HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In logic and mathematics, contraposition refers to the inference of going from a conditional statement into its logically equivalent contrapositive, and an associated proof method known as proof by contraposition. The contrapositive of a statement has its antecedent and
consequent A consequent is the second half of a hypothetical proposition. In the standard form of such a proposition, it is the part that follows "then". In an implication, if ''P'' implies ''Q'', then ''P'' is called the antecedent and ''Q'' is called ...
inverted and flipped. Conditional statement P \rightarrow Q. In
formulas In science, a formula is a concise way of expressing information symbolically, as in a mathematical formula or a '' chemical formula''. The informal use of the term ''formula'' in science refers to the general construct of a relationship betw ...
: the contrapositive of P \rightarrow Q is \neg Q \rightarrow \neg P . If ''P'', Then ''Q''. — If not ''Q'', Then not ''P''. ''"''If ''it is raining,'' then ''I wear my coat" —'' "If ''I don't wear my coat,'' then ''it isn't raining."'' The law of contraposition says that a conditional statement is true if, and only if, its contrapositive is true. The contrapositive ( \neg Q \rightarrow \neg P ) can be compared with three other statements: ;
Inversion Inversion or inversions may refer to: Arts * , a French gay magazine (1924/1925) * ''Inversion'' (artwork), a 2005 temporary sculpture in Houston, Texas * Inversion (music), a term with various meanings in music theory and musical set theory * ...
(the inverse), \neg P \rightarrow \neg Q:"If ''it is not raining,'' then ''I don't wear my coat''." Unlike the contrapositive, the inverse's truth value is not at all dependent on whether or not the original proposition was true, as evidenced here. ; Conversion (the converse), Q \rightarrow P:"If ''I wear my coat,'' then ''it is raining''." The converse is actually the contrapositive of the inverse, and so always has the same truth value as the inverse (which as stated earlier does not always share the same truth value as that of the original proposition). ; Negation (the logical complement), \neg (P \rightarrow Q):"''It is not the case that'' if ''it is raining'' then ''I wear my coat.''", or equivalently, "''Sometimes, when it is raining, I don't wear my coat''. " If the negation is true, then the original proposition (and by extension the contrapositive) is false. Note that if P \rightarrow Q is true and one is given that ''Q'' is false (i.e., \neg Q), then it can logically be concluded that ''P'' must be also false (i.e., \neg P). This is often called the ''law of contrapositive'', or the '' modus tollens''
rule of inference In the philosophy of logic, a rule of inference, inference rule or transformation rule is a logical form consisting of a function which takes premises, analyzes their syntax, and returns a conclusion (or conclusions). For example, the rule of in ...
.


Intuitive explanation

In the
Euler diagram An Euler diagram (, ) is a diagrammatic means of representing sets and their relationships. They are particularly useful for explaining complex hierarchies and overlapping definitions. They are similar to another set diagramming technique, Ven ...
shown, if something is in A, it must be in B as well. So we can interpret "all of A is in B" as: :A \to B It is also clear that anything that is ''not'' within B (the blue region) ''cannot'' be within A, either. This statement, which can be expressed as: :\neg B \to \neg A is the contrapositive of the above statement. Therefore, one can say that :(A \to B) \leftrightarrow (\neg B \to \neg A). In practice, this equivalence can be used to make proving a statement easier. For example, if one wishes to prove that every girl in the United States (A) has brown hair (B), one can either try to directly prove A \to B by checking that all girls in the United States do indeed have brown hair, or try to prove \neg B \to \neg A by checking that all girls without brown hair are indeed all outside the US. In particular, if one were to find at least one girl without brown hair within the US, then one would have disproved \neg B \to \neg A, and equivalently A \to B. In general, for any statement where ''A'' implies ''B'', ''not B'' always implies ''not A''. As a result, proving or disproving either one of these statements automatically proves or disproves the other, as they are logically equivalent to each other.


Formal definition

A proposition ''Q'' is implicated by a proposition ''P'' when the following relationship holds: :(P \to Q) This states that, "if P, then Q", or, "if ''Socrates is a man'', then ''Socrates is human''." In a conditional such as this, P is the antecedent, and Q is the
consequent A consequent is the second half of a hypothetical proposition. In the standard form of such a proposition, it is the part that follows "then". In an implication, if ''P'' implies ''Q'', then ''P'' is called the antecedent and ''Q'' is called ...
. One statement is the contrapositive of the other only when its antecedent is the
negated In logic, negation, also called the logical complement, is an operation that takes a proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P or \overline. It is interpreted intuitively as being true when P is false, and fals ...
consequent of the other, and vice versa. Thus a contrapositive generally takes the form of: :(\neg Q \to \neg P). That is, "If not-Q, then not-P", or, more clearly, "If Q is not the case, then ''P'' is not the case." Using our example, this is rendered as "If ''Socrates is not human'', then ''Socrates is not a man''." This statement is said to be ''contraposed'' to the original and is logically equivalent to it. Due to their logical equivalence, stating one effectively states the other; when one is true, the other is also true, and when one is false, the other is also false. Strictly speaking, a contraposition can only exist in two simple conditionals. However, a contraposition may also exist in two complex, universal conditionals, if they are similar. Thus, \forall(P \to Q), or "All Ps are Qs," is contraposed to \forall(\neg Q \to \neg P), or "All non-Qs are non-Ps."


Simple proof by definition of a conditional

In
first-order logic First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantifi ...
, the conditional is defined as: :A \to B \, \leftrightarrow \, \neg A \lor B which can be made equivalent to its contrapositive, as follows: : \begin \neg A \lor B \,& \, \leftrightarrow B \lor \neg A \\ \, & \, \leftrightarrow \neg B \to \neg A \end


Simple proof by contradiction

Let: :(A \to B)\land \neg B It is given that, if A is true, then B is true, and it is also given that B is not true. We can then show that A must not be true by contradiction. For if A were true, then B would have to also be true (by Modus Ponens). However, it is given that B is not true, so we have a contradiction. Therefore, A is not true (assuming that we are dealing with bivalent statements that are either true or false): :(A \to B) \to (\neg B \to \neg A) We can apply the same process the other way round, starting with the assumptions that: :(\neg B \to \neg A)\land A Here, we also know that B is either true or not true. If B is not true, then A is also not true. However, it is given that A is true, so the assumption that B is not true leads to a contradiction, which means that it is not the case that B is not true. Therefore, B must be true: :(\neg B \to \neg A) \to (A \to B) Combining the two proved statements together, we obtain the sought-after logical equivalence between a conditional and its contrapositive: :(A \to B) \equiv (\neg B \to \neg A)


More rigorous proof of the equivalence of contrapositives

Logical equivalence between two propositions means that they are true together or false together. To prove that contrapositives are logically equivalent, we need to understand when material implication is true or false. :P \to Q This is only false when P is true and Q is false. Therefore, we can reduce this proposition to the statement "False when P and not-Q" (i.e. "True when it is not the case that P and not-Q"): :\neg(P \land \neg Q) The elements of a
conjunction Conjunction may refer to: * Conjunction (grammar), a part of speech * Logical conjunction, a mathematical operator ** Conjunction introduction, a rule of inference of propositional logic * Conjunction (astronomy), in which two astronomical bodies ...
can be reversed with no effect (by
commutativity In mathematics, a binary operation is commutative if changing the order of the operands does not change the result. It is a fundamental property of many binary operations, and many mathematical proofs depend on it. Most familiar as the name ...
): :\neg(\neg Q \land P) We define R as equal to "\neg Q", and S as equal to \neg P (from this, \neg S is equal to \neg\neg P, which is equal to just P): :\neg(R \land \neg S) This reads "It is not the case that (''R'' is true and ''S'' is false)", which is the definition of a material conditional. We can then make this substitution: :R \to S By reverting ''R'' and ''S'' back into P and Q, we then obtain the desired contrapositive: :\neg Q \to \neg P


Comparisons


Examples

Take the statement "''All red objects have color.''" This can be equivalently expressed as "''If an object is red, then it has color.''" * The contrapositive is "''If an object does not have color, then it is not red.''" This follows logically from our initial statement and, like it, it is evidently true. * The inverse is "''If an object is not red, then it does not have color.''" An object which is blue is not red, and still has color. Therefore, in this case the inverse is false. * The converse is "''If an object has color, then it is red.''" Objects can have other colors, so the converse of our statement is false. * The negation is "''There exists a red object that does not have color.''" This statement is false because the initial statement which it negates is true. In other words, the contrapositive is logically equivalent to a given
conditional Conditional (if then) may refer to: *Causal conditional, if X then Y, where X is a cause of Y *Conditional probability, the probability of an event A given that another event B has occurred *Conditional proof, in logic: a proof that asserts a co ...
statement, though not sufficient for a
biconditional In logic and mathematics, the logical biconditional, sometimes known as the material biconditional, is the logical connective (\leftrightarrow) used to conjoin two statements and to form the statement " if and only if ", where is known as th ...
. Similarly, take the statement "''All
quadrilaterals In geometry a quadrilateral is a four-sided polygon, having four edges (sides) and four corners (vertices). The word is derived from the Latin words ''quadri'', a variant of four, and ''latus'', meaning "side". It is also called a tetragon, ...
have four sides,''" or equivalently expressed "''If a polygon is a quadrilateral, then it has four sides.''" * The contrapositive is "''If a polygon does not have four sides, then it is not a quadrilateral.''" This follows logically, and as a rule, contrapositives share the truth value of their conditional. * The inverse is "''If a polygon is not a quadrilateral, then it does not have four sides.''" In this case, unlike the last example, the inverse of the statement is true. * The converse is "''If a polygon has four sides, then it is a quadrilateral.''" Again, in this case, unlike the last example, the converse of the statement is true. * The negation is "''There is at least one quadrilateral that does not have four sides.''" This statement is clearly false. Since the statement and the converse are both true, it is called a
biconditional In logic and mathematics, the logical biconditional, sometimes known as the material biconditional, is the logical connective (\leftrightarrow) used to conjoin two statements and to form the statement " if and only if ", where is known as th ...
, and can be expressed as "A polygon is a quadrilateral ''if, and only if,'' it has four sides." (The phrase ''if and only if'' is sometimes abbreviated as ''iff''.) That is, having four sides is both necessary to be a quadrilateral, and alone sufficient to deem it a quadrilateral.


Truth

* If a statement is true, then its contrapositive is true (and vice versa). * If a statement is false, then its contrapositive is false (and vice versa). * If a statement's inverse is true, then its converse is true (and vice versa). * If a statement's inverse is false, then its converse is false (and vice versa). * If a statement's negation is false, then the statement is true (and vice versa). * If a statement (or its contrapositive) and the inverse (or the converse) are both true or both false, then it is known as a
logical biconditional In logic and mathematics, the logical biconditional, sometimes known as the material biconditional, is the logical connective (\leftrightarrow) used to conjoin two statements and to form the statement " if and only if ", where is known as t ...
.


Application

Because the contrapositive of a statement always has the same truth value (truth or falsity) as the statement itself, it can be a powerful tool for proving mathematical theorems (especially if the truth of the contrapositive is easier to establish than the truth of the statement itself). A proof by contraposition (contrapositive) is a direct proof of the contrapositive of a statement. However, indirect methods such as
proof by contradiction In logic and mathematics, proof by contradiction is a form of proof that establishes the truth or the validity of a proposition, by showing that assuming the proposition to be false leads to a contradiction. Proof by contradiction is also known a ...
can also be used with contraposition, as, for example, in the proof of the irrationality of the square root of 2. By the definition of a rational number, the statement can be made that "''If \sqrt is rational, then it can be expressed as an irreducible fraction''". This statement is true because it is a restatement of a definition. The contrapositive of this statement is "''If \sqrt cannot be expressed as an irreducible fraction, then it is not rational''". This contrapositive, like the original statement, is also true. Therefore, if it can be proven that \sqrt cannot be expressed as an irreducible fraction, then it must be the case that \sqrt is not a rational number. The latter can be proved by contradiction. The previous example employed the contrapositive of a definition to prove a theorem. One can also prove a theorem by proving the contrapositive of the theorem's statement. To prove that ''if a positive integer ''N'' is a non-square number, its square root is irrational'', we can equivalently prove its contrapositive, that ''if a positive integer ''N'' has a square root that is rational, then ''N'' is a square number.'' This can be shown by setting equal to the rational expression ''a/b'' with ''a'' and ''b'' being positive integers with no common prime factor, and squaring to obtain ''N'' = ''a''2/''b''2 and noting that since ''N'' is a positive integer ''b''=1 so that ''N'' = ''a''2, a square number.


Correspondence to other mathematical frameworks


Intuitionistic logic

In intuitionistic logic, the statement P \to Q cannot be proven to be equivalent to \lnot Q \to \lnot P. We can prove that P \to Q implies \lnot Q \to \lnot P, but the reverse implication, from \lnot Q \to \lnot P to P \to Q, requires the
law of the excluded middle In logic, the law of excluded middle (or the principle of excluded middle) states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the so-called three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontradi ...
or an equivalent axiom.


Probability calculus

''Contraposition'' represents an instance of
Bayes' theorem In probability theory and statistics, Bayes' theorem (alternatively Bayes' law or Bayes' rule), named after Thomas Bayes, describes the probability of an event, based on prior knowledge of conditions that might be related to the event. For examp ...
which in a specific form can be expressed as: \Pr(\lnot P\mid \lnot Q) = \frac. In the equation above the
conditional probability In probability theory, conditional probability is a measure of the probability of an event occurring, given that another event (by assumption, presumption, assertion or evidence) has already occurred. This particular method relies on event B occur ...
\Pr(\lnot Q\mid P) generalizes the logical statement P \to \lnot Q, i.e. in addition to assigning TRUE or FALSE we can also assign any probability to the statement. The term a(P) denotes the
base rate In probability and statistics, the base rate (also known as prior probabilities) is the class of probabilities unconditional on "featural evidence" (likelihoods). For example, if 1% of the population were medical professionals, and remaining ...
(aka. the prior probability) of P. Assume that \Pr(\lnot Q \mid P) = 1 is equivalent to P\to \lnot Q being TRUE, and that \Pr(\lnot Q \mid P) = 0 is equivalent to P \to \lnot Q being FALSE. It is then easy to see that \Pr(\lnot P \mid \lnot Q) = 1 when \Pr(Q\mid P) = 1 i.e. when P \to Q is TRUE. This is because \Pr(\lnot Q\mid P) = 1 - \Pr(Q\mid P) = 0 so that the fraction on the right-hand side of the equation above is equal to 1, and hence \Pr(\lnot P\mid \lnot Q) = 1 which is equivalent to \lnot Q \to \lnot P being TRUE. Hence,
Bayes' theorem In probability theory and statistics, Bayes' theorem (alternatively Bayes' law or Bayes' rule), named after Thomas Bayes, describes the probability of an event, based on prior knowledge of conditions that might be related to the event. For examp ...
represents a generalization of ''contraposition''.


Subjective logic

''Contraposition'' represents an instance of the subjective Bayes' theorem in subjective logic expressed as: (\omega^_,\omega^_) = (\omega^_,\omega^_)\,\widetilde\, a_\,, where (\omega^_,\omega^_) denotes a pair of binomial conditional opinions given by source A. The parameter a_ denotes the
base rate In probability and statistics, the base rate (also known as prior probabilities) is the class of probabilities unconditional on "featural evidence" (likelihoods). For example, if 1% of the population were medical professionals, and remaining ...
(aka. the prior probability) of P. The pair of derivative inverted conditional opinions is denoted (\omega^_,\omega^_). The conditional opinion \omega^_ generalizes the logical statement P \to Q, i.e. in addition to assigning TRUE or FALSE the source A can assign any subjective opinion to the statement. The case where \omega^_ is an absolute TRUE opinion is equivalent to source A saying that P\to Q is TRUE, and the case where \omega^_ is an absolute FALSE opinion is equivalent to source A saying that P\to Q is FALSE. In the case when the conditional opinion \omega^_ is absolute TRUE the subjective Bayes' theorem operator \widetilde of subjective logic produces an absolute FALSE derivative conditional opinion \omega^_ and thereby an absolute TRUE derivative conditional opinion \omega^_ which is equivalent to \lnot Q \to \lnot P being TRUE. Hence, the subjective Bayes' theorem represents a generalization of both ''contraposition'' and
Bayes' theorem In probability theory and statistics, Bayes' theorem (alternatively Bayes' law or Bayes' rule), named after Thomas Bayes, describes the probability of an event, based on prior knowledge of conditions that might be related to the event. For examp ...
.Audun Jøsang 2016:92


See also

* ''
Reductio ad absurdum In logic, (Latin for "reduction to absurdity"), also known as (Latin for "argument to absurdity") or ''apagogical arguments'', is the form of argument that attempts to establish a claim by showing that the opposite scenario would lead to absu ...
''


References


Sources

* Audun Jøsang, 2016, ''Subjective Logic; A formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty'' Springer, Cham,


External links

* {{Mathematical logic Mathematical logic Theorems in propositional logic