HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In social choice and operations research, the utilitarian rule (also called the max-sum rule) is a rule saying that, among all possible alternatives, society should pick the alternative which maximizes the ''sum of the utilities'' of all individuals in society. It is a formal mathematical representation of the utilitarian philosophy.


Definition

Let X be a set of possible `states of the world' or `alternatives'. Society wishes to choose a single state from X. For example, in a
single-winner election A single-member district is an electoral district represented by a single officeholder. It contrasts with a multi-member district, which is represented by multiple officeholders. Single-member districts are also sometimes called single-winner vo ...
, X may represent the set of candidates; in a resource allocation setting, X may represent all possible allocations of the resource. Let I be a finite set, representing a collection of individuals. For each i \in I, let u_i:X\longrightarrow\mathbb be a '' utility function'', describing the amount of happiness an individual ''i'' derives from each possible state. A '' social choice rule'' is a mechanism which uses the data (u_i)_ to select some element(s) from X which are `best' for society (the question of what 'best' means is the basic problem of social choice theory). The utilitarian rule selects an element x \in X which maximizes the ''utilitarian sum'' : U(x):= \sum_ u_i(x).


Tangible utility functions

The utilitarian rule is easy to interpret and implement when the functions ''ui'' represent some tangible, measurable form of utility. For example: * Consider a problem of allocating wood among builders. The utility functions may represent their productive power – u_i(y_i) is the number of buildings that agent i can build using y_i units of wood. The utilitarian rule then allocates the wood in a way that maximizes the number of buildings. * Consider a problem of allocating a rare medication among patient. The utility functions may represent their chance of recovery – u_i(y_i) is the probability of agent i to recover by getting y_i doses of the medication. The utilitarian rule then allocates the medication in a way that maximizes the expected number of survivors.


Abstract utility functions

When the functions ''ui'' represent some abstract form of "happiness", the utilitarian rule becomes harder to interpret. For the above formula to make sense, it must be assumed that the utility functions (u_i)_ are both
cardinal Cardinal or The Cardinal may refer to: Animals * Cardinal (bird) or Cardinalidae, a family of North and South American birds **''Cardinalis'', genus of cardinal in the family Cardinalidae **''Cardinalis cardinalis'', or northern cardinal, the ...
and interpersonally comparable at a cardinal level. The notion that individuals have cardinal utility functions is not that problematic. Cardinal utility has been implicitly assumed in decision theory ever since
Daniel Bernoulli Daniel Bernoulli FRS (; – 27 March 1782) was a Swiss mathematician and physicist and was one of the many prominent mathematicians in the Bernoulli family from Basel. He is particularly remembered for his applications of mathematics to mechan ...
's analysis of the
Saint Petersburg Paradox The St. Petersburg paradox or St. Petersburg lottery is a paradox involving the game of flipping a coin where the expected payoff of the theoretical lottery game approaches infinity but nevertheless seems to be worth only a very small amount to ...
. Rigorous mathematical theories of cardinal utility (with application to risky decision making) were developed by Frank P. Ramsey, Bruno de Finetti, von Neumann and Morgenstern, and Leonard Savage. However, in these theories, a person's utility function is only well-defined up to an `affine rescaling'. Thus, if the utility function u_i:X\longrightarrow \mathbb is valid description of her preferences, and if r_i,s_i\in \mathbb are two constants with s_i>0, then the `rescaled' utility function v_i(x) := s_i\, u_i(x) + r_i is an equally valid description of her preferences. If we define a new package of utility functions (v_i)_ using possibly different r_i\in \mathbb and s_i>0 for all i \in I, and we then consider the utilitarian sum : V(x):= \sum_ v_i(x), then in general, the maximizer of V will ''not'' be the same as the maximizer of U. Thus, in a sense, classic utilitarian social choice is not well-defined within the standard model of cardinal utility used in decision theory, unless a mechanism is specified to `calibrate' the utility functions of the different individuals.


Relative utilitarianism

''Relative utilitarianism'' proposes a natural calibration mechanism. For every i \in I , suppose that the values : m_i \ := \ \min_ \, u_i(x) \quad \text\quad M_i \ := \ \max_ \, u_i(x) are well-defined. (For example, this will always be true if X is finite, or if X is a compact space and u_i is a continuous function.) Then define : w_i(x) \ := \ \frac for all x\in X. Thus, w_i:X \longrightarrow \mathbb is a `rescaled' utility function which has a minimum value of 0 and a maximum value of 1. The Relative Utilitarian social choice rule selects the element in X which maximizes the utilitarian sum : W(x):= \sum_ w_i(x). As an abstract social choice function, relative utilitarianism has been analyzed by Cao (1982), Dhillon (1998), Karni (1998), Dhillon and Mertens (1999), Segal (2000), Sobel (2001) and Pivato (2008). (Cao (1982) refers to it as the `modified Thomson solution'.)


The utilitarian rule and Pareto-efficiency

Every Pareto efficient choice is necessarily utilitarian. This is because every Pareto improvement necessarily increases the sum of utilities. But the utilitarian choice is not the only Pareto-efficient one. In fact, every ''weighted'' utilitarian choice (maximizing a weighted sum of utilities) is Pareto-optimal, whenever the weights of all individuals are positive.


The utilitarian rule in specific contexts

In the context of voting, the utilitarian rule leads to several voting methods: *
Range voting Score voting or range voting is an electoral system for single-seat elections, in which voters give each candidate a score, the scores are added (or averaged), and the candidate with the highest total is elected. It has been described by various ...
(also called score voting or utilitarian voting) implements the relative-utilitarian rule by letting voters explicitly express their utilities to each alternative on a common normalized scale. *
Implicit utilitarian voting Implicit utilitarian voting (IUV) is a voting system in which the agents express their preferences by ranking the alternatives (like in ranked voting), and the system tries to select an alternative which maximizes the sum of utilities, as in the ut ...
tries to approximate the utilitarian rule while letting the voters express only ordinal rankings over candidates. *A related voting rule is Nanson's method. In the context of resource allocation, the utilitarian rule leads to: * A particular rule for division of a single homogeneous resource; * Several rules and algorithms for utilitarian cake-cutting – dividing a heterogeneous resource; *A particular rule for fair item allocation.


See also

* Egalitarian rule – a different rule, that emphasizes the welfare of the worst-off individual rather than the sum of utilities. * Proportional-fair rule – a rule that tries to balance the efficiency of the utilitarian rule and the fairness of the egalitarian rule. * Utility maximization problem – a problem solved by an individual consumer (rather than by society).


References

{{Reflist * Voting theory Utilitarianism Mathematical optimization de:Sozialwahltheorie it:Teoria della scelta sociale ja:社会選択理論 pt:Teoria da escolha social