In
linguistics, binding is the phenomenon in which
anaphoric elements such as
pronoun
In linguistics and grammar, a pronoun (abbreviated ) is a word or a group of words that one may substitute for a noun or noun phrase.
Pronouns have traditionally been regarded as one of the parts of speech, but some modern theorists would not ...
s are grammatically associated with their
antecedent
An antecedent is a preceding event, condition, cause, phrase, or word.
The etymology is from the Latin noun ''antecedentem'' meaning "something preceding", which comes from the preposition ''ante'' ("before") and the verb ''cedere'' ("to go").
...
s. For instance in the English sentence "Mary saw herself", the
anaphor
In linguistics, anaphora () is the use of an expression whose interpretation depends upon another expression in context (its antecedent or postcedent). In a narrower sense, anaphora is the use of an expression that depends specifically upon an a ...
"herself" is bound by its antecedent "Mary". Binding can be licensed or blocked in certain contexts or syntactic configurations, e.g. the pronoun "her" cannot be bound by "Mary" in the English sentence "Mary saw her". While all languages have binding, restrictions on it vary even among closely related languages. Binding has been a major area of research in
syntax and
semantics since the 1970s, and was a major for the
government and binding theory
A government is the system or group of people governing an organized community, generally a state.
In the case of its broad associative definition, government normally consists of legislature, executive, and judiciary. Government is a ...
paradigm.
Some basic examples and questions
The following sentences illustrate some basic facts of binding. The words that bear the index i should be construed as referring to the same person or thing.
::a. Fred
i is impressed with himself
i.
– Indicated reading obligatory
::b. *Fred
i is impressed with him
i.
– Indicated reading impossible
::a. *Susan
i asked Arthur to help herself
i.
– Indicated reading impossible, sentence ungrammatical
::b. Susan
i asked Arthur to help her
i.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::a. Sue
i said she
i was tired.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b. *She
i said Sue
i was tired.
– Indicated reading impossible
::a. Fred's
i friends venerate him
i.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b.
?His
i friends venerate Fred
i.
– Indicated reading unlikely
These sentences illustrate some aspects of the distribution of
reflexive and
personal
Personal may refer to:
Aspects of persons' respective individualities
* Privacy
* Personality
* Personal, personal advertisement, variety of classified advertisement used to find romance or friendship
Companies
* Personal, Inc., a Washington ...
pronouns. In the first pair of sentences, the reflexive pronoun must appear for the indicated reading to be possible. In the second pair, the personal pronoun must appear for the indicated reading to be possible. The third pair shows that at times a personal pronoun must follow its antecedent, and the fourth pair further illustrates the same point, although the acceptability judgement is not as robust. Based on such data, one sees that reflexive and personal pronouns differ in their distribution and that linear order (of a pronoun in relation to its antecedent or postcedent) is a factor influencing where at least some pronouns can appear. A theory of binding should be capable of predicting and explaining the differences in distribution seen in sentences like these. It should be able to answer questions like: What explains where a reflexive pronoun must appear as opposed to a personal pronoun? When does linear order play a role in determining where pronouns can appear? What other factor (or factors) beyond linear order help predict where pronouns can appear?
Binding domains
The following three subsections consider the binding domains that are relevant for the distribution of pronouns and nouns in English. The discussion follows the outline provided by the traditional binding theory (see below), which divides nominals into three basic categories: reflexive and reciprocal pronouns, personal pronouns, and nouns (
common
Common may refer to:
Places
* Common, a townland in County Tyrone, Northern Ireland
* Boston Common, a central public park in Boston, Massachusetts
* Cambridge Common, common land area in Cambridge, Massachusetts
* Clapham Common, originally c ...
and
proper
Proper may refer to:
Mathematics
* Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact
* Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
).
Reflexive and reciprocal pronouns ("anaphors")
When one examines the distribution of
reflexive pronouns and
reciprocal pronouns (which are often subsumed under the general category of "anaphor"), one sees that there are certain domains that are relevant, a "domain" being a syntactic unit that is
clause
In language, a clause is a constituent that comprises a semantic predicand (expressed or not) and a semantic predicate. A typical clause consists of a subject and a syntactic predicate, the latter typically a verb phrase composed of a verb with ...
-like. Reflexive and reciprocal pronouns often seek their antecedent close by, in a binding domain that is local, e.g.
::a. Fred
i praises himself
i.
– Indicated reading obligatory
::b. *Fred
i praises him
i.
– Indicated reading impossible
::a. The girls
i like each other
i.
– Indicated reading obligatory
::b. *The girls
i like them
i.
– Indicated reading impossible
These examples illustrate that there is a domain within which a reflexive or reciprocal pronoun should find its antecedent. The a-sentences are fine because the reflexive or reciprocal pronoun has its antecedent within the clause. The b-sentences, in contrast, do not allow the indicated reading, a fact illustrating that personal pronouns have a distribution that is different from that of reflexive and reciprocal pronouns. A related observation is that a reflexive and reciprocal pronoun often cannot seek its antecedent in a superordinate clause, e.g.
::a. Susan thinks that Jill
i should praise herself
i.
– Indicated reading (almost) obligatory
::b.
??Susan
i thinks that Jill should praise herself
i.
– Indicated reading very unlikely
::a. They asked whether the girls
i like each other
i.
– Indicated reading (almost) obligatory
::b.
??They
i asked whether the girls like each other
i.
– Indicated reading very unlikely
When the reflexive or reciprocal pronoun attempts to find an antecedent outside of the immediate clause containing it, it fails. In other words, it can hardly seek its antecedent in the superordinate clause. The binding domain that is relevant is the immediate clause containing it.
Personal pronouns
Personal pronouns have a distribution that is different from reflexive and reciprocal pronouns, a point that is evident with the first two b-sentences in the previous section. The local binding domain that is decisive for the distribution of reflexive and reciprocal pronouns is also decisive for personal pronouns, but in a different way. Personal pronouns seek their antecedent outside of the local binding domain containing them, e.g.
::a. Fred
i asked whether Jim mentioned him
i.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b. *Fred asked whether Jim
i mentioned him
i.
– Indicated reading impossible
::a. Gina
i hopes that Wilma will mention her
i.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b. *Gina hopes that Wilma
i will mention her
i.
– Indicated reading impossible
In these cases, the pronoun has to look outside of the embedded clause containing it to the matrix clause to find its antecedent. Hence based on such data, the relevant binding domain appears to be the clause. Further data illustrate, however, that the clause is actually not the relevant domain:
::a. Fred
i likes the picture of him
i.
– Indicated reading possible
::b. Gina
i has heard the rumor about her
i.
– Indicated reading possible
Since the pronouns appear within the same minimal clause containing their antecedents in these cases, one cannot argue that the relevant binding domain is the clause. The most one can say based on such data is that the domain is "clause-like".
Nouns
The distribution of common and proper nouns is unlike that of reflexive, reciprocal, and personal pronouns. The relevant observation in this regard is that a noun is often reluctantly coreferential with another nominal that is within its binding domain or in a superordinate binding domain, e.g.
::a. Susan
i admires herself
i.
– Indicated reading obligatory
::b. #Susan
i admires Susan
i.
– Indicated reading possible, but special context necessary
::a. Fred
i thinks that he
i is the best.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b. #Fred
i thinks that Fred
i is the best.
– Indicated reading possible, but special context necessary
The readings indicated in the a-sentences are natural, whereas the b-sentences are very unusual. Indeed, sentences like these b-sentences were judged to be impossible in the traditional binding theory according to Condition C (see below). Given a contrastive context, however, the b-sentences can work, e.g. ''Susan does not admire Jane, but rather Susan
i admires Susan
i''. One can therefore conclude that nouns are not sensitive to binding domains in the same way that reflexive, reciprocal, and personal pronouns are.
Linear order
The following subsections illustrate the extent to which pure linear order impacts the distribution of pronouns. While linear order is clearly important, it is not the only factor influencing where pronouns can appear.
Linear order is a factor
A simple hypothesis concerning the distribution of many anaphoric elements, of personal pronouns in particular, is that linear order plays a role. In most cases, a pronoun follows its antecedent, and in many cases, the coreferential reading is impossible if the pronoun precedes its antecedent. The following sentences suggest that pure linear can indeed be important for the distribution of pronouns:
::a. Jim's
i grade upsets him
i.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b.
?His
i grade upsets Jim
i.
– Indicated reading unlikely
::a. Larry's
i family avoids him
i.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b.
?His
i family avoids Larry
i.
– Indicated reading unlikely
::a. We spoke to Tina's
i mother about her
i.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b.
?We spoke to her
i mother about Tina
i.
– Indicated reading unlikely
While the coreferential readings indicated in these b-sentences are possible, they are unlikely. The order presented in the a-sentences is strongly preferred. The following, more extensive data sets further illustrate that linear order is important:
::a. Sam
i mentioned twice that he
i was hungry.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b. *He
i mentioned twice that Sam
i was hungry.
– Indicated reading impossible
::c. That Sam
i was hungry, he
i mentioned twice.
– Indicated reading possible
::d.
?That he
i was hungry, Sam
i mentioned twice.
– Indicated reading unlikely
::a. You asked Fred
i twice when he
i would study.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b. *You asked him
i twice when Fred
i would study.
– Indicated reading impossible
::c. When Fred
i would study, you asked him
i twice.
– Indicated reading possible
::d.
?When he
i would study, you asked Fred
i twice.
– Indicated reading unlikely
While the acceptability judgements here are nuanced, one can make a strong case that pure linear order is at least in part predictive of when the indicated reading is available. The a- and c-sentences allow the coreferential reading more easily than their b- and d-counterparts.
Linear order is not the only factor
While linear order is an important factor influencing the distribution of pronouns, it is not the only factor. The following sentences are similar to the c- and d-sentences in the previous section insofar as an embedded clause is present.
::a. When the boys
i are at home, they
i play video games.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b. When they
i are at home, the boys
i play video games.
– Indicated reading possible
::a. If Susan
i tries, she
i will succeed.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b. If she
i tries, Susan
i will succeed.
– Indicated reading possible
While there may be a mild preference for the order in the a-sentences here, the indicated reading in the b-sentences is also available. Hence linear order is hardly playing a role in such cases. The relevant difference between these sentences and the c- and d-sentences in the previous section is that the embedded clauses here are
adjunct clauses, whereas they are
argument
An argument is a statement or group of statements called premises intended to determine the degree of truth or acceptability of another statement called conclusion. Arguments can be studied from three main perspectives: the logical, the dialec ...
clauses above. The following examples involve adjunct phrases:
::a. Rosa
i found a scratch in Ben's picture of her
i.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b. *She
i found a scratch in Ben's picture of Rosa
i.
– Indicated reading impossible
::c.
?In Ben's picture of Rosa
i, she
i found a scratch.
– Indicated reading unlikely
::d. In Ben's picture of her
i, Rosa
i found a scratch.
– Indicated reading possible
::a. Zelda
i spent her sweetest hours in her
i bed.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b. *She
i spent her sweetest hours in Zelda's
i bed.
– Indicated reading impossible
::c.
??In Zelda's
i bed, she
i spent her sweetest hours. –
Indicated reading very unlikely
::d. In her
i bed, Zelda
i spent her sweetest hours.
– Indicated reading possible
The fact that the c-sentences marginally allow the indicated reading whereas the b-sentences do not at all allow this reading further demonstrates that linear order is important. But in this regard, the d-sentences are telling, since if linear order were the entire story, one would expect the d-sentences to be less acceptable than they are. The conclusion that one can draw from such data is that there are one or more other factors beyond linear order that are impacting the distribution of pronouns.
Configuration vs. function
Given that linear order is not the only factor influencing the distribution of pronouns, the question is what other factor or factors might also be playing a role. The traditional binding theory (see below) took
c-command to be the all important factor, but the importance of c-command for syntactic theorizing has been extensively criticized in recent years. The primary alternative to c-command is functional rank. These two competing concepts (c-command vs. rank) have been debated extensively and they continue to be debated. C-command is a configurational notion; it is defined over concrete syntactic configurations. Syntactic rank, in contrast, is a functional notion that resides in the lexicon; it is defined over the ranking of the arguments of
predicate
Predicate or predication may refer to:
* Predicate (grammar), in linguistics
* Predication (philosophy)
* several closely related uses in mathematics and formal logic:
**Predicate (mathematical logic)
**Propositional function
**Finitary relation, o ...
s. Subjects are ranked higher than objects, first objects are ranked higher than second objects, and prepositional objects are ranked lowest. The following two subsections briefly consider these competing notions.
Configuration (c-command)
C-command is a configurational notion that acknowledges the syntactic configuration as primitive. Basic
subject
Subject ( la, subiectus "lying beneath") may refer to:
Philosophy
*''Hypokeimenon'', or ''subiectum'', in metaphysics, the "internal", non-objective being of a thing
**Subject (philosophy), a being that has subjective experiences, subjective cons ...
-
object
Object may refer to:
General meanings
* Object (philosophy), a thing, being, or concept
** Object (abstract), an object which does not exist at any particular time or place
** Physical object, an identifiable collection of matter
* Goal, an ai ...
asymmetries, which are numerous in many languages, are explained by the fact that the subject appears outside of the finite verb phrase (VP) constituent, whereas the object appears inside it. Subjects therefore c-command objects, but not vice versa. C-command is defined as follows:
::C-command
::Node A c-commands node B if every node dominating A also dominates B, and neither A nor B dominates the other.
Given the binary division of the clause (S → NP + VP) associated with most
phrase structure grammar
The term phrase structure grammar was originally introduced by Noam Chomsky as the term for grammar studied previously by Emil Post and Axel Thue ( Post canonical systems). Some authors, however, reserve the term for more restricted grammars in t ...
s, this definition sees a typical subject c-commanding everything inside the
verb phrase (VP), whereas everything inside the VP is incapable of c-commanding anything outside of the VP. Some basic binding facts are explained in this manner, e.g.
::a. Larry
i promoted himself
i.
– Indicated reading obligatory
::b. *Himself
i promoted Larry
i.
– Indicated reading impossible; sentence ungrammatical
Sentence a is fine because the subject ''Larry'' c-commands the object ''himself'', whereas sentence b does not work because the object ''Larry'' does not c-command the subject ''himself''. The assumption has been that within its binding domain, a reflexive pronoun must be c-commanded by its antecedent. While this approach based on c-command makes a correct prediction much of the time, there are other cases where it fails to make the correct prediction, e.g.
::The picture of himself
i upsets Larry
i.
– Indicated reading possible
The reading indicated is acceptable in this case, but if c-command were the key notion helping to explain where the reflexive can and must appear, then the reading should be impossible since ''himself'' is not c-commanded by ''Larry''.
As reflexive and personal pronouns occur in complementary distribution, the notion of c-command can also be used to explain where personal pronouns can appear. The assumption is that personal pronouns ''cannot'' c-command their antecedent, e.g.
::a. When Alice
i felt tired, she
i lay down.
– Indicated reading easily possible
::b When she
i felt tired, Alice
i lay down.
– Indicated reading possible
In both examples, the personal pronoun ''she'' does not c-command its antecedent ''Alice'', resulting in the grammaticality of both sentences despite reversed linear order.
Function (rank)
The alternative to a c-command approach posits a ranking of syntactic functions (SUBJECT > FIRST OBJECT > SECOND OBJECT > PREPOSITIONAL OBJECT). Subject-object asymmetries are addressed in terms of this ranking. Since subjects are ranked higher than objects, an object can have the subject as its antecedent, but not vice versa. With basic cases, this approach makes the same prediction as the c-command approach. The first two sentences from the previous section are repeated here:
::a. Larry
i promoted himself
i.
– Indicated reading obligatory
::b. *Himself
i promoted Larry
i.
– Indicated reading impossible; sentence ungrammatical
Since the subject outranks the object, sentence a is predictably acceptable, the subject ''Larry'' outranking the object ''himself''. Sentence b, in contrast, is bad because the subject reflexive pronoun ''himself'' outranks its postcedent ''Larry''. In other words, this approach in terms of rank is assuming that within its binding domain, a reflexive pronoun may not outrank its antecedent (or postcedent). Consider the third example sentence from the previous section in this regard:
::The picture of himself
i upset Larry
i.
– Indicated reading possible
The approach based on rank does not require a particular configurational relationship to hold between a reflexive pronoun and its antecedent. In other words, it makes no prediction in this case, and hence does not make an incorrect prediction. The reflexive pronoun ''himself'' is embedded within the subject noun phrase, which means that it is not the subject and hence does not outrank the object ''Larry''.
A theory of binding that acknowledges both linear order and rank can at least begin to predict many of the marginal readings. When both linear order and rank combine, acceptability judgments are robust, e.g.
::a. Barbara
i hopes that she
i will be promoted.
– Linear order and rank combine to make the indicated reading easily possible.
::b. *She
i hopes that Barbara
i will be promoted.
– Linear order and rank combine to make the indicated reading impossible.
::a. Bill's
i grade upset him
i.
– Linear order alone makes the indicated reading possible; rank is not involved.
::b.
?His
i grade upset Bill
i.
– Linear order alone makes the indicated reading unlikely; rank is not involved.
This ability to address marginal readings is something that an approach combining linear order and rank can accomplish, whereas an approach that acknowledges only c-command cannot do the same.
The traditional binding theory: Conditions A, B, and C
The exploration of binding phenomena got started in the 1970s and interest peaked in the 1980s with
Government and Binding Theory
A government is the system or group of people governing an organized community, generally a state.
In the case of its broad associative definition, government normally consists of legislature, executive, and judiciary. Government is a ...
, a grammar framework in the tradition of
generative syntax that is still prominent today. The theory of binding that became widespread at that time serves now merely as reference point (since it is no longer believed to be correct). This theory distinguishes between 3 different binding conditions: A, B, and C. The theory classifies nominals according to two features,
±anaphorand
±pronominal which are binary. The binding characteristics of a nominal are determined by the values of these features, either plus or minus. Thus, a nominal that is
anaphor, -pronominalis an R-expression (referring expression), such as a
common noun
A proper noun is a noun that identifies a single entity and is used to refer to that entity (''Africa'', ''Jupiter'', ''Sarah'', ''Microsoft)'' as distinguished from a common noun, which is a noun that refers to a class of entities (''continent, ...
or a
proper name
A proper noun is a noun that identifies a single entity and is used to refer to that entity (''Africa'', ''Jupiter'', '' Sarah'', ''Microsoft)'' as distinguished from a common noun, which is a noun that refers to a class of entities (''continent ...
. A nominal that is
anaphor, +pronominalis a pronoun, such as ''he'' or ''they'', and a nominal that is
anaphor, -pronominalis a reflexive pronoun, such as ''himself'' or ''themselves''. Note that the term ''anaphor'' here is being used in a specialized sense; it essentially means "reflexive". This meaning is specific to the Government and Binding framework and has not spread beyond this framework.
[Most syntax textbooks on generative grammar use the term in this way. See for instance Carnie (2013:148).]
Based on the classifications according to these two features, three conditions are formulated:
::Condition A
::An anaphor (reflexive) must have a local (nearby) antecedent. Thus, ''John
i washed himself
i'' obeys Condition A: the antecedent of ''himself'', which is ''John'', is nearby. In contrast, *''John
i asked Mary to wash himself
i'' is unacceptable, because the reflexive and its antecedent are too far away from each other.
::Condition B
::A pronoun can have an antecedent as long as the antecedent is not local or does not c-command the pronoun. Thus ''John
i asked Mary to wash him
i'' obeys Condition B; ''John'' is the antecedent of ''him'', and ''him'' is sufficiently far away. On the other hand, *''John
i washed him
i'' is unacceptable.
::Condition C
::An R-expression cannot have an antecedent that c-commands it. Thus *''He
i asked Mary to wash John
i'' is unacceptable.
While the theory of binding that these three conditions represent is no longer held to be valid, as mentioned above, the associations with the three conditions are so firmly anchored in the study of binding that one often refers to, for example, "Condition A effects" or "Condition B effects" when describing binding phenomena.
See also
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
Notes
References
*Bresnan, Joan. 2001. Lexical–Functional Syntax. Oxford: Blackwell.
*Bruening, B. 2014. Precede-and-command revisited. Language 90(1).
*Carnie, C. 2013. Syntax: A generative introduction, 3rd edition. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
*Langacker, R. 1969. On pronominalization and the chain of command. Modern Studies in English, eds. D. Reibel & S. Schane, 160-186. Engelwood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
*Pollard, C. and I. Sag. 1992. Reflexives in English and the scope of binding theory. Linguistic Inquiry 23, 261-303.
*Pollard, C. and I. Sag. 1994. Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar. University of Chicago Press.
*
Radford, A. (2004) English syntax: An introduction. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
*Reinhart, T. 1983. Anaphora and semantic interpretation. London: Croom Helm.
Further reading
*Büring, D. 2005. Binding Theory. New York: Cambridge University Press.
*Chomsky, N.1981. Lectures on Government and Binding. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.
*Crystal, D. 1997. A dictionary of linguistics and phonetics. 4th edition. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers.
*Heim, I., and A. Kratzer. 1988. Semantics in Generative Grammar. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
*Hornstein, N. Nunes, J. Grohmann, K. 2005. Understanding Minimalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
*Reinhart, T. and E. Reuland. 1993. Reflexivity. Linguistic Inquiry 24, 657-720.
{{Formal semantics
Generative syntax
Semantics
Formal semantics (natural language)
Syntactic relationships
Syntax–semantics interface