group structure and the axiom of choice
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematics a
group A group is a number of persons or things that are located, gathered, or classed together. Groups of people * Cultural group, a group whose members share the same cultural identity * Ethnic group, a group whose members share the same ethnic ide ...
is a
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
together with a binary operation on the set called multiplication that obeys the
group axioms In mathematics, a group is a set and an operation that combines any two elements of the set to produce a third element of the set, in such a way that the operation is associative, an identity element exists and every element has an inverse. Thes ...
. The
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
is an axiom of ZFC
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly conce ...
which in one form states that every set can be wellordered. In ZF set theory, i.e. ZFC without the axiom of choice, the following statements are equivalent: * For every
nonempty set In mathematics, the empty set is the unique set having no elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exists by including an axiom of empty set, while in othe ...
there exists a binary operation such that is a group. * The axiom of choice is true.


A group structure implies the axiom of choice

In this section it is assumed that every set can be endowed with a group structure . Let be a set. Let be the
Hartogs number In mathematics, specifically in axiomatic set theory, a Hartogs number is an ordinal number associated with a set. In particular, if ''X'' is any set, then the Hartogs number of ''X'' is the least ordinal α such that there is no injection from Π...
of . This is the least
cardinal number In mathematics, cardinal numbers, or cardinals for short, are a generalization of the natural numbers used to measure the cardinality (size) of sets. The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number: the number of elements in the set. T ...
such that there is no
injection Injection or injected may refer to: Science and technology * Injective function, a mathematical function mapping distinct arguments to distinct values * Injection (medicine), insertion of liquid into the body with a syringe * Injection, in broadca ...
from into . It exists without the assumption of the axiom of choice. Assume here for technical simplicity of proof that has no ordinal. Let denote multiplication in the group . For any there is an such that . Suppose not. Then there is an such that ''for all'' . But by elementary group theory, the are all different as α ranges over (i). Thus such a gives an injection from into . This is impossible since is a cardinal such that no injection into exists. Now define a map of into endowed with the lexicographical wellordering by sending to the least such that . By the above reasoning the map exists and is unique since least elements of subsets of wellordered sets are unique. It is, by elementary group theory, injective. Finally, define a wellordering on by if . It follows that every set can be wellordered and thus that the axiom of choice is true. For the crucial property expressed in (i) above to hold, and hence the whole proof, it is sufficient for to be a cancellative magma, e.g. a
quasigroup In mathematics, especially in abstract algebra, a quasigroup is an algebraic structure resembling a group in the sense that " division" is always possible. Quasigroups differ from groups mainly in that they need not be associative and need not have ...
. The cancellation property is enough to ensure that the are all different.


The axiom of choice implies a group structure

Any nonempty finite set has a group structure as a
cyclic group In group theory, a branch of abstract algebra in pure mathematics, a cyclic group or monogenous group is a group, denoted C''n'', that is generated by a single element. That is, it is a set of invertible elements with a single associative bina ...
generated by any element. Under the assumption of the axiom of choice, every infinite set is
equipotent In mathematics, two sets or classes ''A'' and ''B'' are equinumerous if there exists a one-to-one correspondence (or bijection) between them, that is, if there exists a function from ''A'' to ''B'' such that for every element ''y'' of ''B'', the ...
with a unique cardinal number which equals an aleph. Using the axiom of choice, one can show that for any family of sets (A). Moreover, by Tarski's theorem on choice, another equivalent of the axiom of choice, for all finite (B). Let be an infinite set and let denote the set of all finite subsets of . There is a natural multiplication on . For , let , where denotes the
symmetric difference In mathematics, the symmetric difference of two sets, also known as the disjunctive union, is the set of elements which are in either of the sets, but not in their intersection. For example, the symmetric difference of the sets \ and \ is \. Th ...
. This turns into a group with the empty set, , being the identity and every element being its own inverse; . The associative property, i.e. is verified using basic properties of union and set difference. Thus is a group with multiplication . Any set that can be put into bijection with a group becomes a group via the bijection. It will be shown that , and hence a one-to-one correspondence between and the group exists. For , let be the subset of consisting of all subsets of cardinality exactly . Then is the
disjoint union In mathematics, a disjoint union (or discriminated union) of a family of sets (A_i : i\in I) is a set A, often denoted by \bigsqcup_ A_i, with an injection of each A_i into A, such that the images of these injections form a partition of A ( ...
of the . The number of subsets of of cardinality is at most because every subset with elements is an element of the -fold cartesian product of . So for all (C) by (B). Putting these results together it is seen that by (A) and (C). Also, , since contains all singletons. Thus, and , so, by the
Schröder–Bernstein theorem In set theory, the Schröder–Bernstein theorem states that, if there exist injective functions and between the sets and , then there exists a bijective function . In terms of the cardinality of the two sets, this classically implies that if ...
, . This means precisely that there is a bijection between and . Finally, for define . This turns into a group. Hence every set admits a group structure.


A ZF set with no group structure

There are models of ZF in which the axiom of choice fails. In such a model, there are sets that cannot be well-ordered (call these "non-wellorderable" sets). Let be any such set. Now consider the set . If were to have a group structure, then, by the construction in first section, can be well-ordered. This contradiction shows that there is no group structure on the set . If a set is such that it cannot be endowed with a group structure, then it is necessarily non-wellorderable. Otherwise the construction in the second section does yield a group structure. However these properties are not equivalent. Namely, it is possible for sets which cannot be well-ordered to have a group structure. For example, if X is any set, then \mathcal P(X) has a group structure, with
symmetric difference In mathematics, the symmetric difference of two sets, also known as the disjunctive union, is the set of elements which are in either of the sets, but not in their intersection. For example, the symmetric difference of the sets \ and \ is \. Th ...
as the group operation. Of course, if X cannot be well-ordered, then neither can \mathcal P(X). One interesting example of sets which cannot carry a group structure is from sets X with the following two properties: # X is an infinite
Dedekind-finite In mathematics, a set ''A'' is Dedekind-infinite (named after the German mathematician Richard Dedekind) if some proper subset ''B'' of ''A'' is equinumerous to ''A''. Explicitly, this means that there exists a bijective function from ''A'' ont ...
set. In other words, X has no countably infinite subset. # If X is partitioned into finite sets, then all but finitely many of them are singletons. To see that the combination of these two cannot admit a group structure, note that given any permutation of such set must have only finite orbits, and almost all of them are necessarily singletons which implies that most elements are not moved by the permutation. Now consider the permutations given by x\mapsto a\cdot x, for a which is not the neutral element, there are infinitely many x such that a\cdot x=x, so at least one of them is not the neutral element either. Multiplying by x^ gives that a is in fact the identity element which is a contradiction. The existence of such a set X is consistent, for example given in Cohen's first model. Surprisingly, however, being an infinite Dedekind-finite set is not enough to rule out a group structure, as it is consistent that there are infinite Dedekind-finite sets with Dedekind-finite power sets.


Notes


References

* * * * * {{cite book, last1=Adkins , last2= Weintraub, title=Algebra, url=https://archive.org/details/springer_10.1007-978-1-4612-0923-2 , publisher=Springer, year=1992, series=Graduate Texts in Mathematics, volume= 136 Axiom of choice Group theory