HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
, a concrete category is a
category Category, plural categories, may refer to: Philosophy and general uses *Categorization, categories in cognitive science, information science and generally * Category of being * ''Categories'' (Aristotle) * Category (Kant) * Categories (Peirce) ...
that is equipped with a
faithful functor In category theory, a faithful functor is a functor that is injective on hom-sets, and a full functor is surjective on hom-sets. A functor that has both properties is called a full and faithful functor. Formal definitions Explicitly, let ''C'' ...
to the
category of sets In the mathematical field of category theory, the category of sets, denoted as Set, is the category whose objects are sets. The arrows or morphisms between sets ''A'' and ''B'' are the total functions from ''A'' to ''B'', and the composition o ...
(or sometimes to another category, ''see Relative concreteness below''). This functor makes it possible to think of the objects of the category as sets with additional
structure A structure is an arrangement and organization of interrelated elements in a material object or system, or the object or system so organized. Material structures include man-made objects such as buildings and machines and natural objects such a ...
, and of its
morphism In mathematics, particularly in category theory, a morphism is a structure-preserving map from one mathematical structure to another one of the same type. The notion of morphism recurs in much of contemporary mathematics. In set theory, morphisms ...
s as structure-preserving functions. Many important categories have obvious interpretations as concrete categories, for example the
category of topological spaces In mathematics, the category of topological spaces, often denoted Top, is the category whose objects are topological spaces and whose morphisms are continuous maps. This is a category because the composition of two continuous maps is again cont ...
and the
category of groups In mathematics, the category Grp (or Gp) has the class of all groups for objects and group homomorphisms for morphisms. As such, it is a concrete category. The study of this category is known as group theory. Relation to other categories There a ...
, and trivially also the category of sets itself. On the other hand, the homotopy category of topological spaces is not concretizable, i.e. it does not admit a faithful functor to the category of sets. A concrete category, when defined without reference to the notion of a category, consists of a
class Class or The Class may refer to: Common uses not otherwise categorized * Class (biology), a taxonomic rank * Class (knowledge representation), a collection of individuals or objects * Class (philosophy), an analytical concept used differently ...
of ''objects'', each equipped with an ''underlying set''; and for any two objects ''A'' and ''B'' a set of functions, called ''morphisms'', from the underlying set of ''A'' to the underlying set of ''B''. Furthermore, for every object ''A'', the identity function on the underlying set of ''A'' must be a morphism from ''A'' to ''A'', and the composition of a morphism from ''A'' to ''B'' followed by a morphism from ''B'' to ''C'' must be a morphism from ''A'' to ''C''.


Definition

A concrete category is a pair (''C'',''U'') such that *''C'' is a category, and *''U'' : ''C'' → Set (the category of sets and functions) is a
faithful functor In category theory, a faithful functor is a functor that is injective on hom-sets, and a full functor is surjective on hom-sets. A functor that has both properties is called a full and faithful functor. Formal definitions Explicitly, let ''C'' ...
. The functor ''U'' is to be thought of as a
forgetful functor In mathematics, in the area of category theory, a forgetful functor (also known as a stripping functor) 'forgets' or drops some or all of the input's structure or properties 'before' mapping to the output. For an algebraic structure of a given sign ...
, which assigns to every object of ''C'' its "underlying set", and to every morphism in ''C'' its "underlying function". A category ''C'' is concretizable if there exists a concrete category (''C'',''U''); i.e., if there exists a faithful functor ''U'': ''C'' → Set. All small categories are concretizable: define ''U'' so that its object part maps each object ''b'' of ''C'' to the set of all morphisms of ''C'' whose
codomain In mathematics, the codomain or set of destination of a function is the set into which all of the output of the function is constrained to fall. It is the set in the notation . The term range is sometimes ambiguously used to refer to either th ...
is ''b'' (i.e. all morphisms of the form ''f'': ''a'' → ''b'' for any object ''a'' of ''C''), and its morphism part maps each morphism ''g'': ''b'' → ''c'' of ''C'' to the function ''U''(''g''): ''U''(''b'') → ''U''(''c'') which maps each member ''f'': ''a'' → ''b'' of ''U''(''b'') to the composition ''gf'': ''a'' → ''c'', a member of ''U''(''c''). (Item 6 under Further examples expresses the same ''U'' in less elementary language via presheaves.) The Counter-examples section exhibits two large categories that are not concretizable.


Remarks

It is important to note that, contrary to intuition, concreteness is not a
property Property is a system of rights that gives people legal control of valuable things, and also refers to the valuable things themselves. Depending on the nature of the property, an owner of property may have the right to consume, alter, share, r ...
which a category may or may not satisfy, but rather a structure with which a category may or may not be equipped. In particular, a category ''C'' may admit several faithful functors into Set. Hence there may be several concrete categories (''C'', ''U'') all corresponding to the same category ''C''. In practice, however, the choice of faithful functor is often clear and in this case we simply speak of the "concrete category ''C''". For example, "the concrete category Set" means the pair (Set, ''I'') where ''I'' denotes the
identity functor In mathematics, specifically category theory, a functor is a mapping between categories. Functors were first considered in algebraic topology, where algebraic objects (such as the fundamental group) are associated to topological spaces, and m ...
Set → Set. The requirement that ''U'' be faithful means that it maps different morphisms between the same objects to different functions. However, ''U'' may map different objects to the same set and, if this occurs, it will also map different morphisms to the same function. For example, if ''S'' and ''T'' are two different topologies on the same set ''X'', then (''X'', ''S'') and (''X'', ''T'') are distinct objects in the category Top of topological spaces and continuous maps, but mapped to the same set ''X'' by the forgetful functor Top → Set. Moreover, the identity morphism (''X'', ''S'') → (''X'', ''S'') and the identity morphism (''X'', ''T'') → (''X'', ''T'') are considered distinct morphisms in Top, but they have the same underlying function, namely the identity function on ''X''. Similarly, any set with four elements can be given two non-isomorphic group structures: one isomorphic to \mathbb/2\mathbb \times \mathbb/2\mathbb, and the other isomorphic to \mathbb/4\mathbb.


Further examples

# Any group ''G'' may be regarded as an "abstract" category with one arbitrary object, \ast, and one morphism for each element of the group. This would not be counted as concrete according to the intuitive notion described at the top of this article. But every faithful ''G''-set (equivalently, every representation of ''G'' as a group of permutations) determines a faithful functor ''G'' → Set. Since every group acts faithfully on itself, ''G'' can be made into a concrete category in at least one way. # Similarly, any
poset In mathematics, especially order theory, a partially ordered set (also poset) formalizes and generalizes the intuitive concept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set. A poset consists of a set together with a binary r ...
''P'' may be regarded as an abstract category with a unique arrow ''x'' → ''y'' whenever ''x'' ≤ ''y''. This can be made concrete by defining a functor ''D'' : ''P'' → Set which maps each object ''x'' to D(x)=\ and each arrow ''x'' → ''y'' to the inclusion map D(x) \hookrightarrow D(y). # The category Rel whose objects are sets and whose morphisms are relations can be made concrete by taking ''U'' to map each set ''X'' to its power set 2^X and each relation R \subseteq X \times Y to the function \rho: 2^X \rightarrow 2^Y defined by \rho(A)=\. Noting that power sets are
complete lattice In mathematics, a complete lattice is a partially ordered set in which ''all'' subsets have both a supremum (join) and an infimum (meet). A lattice which satisfies at least one of these properties is known as a ''conditionally complete lattice.'' ...
s under inclusion, those functions between them arising from some relation ''R'' in this way are exactly the supremum-preserving maps. Hence Rel is equivalent to a full subcategory of the category Sup of complete lattices and their sup-preserving maps. Conversely, starting from this equivalence we can recover ''U'' as the composite Rel → Sup → Set of the forgetful functor for Sup with this embedding of Rel in Sup. # The category Setop can be embedded into Rel by representing each set as itself and each function ''f'': ''X'' → ''Y'' as the relation from ''Y'' to ''X'' formed as the set of pairs (''f''(''x''), ''x'') for all ''x'' ∈ ''X''; hence Setop is concretizable. The forgetful functor which arises in this way is the contravariant powerset functor Setop → Set. # It follows from the previous example that the opposite of any concretizable category ''C'' is again concretizable, since if ''U'' is a faithful functor ''C'' → Set then ''C''op may be equipped with the composite ''C''op → Setop → Set. # If ''C'' is any small category, then there exists a faithful functor ''P'' : Set''C''op → Set which maps a presheaf ''X'' to the coproduct \coprod_ X(c). By composing this with the
Yoneda embedding In mathematics, the Yoneda lemma is arguably the most important result in category theory. It is an abstract result on functors of the type ''morphisms into a fixed object''. It is a vast generalisation of Cayley's theorem from group theory (vie ...
''Y'':''C'' → Set''C''op one obtains a faithful functor ''C'' → Set. # For technical reasons, the category Ban1 of
Banach spaces In mathematics, more specifically in functional analysis, a Banach space (pronounced ) is a complete normed vector space. Thus, a Banach space is a vector space with a metric that allows the computation of vector length and distance between vector ...
and linear contractions is often equipped not with the "obvious" forgetful functor but the functor ''U''1 : Ban1 → Set which maps a Banach space to its (closed)
unit ball Unit may refer to: Arts and entertainment * UNIT, a fictional military organization in the science fiction television series ''Doctor Who'' * Unit of action, a discrete piece of action (or beat) in a theatrical presentation Music * ''Unit'' (a ...
. #The category Cat whose objects are small categories and whose morphisms are functors can be made concrete by sending each category C to the set containing its objects and morphisms. Functors can be simply viewed as functions acting on the objects and morphisms.


Counter-examples

The category
hTop htop is an interactive system-monitor process-viewer and process-manager. It is designed as an alternative to the Unix program top. System monitor It shows a frequently updated list of the processes running on a computer, normally ordered by ...
, where the objects are
topological space In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a geometrical space in which closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric distance. More specifically, a topological space is a set whose elements are called poin ...
s and the morphisms are
homotopy classes In topology, a branch of mathematics, two continuous functions from one topological space to another are called homotopic (from grc, ὁμός "same, similar" and "place") if one can be "continuously deformed" into the other, such a defor ...
of continuous functions, is an example of a category that is not concretizable. While the objects are sets (with additional structure), the morphisms are not actual functions between them, but rather classes of functions. The fact that there does not exist ''any'' faithful functor from hTop to Set was first proven by Peter Freyd. In the same article, Freyd cites an earlier result that the category of "small categories and
natural equivalence In category theory, a branch of mathematics, a natural transformation provides a way of transforming one functor into another while respecting the internal structure (i.e., the composition of morphisms) of the Category (mathematics), categories in ...
-classes of functors" also fails to be concretizable.


Implicit structure of concrete categories

Given a concrete category (''C'', ''U'') and a
cardinal number In mathematics, cardinal numbers, or cardinals for short, are a generalization of the natural numbers used to measure the cardinality (size) of sets. The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number: the number of elements in the set. ...
''N'', let ''UN'' be the functor ''C'' → Set determined by ''UN(c) = (U(c))N''. Then a
subfunctor In category theory, a branch of mathematics, a subfunctor is a special type of functor that is an analogue of a subset. Definition Let C be a category, and let ''F'' be a contravariant functor from C to the category of sets Set. A contravariant ...
of ''UN'' is called an ''N-ary predicate'' and a
natural transformation In category theory, a branch of mathematics, a natural transformation provides a way of transforming one functor into another while respecting the internal structure (i.e., the composition of morphisms) of the categories involved. Hence, a natur ...
''UN'' → ''U'' an ''N-ary operation''. The class of all ''N''-ary predicates and ''N''-ary operations of a concrete category (''C'',''U''), with ''N'' ranging over the class of all cardinal numbers, forms a
large Large means of great size. Large may also refer to: Mathematics * Arbitrarily large, a phrase in mathematics * Large cardinal, a property of certain transfinite numbers * Large category, a category with a proper class of objects and morphisms ...
signature A signature (; from la, signare, "to sign") is a Handwriting, handwritten (and often Stylization, stylized) depiction of someone's name, nickname, or even a simple "X" or other mark that a person writes on documents as a proof of identity and ...
. The category of models for this signature then contains a full subcategory which is
equivalent Equivalence or Equivalent may refer to: Arts and entertainment *Album-equivalent unit, a measurement unit in the music industry * Equivalence class (music) *'' Equivalent VIII'', or ''The Bricks'', a minimalist sculpture by Carl Andre *''Equiva ...
to ''C''.


Relative concreteness

In some parts of category theory, most notably
topos theory In mathematics, a topos (, ; plural topoi or , or toposes) is a category that behaves like the category of sheaves of sets on a topological space (or more generally: on a site). Topoi behave much like the category of sets and possess a notio ...
, it is common to replace the category Set with a different category ''X'', often called a ''base category''. For this reason, it makes sense to call a pair (''C'', ''U'') where ''C'' is a category and ''U'' a faithful functor ''C'' → ''X'' a concrete category over ''X''. For example, it may be useful to think of the models of a theory with ''N'' sorts as forming a concrete category over Set''N''. In this context, a concrete category over Set is sometimes called a ''construct''.


Notes


References

* Adámek, Jiří, Herrlich, Horst, & Strecker, George E.; (1990)
''Abstract and Concrete Categories''
(4.2MB PDF). Originally publ. John Wiley & Sons. {{ISBN, 0-471-60922-6. (now free on-line edition). * Freyd, Peter; (1970)

Originally published in: The Steenrod Algebra and its Applications, Springer Lecture Notes in Mathematics Vol. 168. Republished in a free on-line journal: Reprints in Theory and Applications of Categories, No. 6 (2004), with the permission of Springer-Verlag. * Rosický, Jiří; (1981). ''Concrete categories and infinitary languages''.
''Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra''
Volume 22, Issue 3. Category theory