpropositional parts have meanings of their own, like referring to objects or classes of objects.
Whether the simple proposition they form is true depends on their relation to reality, i.e. what the objects they refer to are like. This topic is studied by
theories of reference.
Logical truth
In some cases, a simple or a complex proposition is true independently of the substantive meanings of its parts.
For example, the complex proposition "if Mars is red, then Mars is red" is true independent of whether its parts, i.e. the simple proposition "Mars is red", are true or false. In such cases, the truth is called a logical truth: a proposition is logically true if its truth depends only on the logical vocabulary used in it.
This means that it is true under all interpretations of its non-logical terms. In some
modal logic
Modal logic is a collection of formal systems developed to represent statements about necessity and possibility. It plays a major role in philosophy of language, epistemology, metaphysics, and natural language semantics. Modal logics extend other ...
s, this notion can be understood equivalently as truth at all possible worlds.
Logical truth plays an important role in logic and some theorists even define logic as the study of logical truths.
Truth tables
Truth table
A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional argum ...
s can be used to show how logical connectives work or how the truth of complex propositions depends on their parts. They have a column for each input variable. Each row corresponds to one possible combination of the truth values these variables can take. The final columns present the truth values of the corresponding expressions as determined by the input values. For example, the expression uses the logical connective
(and). It could be used to express a sentence like "yesterday was Sunday and the weather was good". It is only true if both of its input variables,
("yesterday was Sunday") and
("the weather was good"), are true. In all other cases, the expression as a whole is false. Other important logical connectives are
(or),
(if...then), and
(not). Truth tables can also be defined for more complex expressions that use several propositional connectives. For example, given the conditional proposition
, one can form truth tables of its
inverse , and its
contraposition
In logic and mathematics, contraposition refers to the inference of going from a conditional statement into its logically equivalent contrapositive, and an associated proof method known as proof by contraposition. The contrapositive of a stateme ...
.
Arguments and inferences
Logic is commonly defined in terms of arguments or inferences as the study of their correctness.
An ''argument'' is a set of premises together with a conclusion. An ''inference'' is the process of reasoning from these premises to the conclusion.
But these terms are often used interchangeably in logic. Arguments are correct or incorrect depending on whether their premises support their conclusion. Premises and conclusions, on the other hand, are true or false depending on whether they are in accord with
reality
Reality is the sum or aggregate of all that is real or existent within a system, as opposed to that which is only imaginary. The term is also used to refer to the ontological status of things, indicating their existence. In physical terms, re ...
. In formal logic, a
sound argument is an argument that is both correct and has only true premises. Sometimes a distinction is made between simple and complex arguments.
A complex argument is made up of a chain of simple arguments. These simple arguments constitute a ''chain'' because the conclusions of the earlier arguments are used as premises in the later arguments. For a complex argument to be successful, each link of the chain has to be successful.

Arguments and inferences are either are correct or incorrect. If they are correct then their premises support their conclusion. In the incorrect case, this support is missing. It can take different forms corresponding to the different
types of reasoning.
The strongest form of support corresponds to
deductive reasoning. But even arguments that are not deductively valid may still constitute good arguments because their premises offer non-deductive support to their conclusions. For such cases, the term ''ampliative'' or ''inductive reasoning'' is used.
Deductive arguments are associated with formal logic in contrast to the relation between ampliative arguments and informal logic.
Deductive
A ''deductively
valid argument'' is one whose premises guarantee the truth of its conclusion.
For instance, the argument "Victoria is tall; Victoria has brown hair; therefore Victoria is tall and has brown hair" is deductively valid. For deductive validity, it does not matter whether the premises or the conclusion are actually true. So the argument "trees can speak the English language; therefore trees can speak a language" is valid because, if the premise were true, the conclusion would be true as well.
Alfred Tarski holds that deductive arguments have three essential features: (1) they are formal, i.e. they depend only on the form of the premises and the conclusion; (2) they are a priori, i.e. no sense experience is needed to determine whether they obtain; (3) they are modal, i.e. that they hold by
logical necessity for the given propositions, independent of any other circumstances.
Because of the first feature, the focus on formality, deductive inference is usually identified with
rules of inference
In the philosophy of logic, a rule of inference, inference rule or transformation rule is a logical form consisting of a function which takes premises, analyzes their syntax, and returns a conclusion (or conclusions). For example, the rule of ...
. Rules of inference specify how the premises and the conclusion have to be structured for the inference to be valid. Arguments that do not follow any rule of inference are deductively invalid.
The
modus ponens is a prominent rule of inference. It has the form "''p''; if ''p'', then ''q''; therefore ''q''".
Knowing that it has just rained (
) and that after rain the streets are wet (
), one can use modus ponens to deduce that the streets are wet (
).
The third feature can be expressed by stating that deductively valid inferences are truth-preserving: it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false.
Because of this feature, it is often asserted that deductive inferences are uninformative since the conclusion cannot arrive at new
information not already present in the premises.
But this point is not always accepted since it would mean, for example, that most of
mathematics
Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
is uninformative. A different characterization distinguishes between surface and depth information.
On this view, deductive inferences are uninformative on the depth level but can be highly informative on the surface level, as may be the case for various mathematical proofs.
Ampliative
Ampliative inferences, on the other hand, are informative even on the depth level. They are more interesting in this sense since the thinker may acquire substantive information from them and thereby learn something genuinely new.
But this feature comes with a certain cost: the premises support the conclusion in the sense that they make its truth more likely but they do not ensure its truth.
This means that the conclusion of an ampliative argument may be false even though all its premises are true. This characteristic is closely related to ''
non-monotonicity'' and ''
defeasibility'': it may be necessary to retract an earlier conclusion upon receiving new information or in the light of new inferences drawn.
Ampliative reasoning is of central importance since many arguments found in everyday discourse and the
sciences are ampliative. Ampliative arguments are not automatically incorrect. Instead, they just follow different standards of correctness. An important aspect of most ampliative arguments is that the support they provide for their conclusion comes in degrees.
In this sense, the line between correct and incorrect arguments is blurry in some cases, as when the premises offer weak but non-negligible support. This contrasts with deductive arguments, which are either valid or invalid with nothing in-between.
The terminology used to categorize ampliative arguments is inconsistent. Some authors use the term "induction" to cover all forms of non-deductive arguments.
But in a more narrow sense, ''induction'' is only one type of ampliative argument besides ''abductive arguments''.
Some authors also allow ''conductive arguments'' as one more type.
In this narrow sense, induction is often defined as a form of
statistical generalization. In this case, the premises of an inductive argument are many individual observations that all show a certain pattern. The conclusion then is a general law that this pattern always obtains.
In this sense, one may infer that "all elephants are gray" based on one's past observations of the color of elephants.
A closely related form of inductive inference has as its conclusion not a general law but one more specific instance, as when it is inferred that an elephant one has not seen yet is also gray.
Some theorists stipulate that inductive inferences rest only on statistical considerations in order to distinguish them from abductive inference.
Abductive inference may or may not take statistical observations into consideration. In either case, the premises offer support for the conclusion because the conclusion is the best
explanation of why the premises are true.
[On ]abductive reasoning
Abductive reasoning (also called abduction,For example: abductive inference, or retroduction) is a form of logical inference formulated and advanced by American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce beginning in the last third of the 19th centu ...
, see:
* Magnani, L. 2001. ''Abduction, Reason, and Science: Processes of Discovery and Explanation''. New York: Kluwer Academic Plenum Publishers. xvii. .
* Josephson, John R., and Susan G. Josephson. 1994. ''Abductive Inference: Computation, Philosophy, Technology''. New York: Cambridge University Press. viii. .
* Bunt, H. and W. Black. 2000. ''Abduction, Belief and Context in Dialogue: Studies in Computational Pragmatics'', (''Natural Language Processing'' 1). Amsterdam: John Benjamins. vi. . In this sense, abduction is also called the ''inference to the best explanation''.
For example, given the premise that there is a plate with breadcrumbs in the kitchen in the early morning, one may infer the conclusion that one's house-mate had a midnight snack and was too tired to clean the table. This conclusion is justified because it is the best explanation of the current state of the kitchen.
For abduction, it is not sufficient that the conclusion explains the premises. For example, the conclusion that a burglar broke into the house last night, got hungry on the job, and had a midnight snack, would also explain the state of the kitchen. But this conclusion is not justified because it is not the best or most likely explanation.
Fallacies
Not all arguments live up to the standards of correct reasoning. When they do not, they are usually referred to as
fallacies. Their central aspect is not that their conclusion is false but that there is some flaw with the reasoning leading to this conclusion.
So the argument "it is sunny today; therefore spiders have eight legs" is fallacious even though the conclusion is true. Some theorists give a more restrictive definition of fallacies by additionally requiring that they appear to be correct.
This way, genuine fallacies can be distinguished from mere mistakes of reasoning due to carelessness. This explains why people tend to commit fallacies: because they have an alluring element that seduces people into committing and accepting them.
However, this reference to appearances is controversial because it belongs to the field of
psychology, not logic, and because appearances may be different for different people.

Fallacies are usually divided into formal and informal fallacies.
For formal fallacies, the source of the error is found in the ''form'' of the argument. For example,
denying the antecedent is one type of formal fallacy, as in "if Othello is a bachelor, then he is male; Othello is not a bachelor; therefore Othello is not male".
But most fallacies fall into the category of informal fallacies, of which a great variety is discussed in the academic literature. The source of their error is usually found in the ''content'' or the ''context'' of the argument.
Informal fallacies are sometimes categorized as fallacies of ambiguity, fallacies of presumption, or fallacies of relevance. For fallacies of ambiguity, the ambiguity and vagueness of natural language are responsible for their flaw, as in "feathers are light; what is light cannot be dark; therefore feathers cannot be dark".
Fallacies of presumption have a wrong or unjustified premise but may be valid otherwise.
In the case of fallacies of relevance, the premises do not support the conclusion because they are not relevant to it.
Definitory and strategic rules
The main focus of most logicians is to investigate the criteria according to which an argument is correct or incorrect. A fallacy is committed if these criteria are violated. In the case of formal logic, they are known as ''rules of inference''. They constitute definitory rules, which determine whether a certain inference is correct or which inferences are allowed. Definitory rules contrast with strategic rules.
Strategic rules specify which inferential moves are necessary in order to reach a given conclusion based on a certain set of premises.
This distinction does not just apply to logic but also to various games as well. In
chess, for example, the definitory rules dictate that
bishops may only move diagonally while the strategic rules describe how the allowed moves may be used to win a game, for example, by controlling the center and by defending one's
king.
A third type of rules concerns
empirical
Empirical evidence for a proposition is evidence, i.e. what supports or counters this proposition, that is constituted by or accessible to sense experience or experimental procedure. Empirical evidence is of central importance to the sciences ...
descriptive rules. They belong to the field of psychology and generalize how people actually draw inferences. It has been argued that logicians should give more emphasis to strategic rules since they are highly relevant for effective reasoning.
Formal systems
A formal system of logic consists of a
language, a
proof system, and a
semantics.
The term "a logic" is often used a
countable noun to refer to a particular formal system of logic.
Starting in the 20th century,
many new formal systems have been proposed.
[The term "a logic" is sometimes reserved for just the system's syntax, i.e. its language and proof theory. In the philosophical literature, the term is sometimes further restricted to refer only to particular logic-based formal systems such as those which are complete or motivated by intuitions close to those which motivated classical logic.]
Formal language
A ''formal language'' consists of an ''alphabet'' and syntactic rules. The alphabet is the set of basic symbols used in
expressions. The syntactic rules determine how these symbols may be arranged to result in well-formed formulas. For instance, the syntactic rules of
propositional logic determine that is a well-formed formula but is not.
Proof system
A ''proof system'' is a collection of formal rules which define when a conclusion follows from given premises. For instance, the classical rule of
conjunction introduction states that
follows from the premises
and
. Rules in a proof systems are always defined in terms of formulas' syntactic form, never in terms of their meanings. Such rules can be applied sequentially, giving a mechanical procedure for generating conclusions from premises. There are a number of different types of proof systems including
natural deduction In logic and proof theory, natural deduction is a kind of proof calculus in which logical reasoning is expressed by inference rules closely related to the "natural" way of reasoning. This contrasts with Hilbert-style systems, which instead use a ...
and
sequent calculi.
Proof systems are closely linked to philosophical work which characterizes logic as the study of valid inference.
Semantics
A ''semantics'' is a system for
mapping expressions of a formal language to their denotations. In many systems of logic, denotations are truth values. For instance, the semantics for
classical propositional logic assigns the formula
the denotation "true" whenever
and
are true.
Entailment is a semantic relation which holds between formulas when the first cannot be true without the second being true as well.
Semantics is closely tied to the philosophical characterization of logic as the study of logical truth.
Soundness and completeness
A system of logic is ''sound'' when its proof system cannot derive a conclusion from a set of premises unless it is semantically entailed by them. In other words, its proof system cannot lead to false conclusions, as defined by the semantics. A system is ''complete'' when its proof system can derive every conclusion that is semantically entailed by its premises. In other words, its proof system can lead to any true conclusion, as defined by the semantics. Thus, soundness and completeness together describe a system whose notions of validity and entailment line up perfectly.
The study of properties of formal systems is called ''metalogic''. Other important metalogical properties include ''
consistency'', ''
decidability'', and ''
expressive power''.
Systems of logic
Systems of logic are theoretical frameworks for assessing the correctness of reasoning and arguments. For over two thousand years,
Aristotelian logic was treated as the canon of logic in the Western world,
but modern developments in this field have led to a vast proliferation of logical systems.
One prominent categorization divides modern formal logical systems into classical logic, extended logics, and
deviant logic Deviant logic is a type of logic incompatible with classical logic. Philosopher Susan Haack uses the term ''deviant logic'' to describe certain non-classical systems of logic. In these logics:
* the set of well-formed formulas generated equals ...
s.
Classical logic is to be distinguished from traditional or Aristotelian logic. It encompasses propositional logic and first-order logic. It is "classical" in the sense that it is based on various fundamental logical intuitions shared by most logicians.
These intuitions include the
law of excluded middle
In logic, the law of excluded middle (or the principle of excluded middle) states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the so-called three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontrad ...
, the
double negation elimination, the
principle of explosion, and the bivalence of truth.
It was originally developed to analyze mathematical arguments and was only later applied to other fields as well. Because of this focus on mathematics, it does not include logical vocabulary relevant to many other topics of philosophical importance, like the distinction between necessity and possibility, the problem of ethical obligation and permission, or the relations between past, present, and future.
Such issues are addressed by extended logics. They build on the fundamental intuitions of classical logic and expand it by introducing new logical vocabulary. This way, the exact logical approach is applied to fields like
ethics or epistemology that lie beyond the scope of mathematics.
Deviant logics, on the other hand, reject some of the fundamental intuitions of classical logic.
Because of this, they are usually seen not as its supplements but as its rivals. Deviant logical systems differ from each other either because they reject different classical intuitions or because they propose different alternatives to the same issue.
Informal logic is usually carried out in a less systematic way. It often focuses on more specific issues, like investigating a particular type of fallacy or studying a certain aspect of argumentation.
Nonetheless, some systems of informal logic have also been presented that try to provide a systematic characterization of the correctness of arguments.
Aristotelian
Aristotelian logic encompasses a great variety of topics, including
metaphysical theses about
ontological categories and problems of scientific explanation.
But in a more narrow sense, it refers to
term logic
In philosophy, term logic, also known as traditional logic, syllogistic logic or Aristotelian logic, is a loose name for an approach to formal logic that began with Aristotle and was developed further in ancient history mostly by his followers, ...
or syllogistics. A
syllogism is a certain form of argument involving three propositions: two premises and a conclusion. Each proposition has three essential parts: a
subject, a predicate, and a
copula connecting the subject to the predicate.
For example, the proposition "Socrates is wise" is made up of the subject "Socrates", the predicate "wise", and the copula "is".
The subject and the predicate are the ''terms'' of the proposition. In this sense, Aristotelian logic does not contain complex propositions made up of various simple propositions.
It differs in this aspect from propositional logic, in which any two propositions can be linked using a logical connective like "and" to form a new complex proposition.

Aristotelian logic differs from predicate logic in that the subject is either ''universal'', ''particular'', ''indefinite'', or ''singular''.
For example, the term "all humans" is a universal subject in the proposition "all humans are mortal". A similar proposition could be formed by replacing it with the particular term "some humans", the indefinite term "a human", or the singular term "Socrates".
In predicate logic, on the other hand, universal and particular propositions would be expressed by using a
quantifier and two predicates.
Another important difference is that Aristotelian logic only includes predicates for simple
properties
Property is the ownership of land, resources, improvements or other tangible objects, or intellectual property.
Property may also refer to:
Mathematics
* Property (mathematics)
Philosophy and science
* Property (philosophy), in philosophy a ...
of entities, but lacks predicates corresponding to
relations between entities. The predicate can be linked to the subject in two ways: either by affirming it or by denying it.
For example, the proposition "Socrates is not a cat" involves the denial of the predicate "cat" to the subject "Socrates". Using different combinations of subjects and predicates, a great variety of propositions and syllogisms can be formed. Syllogisms are characterized by the fact that the premises are linked to each other and to the conclusion by sharing one predicate in each case.
Thus, these three propositions contain three predicates, referred to as ''major term'', ''minor term'', and ''middle term''.
The central aspect of Aristotelian logic involves classifying all possible syllogisms into valid and invalid arguments according to how the propositions are formed.
For example, the syllogism "all men are mortal; Socrates is a man; therefore Socrates is mortal" is valid. The syllogism "all cats are mortal; Socrates is mortal; therefore Socrates is a cat", on the other hand, is invalid.
Classical
Propositional logic
Propositional logic comprises formal systems in which formulae are built from
atomic propositions using
logical connectives. For instance, propositional logic represents the
conjunction
Conjunction may refer to:
* Conjunction (grammar), a part of speech
* Logical conjunction, a mathematical operator
** Conjunction introduction, a rule of inference of propositional logic
* Conjunction (astronomy)
In astronomy, a conjunction occ ...
of two atomic propositions
and
as the complex formula
. Unlike predicate logic where terms and predicates are the smallest units, propositional logic takes full propositions with truth values as its most basic component.
Thus, propositional logics can only represent logical relationships that arise from the way complex propositions are built from simpler ones; it cannot represent inferences that results from the inner structure of a proposition.
First-order logic

First-order logic includes the same propositional connectives as propositional logic but differs from it because it articulates the internal structure of propositions. This happens through devices such as singular terms, which refer to particular objects,
predicates, which refer to properties and relations, and quantifiers, which treat notions like "some" and "all".
For example, to express the proposition "this raven is black", one may use the predicate
for the property "black" and the singular term
referring to the raven to form the expression
. To express that some objects are black, the existential quantifier
is combined with the variable
to form the proposition
. First-order logic contains various rules of inference that determine how expressions articulated this way can form valid arguments, for example, that one may infer
from
.

The development of first-order logic is usually attributed to
Gottlob Frege, who is also credited as one of the founders of
analytic philosophy
Analytic philosophy is a branch and tradition of philosophy using analysis, popular in the Western world and particularly the Anglosphere, which began around the turn of the 20th century in the contemporary era in the United Kingdom, United ...
. However, the formulation of first-order logic most often used today is found in
Principles of Mathematical Logic by
David Hilbert and
Wilhelm Ackermann in 1928. The analytical generality of first-order logic allowed the formalization of mathematics, drove the investigation of
set theory, and allowed the development of Alfred Tarski's approach to
model theory. It provides the foundation of modern
mathematical logic.
Extended
Modal logic
Many extended logics take the form of modal logic by introducing modal operators. Modal logics were originally developed to represent statements about necessity and possibility. For instance the modal formula
can be read as "possibly
" while
can be read as "necessarily
". Modal logics can be used to represent different phenomena depending on what ''flavor'' of necessity and possibility is under consideration. When
is used to represent
epistemic necessity,
states that
is known. When
is used to represent
deontic necessity,
states that
is a moral or legal obligation. Within philosophy, modal logics are widely used in
formal epistemology,
formal ethics, and metaphysics. Within
linguistic semantics, systems based on modal logic are used to analyze
linguistic modality
In linguistics and philosophy, modality refers to the ways language can express various relationships to reality or truth. For instance, a modal expression may convey that something is likely, desirable, or permissible. Quintessential modal ...
in natural languages.
Other fields such as
computer science and set theory have applied the
relational semantics
Kripke semantics (also known as relational semantics or frame semantics, and often confused with possible world semantics) is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems created in the late 1950s and early 1960s by Saul Kripke and André ...
for modal logic beyond its original conceptual motivation, using it to provide insight into patterns including the
set-theoretic multiverse and
transition systems in computation.
Higher order logic
Higher-order logics extend classical logic not by using modal operators but by introducing new forms of quantification.
Quantifiers correspond to terms like "all" or "some". In classical first-order logic, quantifiers are only applied to individuals. The formula (''some'' apples are sweet) is an example of the
existential quantifier applied to the individual variable . In higher-order logics, quantification is also allowed over predicates. This increases its expressive power. For example, to express the idea that Mary and John share some qualities, one could use the formula . In this case, the existential quantifier is applied to the predicate variable .
The added expressive power is especially useful for mathematics since it allows for more succinct formulations of mathematical theories.
But it has various drawbacks in regard to its meta-logical properties and ontological implications, which is why first-order logic is still much more widely used.
Deviant
A great variety of deviant logics have been proposed. One major paradigm is
intuitionistic logic, which rejects the
law of the excluded middle
In logic, the law of excluded middle (or the principle of excluded middle) states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the so-called three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontra ...
. Intuitionism was developed by the Dutch mathematicians
L.E.J. Brouwer and
Arend Heyting to underpin their
constructive approach to mathematics, in which the existence of a mathematical object can only be proven by constructing it. Intuitionism was further pursued by
Gerhard Gentzen,
Kurt Gödel,
Michael Dummett
Sir Michael Anthony Eardley Dummett (27 June 1925 – 27 December 2011) was an English academic described as "among the most significant British philosophers of the last century and a leading campaigner for racial tolerance and equality." He w ...
, among others. Intuitionistic logic is of great interest to computer scientists, as it is a
constructive logic and sees many applications, such as extracting verified programs from proofs and influencing the design of
programming languages through the
formulae-as-types correspondence. It is closely related to nonclassical systems such as
Gödel–Dummett logic and
inquisitive logic.
Multi-valued logics depart from classicality by rejecting the
principle of bivalence which requires all propositions to be either true or false. For instance,
Jan Łukasiewicz and
Stephen Cole Kleene both proposed
ternary logics which have a third truth value representing that a statement's truth value is indeterminate. These logics have seen applications including to
presupposition
In the branch of linguistics known as pragmatics, a presupposition (or PSP) is an implicit assumption about the world or background belief relating to an utterance whose truth is taken for granted in discourse. Examples of presuppositions incl ...
in linguistics.
Fuzzy logics are multivalued logics that have an infinite number of "degrees of truth", represented by a
real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a ''continuous'' one- dimensional quantity such as a distance, duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that values can have arbitrarily small variations. Ever ...
between 0 and 1.
Paraconsistent logics are logical systems that can deal with contradictions. They are formulated to avoid the principle of explosion: for them, it is not the case that anything follows from a contradiction.
They are often motivated by
dialetheism, the view that contradictions are real or that reality itself is contradictory.
Graham Priest is an important contemporary proponent of this position and similar views have been ascribed to
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (; ; 27 August 1770 – 14 November 1831) was a German philosopher. He is one of the most important figures in German idealism and one of the founding figures of modern Western philosophy. His influence extends ...
.
Informal
The ''pragmatic'' or ''dialogical approach'' to informal logic sees arguments as
speech act
In the philosophy of language and linguistics, speech act is something expressed by an individual that not only presents information but performs an action as well. For example, the phrase "I would like the kimchi; could you please pass it to me ...
s and not merely as a set of premises together with a conclusion.
As speech acts, they occur in a certain context, like a
dialogue, which affects the standards of right and wrong arguments.
A prominent version by
Douglas N. Walton understands a dialogue as a game between two players.
The initial position of each player is characterized by the propositions to which they are committed and the conclusion they intend to prove. Dialogues are games of persuasion: each player has the goal of convincing the opponent of their own conclusion.
This is achieved by making arguments: arguments are the moves of the game.
They affect to which propositions the players are committed. A winning move is a successful argument that takes the opponent's commitments as premises and shows how one's own conclusion follows from them.
This is usually not possible straight away. For this reason, it is normally necessary to formulate a sequence of arguments as intermediary steps, each of which brings the opponent a little closer to one's intended conclusion. Besides these positive arguments leading one closer to victory, there are also negative arguments preventing the opponent's victory by denying their conclusion.
Whether an argument is correct depends on whether it promotes the progress of the dialogue. Fallacies, on the other hand, are violations of the standards of proper argumentative rules.
These standards also depend on the type of dialogue. For example, the standards governing the scientific discourse differ from the standards in business negiotiations.
The ''epistemic approach'' to informal logic, on the other hand, focuses on the epistemic role of arguments.
It is based on the idea that arguments aim to increase our knowledge. They achieve this by linking justified beliefs to beliefs that are not yet justified.
Correct arguments succeed at expanding knowledge while fallacies are epistemic failures: they do not justify the belief in their conclusion.
In this sense, logical normativity consists in epistemic success or rationality.
For example, the fallacy of begging the question is a ''fallacy'' because it fails to provide independent justification for its conclusion, even though it is deductively valid.
The
Bayesian approach is one example of an epistemic approach.
Central to Bayesianism is not just whether the agent believes something but the degree to which they believe it, the so-called ''credence''. Degrees of belief are understood as
subjective probabilities in the believed proposition, i.e. as how certain the agent is that the proposition is true.
On this view, reasoning can be interpreted as a process of changing one's credences, often in reaction to new incoming information.
Correct reasoning, and the arguments it is based on, follows the laws of probability, for example, the
principle of conditionalization. Bad or irrational reasoning, on the other hand, violates these laws.
Areas of research
Logic is studied in various fields. In many cases, this is done by applying its formal method to specific topics outside its scope, like to ethics or computer science.
In other cases, logic itself is made the subject of research in another discipline. This can happen in diverse ways, like by investigating the philosophical presuppositions of fundamental logical concepts, by interpreting and analyzing logic through mathematical structures, or by studying and comparing abstract properties of formal logical systems.
Philosophy of logic and philosophical logic
''Philosophy of logic'' is the philosophical discipline studying the scope and nature of logic.
It investigates many presuppositions implicit in logic, like how to define its fundamental concepts or the metaphysical assumptions associated with them.
It is also concerned with how to classify the different logical systems and considers the
ontological commitments they incur.
''Philosophical logic'' is one important area within the philosophy of logic. It studies the application of logical methods to philosophical problems in fields like metaphysics, ethics, and epistemology.
This application usually happens in the form of
extended or
deviant logical systems.
Mathematical logic
Mathematical logic is the study of logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory,
proof theory
Proof theory is a major branchAccording to Wang (1981), pp. 3–4, proof theory is one of four domains mathematical logic, together with model theory, axiomatic set theory, and recursion theory. Barwise (1978) consists of four corresponding part ...
, set theory, and
computability theory
Computability theory, also known as recursion theory, is a branch of mathematical logic, computer science, and the theory of computation that originated in the 1930s with the study of computable functions and Turing degrees. The field has since ...
.

Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of formal systems of logic. However, it can also include attempts to use logic to analyze mathematical reasoning or to establish logic-based
foundations of mathematics
Foundations of mathematics is the study of the philosophical and logical and/or algorithmic basis of mathematics, or, in a broader sense, the mathematical investigation of what underlies the philosophical theories concerning the nature of mathem ...
.
The latter was a major concern in early 20th century mathematical logic, which pursued the program of
logicism pioneered by philosopher-logicians such as Gottlob Frege and
Bertrand Russell. Mathematical theories were supposed to be logical
tautologies, and the programme was to show this by means of a reduction of mathematics to logic.
The various attempts to carry this out met with failure, from the crippling of Frege's project in his ''Grundgesetze'' by
Russell's paradox, to the defeat of
Hilbert's program
In mathematics, Hilbert's program, formulated by German mathematician David Hilbert in the early part of the 20th century, was a proposed solution to the foundational crisis of mathematics, when early attempts to clarify the foundations of mathem ...
by
Gödel's incompleteness theorems.
Set theory originated in the study of the infinite by
Georg Cantor, and it has been the source of many of the most challenging and important issues in mathematical logic. They include
Cantor's theorem
In mathematical set theory, Cantor's theorem is a fundamental result which states that, for any set A, the set of all subsets of A, the power set of A, has a strictly greater cardinality than A itself.
For finite sets, Cantor's theorem can ...
, the status of the
Axiom of Choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
, the question of the independence of the
continuum hypothesis
In mathematics, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states that
or equivalently, that
In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this is equivalent to ...
, and the modern debate on
large cardinal axioms.
Recursion theory
Computability theory, also known as recursion theory, is a branch of mathematical logic, computer science, and the theory of computation that originated in the 1930s with the study of computable functions and Turing degrees. The field has since ...
captures the idea of computation in logical and
arithmetic terms; its most classical achievements are the undecidability of the
Entscheidungsproblem
In mathematics and computer science, the ' (, ) is a challenge posed by David Hilbert and Wilhelm Ackermann in 1928. The problem asks for an algorithm that considers, as input, a statement and answers "Yes" or "No" according to whether the stat ...
by
Alan Turing, and his presentation of the
Church–Turing thesis.
Today recursion theory is mostly concerned with the more refined problem of
complexity class
In computational complexity theory, a complexity class is a set of computational problems of related resource-based complexity. The two most commonly analyzed resources are time and memory.
In general, a complexity class is defined in terms ...
es and the classification of
degrees of unsolvability.
Computational logic

In computer science, logic is studied as part of the
theory of computation
In theoretical computer science and mathematics, the theory of computation is the branch that deals with what problems can be solved on a model of computation, using an algorithm, how efficiently they can be solved or to what degree (e.g., ...
. Key areas of logic that are relevant to computing include computability theory, modal logic, and
category theory. Early computer machinery was based on ideas from logic such as the
lambda calculus. Computer scientists also apply concepts from logic to problems in computing and vice versa. The works of
Claude Shannon were influential in this regard. He showed how
boolean logic
In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denoted 1 and 0, whereas in ...
can be used to understand and implement computer circuits. The interaction between the two disciplines can be seen, for example, in how modern
artificial intelligence builds on logicians' work in
argumentation theory, while
automated theorem proving can assist logicians in finding and checking proofs. In
logic programming
Logic programming is a programming paradigm which is largely based on formal logic. Any program written in a logic programming language is a set of sentences in logical form, expressing facts and rules about some problem domain. Major logic pr ...
languages such as
Prolog
Prolog is a logic programming language associated with artificial intelligence and computational linguistics.
Prolog has its roots in first-order logic, a formal logic, and unlike many other programming languages, Prolog is intended primaril ...
, a program computes the consequences of logical axioms and rules to answer a query.
Formal semantics of natural language
Formal semantics, a subfield of both
linguistics and philosophy, uses logic to analyze meaning in natural language. It is an empirical field which seeks to characterize the denotations of linguistic expressions and explain how those denotations are
composed from the meanings of their parts. The field was developed by
Richard Montague and
Barbara Partee
Barbara Hall Partee (born June 23, 1940) is a Distinguished University Professor Emerita of Linguistics and Philosophy at the University of Massachusetts Amherst (UMass).
Biography
Born in Englewood, New Jersey, Partee grew up in the Baltimo ...
in the 1970s, and remains an active area of research. Central questions include
scope,
binding, and linguistic modality.
Epistemology of logic
The epistemology of logic investigates how one knows that an argument is valid or that a proposition is logically true.
This includes questions like how to justify that modus ponens is a valid rule of inference or that contradictions are false.
The traditionally dominant view is that this form of logical understanding belongs to knowledge
a priori.
In this regard, it is often argued that the
mind has a special faculty to examine relations between pure ideas and that this faculty is also responsible for apprehending logical truths.
A similar approach understands the rules of logic in terms of
linguistic conventions. On this view, the laws of logic are trivial since they are true by definition: they just express the meanings of the logical vocabulary.
Important objections to the view that logic is knowable a priori were presented in the 20th century by
W. V. Quine and
Hilary Putnam
Hilary Whitehall Putnam (; July 31, 1926 – March 13, 2016) was an American philosopher, mathematician, and computer scientist, and a major figure in analytic philosophy in the second half of the 20th century. He made significant contributions ...
. In his paper "
Is Logic Empirical?",
Putnam builds on a suggestion by Quine and argues that, in general, the facts of propositional logic have a similar epistemological status as facts about the physical universe. This pertains, for example, to the laws of
mechanics or of
general relativity, and in particular to what physicists have learned about quantum mechanics. According to Putnam, these insights provide a compelling case for abandoning certain familiar principles of classical logic: if one wants to be a
realist about the physical phenomena described by quantum theory, then one should abandon the
principle of distributivity. He suggests that classical logic be replaced with the
quantum logic proposed by
Garrett Birkhoff and
John von Neumann.
History
Logic was developed independently in several cultures during antiquity. One major early contributor was
Aristotle
Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatetic school of ...
, who developed term logic in his ''
Organon
The ''Organon'' ( grc, Ὄργανον, meaning "instrument, tool, organ") is the standard collection of Aristotle's six works on logical analysis and dialectic. The name ''Organon'' was given by Aristotle's followers, the Peripatetics.
The six ...
'' and ''
Prior Analytics
The ''Prior Analytics'' ( grc-gre, Ἀναλυτικὰ Πρότερα; la, Analytica Priora) is a work by Aristotle on reasoning, known as his syllogistic, composed around 350 BCE. Being one of the six extant Aristotelian writings on logic ...
''.
In this approach, ''judgements'' are broken down into ''propositions'' consisting of two terms that are related by one of a fixed number of relations. Inferences are expressed by means of syllogisms that consist of two propositions sharing a common term as premise, and a conclusion that is a proposition involving the two unrelated terms from the premises. Aristotle's monumental insight was the notion that arguments can be characterized in terms of their form. The later logician Łukasiewicz described this insight as "one of Aristotle's greatest inventions".
Aristotle's system of logic was also responsible for the introduction of
hypothetical syllogism
In classical logic, a hypothetical syllogism is a valid argument form, a syllogism with a conditional statement for one or both of its premises.
An example in English:
:If I do not wake up, then I cannot go to work.
:If I cannot go to work, t ...
,
temporal modal logic,
and inductive logic,
as well as influential vocabulary such as
terms,
predicables, syllogisms and propositions. Aristotelian logic was highly regarded in classical and medieval times, both in Europe and the Middle East. It remained in wide use in the West until the early 19th century.
It has now been superseded by later work, though many of its key insights are still present in modern systems of logic.
Ibn Sina (Avicenna) (980–1037 CE) was the founder of Avicennian logic, which replaced Aristotelian logic as the dominant system of
logic in the Islamic world.
It also had an important influence on Western medieval writers such as
Albertus Magnus and
William of Ockham. Ibn Sina wrote on the hypothetical syllogism
and on the
propositional calculus. He developed an original "temporally modalized" syllogistic theory, involving temporal logic and modal logic.
He also made use of inductive logic, such as
his methods of agreement, difference, and concomitant variation, which are critical to the
scientific method.
Fakhr al-Din al-Razi (b. 1149) criticised Aristotle's "first figure" and formulated an early system of inductive logic, foreshadowing the system of inductive logic developed by
John Stuart Mill (1806–1873).
In Europe during the later medieval period, major efforts were made to show that Aristotle's ideas were compatible with
Christian faith. During the
High Middle Ages
The High Middle Ages, or High Medieval Period, was the period of European history that lasted from AD 1000 to 1300. The High Middle Ages were preceded by the Early Middle Ages and were followed by the Late Middle Ages, which ended around AD ...
, logic became a main focus of philosophers, who would engage in critical logical analyses of philosophical arguments, often using variations of the methodology of
scholasticism. Initially, medieval Christian scholars drew on the classics that had been preserved in Latin through commentaries by such figures such as
Boethius.
Later, the work of Islamic philosophers such as Ibn Sina and
Ibn Rushd (Averroes 1126–1198 CE) were drawn on. This expanded the range of ancient works available to medieval Christian scholars since more Greek work was available to Muslim scholars that had been preserved in Latin commentaries. In 1323, William of Ockham's influential ''
Summa Logicae'' was released.
By the 18th century, the structured approach to arguments had degenerated and fallen out of favour, as depicted in
Holberg's satirical play ''
Erasmus Montanus''.
Friedrich Nietzsche criticized logic based on the claim that the logical structure of thought is a useful tool for human survival while "
gic itself rests upon assumptions to which nothing in the world of reality corresponds".
The
Chinese logical philosopher
Gongsun Long () proposed the paradox "One and one cannot become two, since neither becomes two". In China, the tradition of scholarly investigation into logic, however, was repressed by the
Qin dynasty following the legalist philosophy of
Han Feizi.
In India, the
Anviksiki school of logic was founded by
Medhātithi (c. 6th century BCE). Innovations in the scholastic school, called
Nyaya
( Sanskrit: न्याय, ''nyā-yá''), literally meaning "justice", "rules", "method" or "judgment",[Navya-Nyāya school. By the 16th century, it developed theories resembling modern logic, such as Gottlob Frege's "distinction between sense and reference of proper names" and his definition of number. Its development of the theory of ''restrictive conditions for universals'' anticipated some of the developments in modern set theory.][Chakrabarti, Kisor Kumar. 1976. "Some Comparisons Between Frege's Logic and Navya-Nyaya Logic." '' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research'' 36(4):554–63. .
"This paper consists of three parts. The first part deals with Frege's distinction between sense and reference of proper names and a similar distinction in Navya-Nyaya logic. In the second part we have compared Frege's definition of number to the Navya-Nyaya definition of number. In the third part we have shown how the study of the so-called 'restrictive conditions for universals' in Navya-Nyaya logic anticipated some of the developments of modern set theory."] Since 1824, Indian logic attracted the attention of many Western scholars, and has had an influence on important 19th-century logicians such as Charles Babbage
Charles Babbage (; 26 December 1791 – 18 October 1871) was an English polymath. A mathematician, philosopher, inventor and mechanical engineer, Babbage originated the concept of a digital programmable computer.
Babbage is considered ...
, Augustus De Morgan, and George Boole. In the 20th century, Western philosophers like Stanislaw Schayer and Klaus Glashoff have explored Indian logic more extensively.
The syllogistic logic developed by Aristotle predominated in the West until the mid-19th century, when interest in the foundations of mathematics stimulated the development of symbolic logic (now called mathematical logic). In 1854, George Boole published '' The Laws of Thought'', introducing symbolic logic and the principles of what is now known as Boolean logic. In 1879, Gottlob Frege published '' Begriffsschrift'', which inaugurated modern logic with the invention of quantifier notation. This invention reconciled the Aristotelian and Stoic logics in a broader system, and solved problems for which Aristotelian logic was impotent, such as the problem of multiple generality. From 1910 to 1913, Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell published ''Principia Mathematica
The ''Principia Mathematica'' (often abbreviated ''PM'') is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics written by mathematician–philosophers Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1913. ...
'' on the foundations of mathematics, attempting to derive mathematical truths from axiom
An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or f ...
s and inference rule
In the philosophy of logic, a rule of inference, inference rule or transformation rule is a logical form consisting of a function which takes premises, analyzes their syntax, and returns a conclusion (or conclusions). For example, the rule of i ...
s in symbolic logic. In 1931, Gödel raised serious problems with the foundationalist program and logic ceased to focus on such issues.
The development of logic since Frege, Russell, and Wittgenstein had a profound influence on the practice of philosophy and the perceived nature of philosophical problems (see analytic philosophy) and philosophy of mathematics
The philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that studies the assumptions, foundations, and implications of mathematics. It aims to understand the nature and methods of mathematics, and find out the place of mathematics in people' ...
. Logic, especially sentential logic, is implemented in computer logic circuits and is fundamental to computer science. Logic is commonly taught by university philosophy, sociology, advertising and literature departments, often as a compulsory discipline.
See also
References
Notes
Citations
Bibliography
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
External links
*
* Introductions and tutorials
** aimed at beginners.
*
forall x: an introduction to formal logic
by P.D. Magnus, covers sentential and quantified logic.
*
Logic Self-Taught: A Workbook
(originally prepared for on-line logic instruction).
* Essays
*
"Symbolic Logic"
an
"The Game of Logic"
Lewis Carroll, 1896.
* Online Tools
*
Interactive Syllogistic Machine
A web-based syllogistic machine for exploring fallacies, figures, terms, and modes of syllogisms.
*
A Logic Calculator
A web-based application for evaluating simple statements in symbolic logic.
* Reference material
*
by Peter Suber
Peter Dain Suber (born November 8, 1951) is a philosopher specializing in the philosophy of law and open access to knowledge. He is a Senior Researcher at the Berkman Klein Center for Internet & Society, Director of the Harvard Office for Scholarly ...
, for translating from English into logical notation.
*
Ontology and History of Logic. An Introduction
with an annotated bibliography.
{{Authority control
Abstraction
Critical thinking
Formal sciences
History of logic
History of philosophy
Intellectual history
Philosophical logic
Philosophy of logic
Reasoning
Thought