HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
probability theory Probability theory is the branch of mathematics concerned with probability. Although there are several different probability interpretations, probability theory treats the concept in a rigorous mathematical manner by expressing it through a set ...
and
statistics Statistics (from German: '' Statistik'', "description of a state, a country") is the discipline that concerns the collection, organization, analysis, interpretation, and presentation of data. In applying statistics to a scientific, indust ...
, a stochastic order quantifies the concept of one
random variable A random variable (also called random quantity, aleatory variable, or stochastic variable) is a mathematical formalization of a quantity or object which depends on random events. It is a mapping or a function from possible outcomes (e.g., the po ...
being "bigger" than another. These are usually
partial order In mathematics, especially order theory, a partially ordered set (also poset) formalizes and generalizes the intuitive concept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set. A poset consists of a set together with a binary ...
s, so that one random variable A may be neither stochastically greater than, less than nor equal to another random variable B. Many different orders exist, which have different applications.


Usual stochastic order

A real random variable A is less than a random variable B in the "usual stochastic order" if :\Pr(A>x) \le \Pr(B>x)\textx \in (-\infty,\infty), where \Pr(\cdot) denotes the probability of an event. This is sometimes denoted A \preceq B or A \le_ B. If additionally \Pr(A>x) < \Pr(B>x) for some x, then A is stochastically strictly less than B, sometimes denoted A \prec B. In decision theory, under this circumstance ''B'' is said to be first-order stochastically dominant over ''A''.


Characterizations

The following rules describe situations when one random variable is stochastically less than or equal to another. Strict version of some of these rules also exist. #A\preceq B if and only if for all non-decreasing functions u, (A)\le (B)/math>. #If u is non-decreasing and A\preceq B then u(A) \preceq u(B) #If u:\mathbb^n\to\mathbb is increasing in each variable and A_i and B_i are independent sets of random variables with A_i \preceq B_i for each i, then u(A_1,\dots,A_n) \preceq u(B_1,\dots,B_n) and in particular \sum_^n A_i \preceq \sum_^n B_i Moreover, the ith order statistics satisfy A_ \preceq B_. #If two sequences of random variables A_i and B_i, with A_i \preceq B_i for all i each converge in distribution, then their limits satisfy A \preceq B. #If A, B and C are random variables such that \sum_c\Pr(C=c)=1 and \Pr(A>u, C=c)\le \Pr(B>u, C=c) for all u and c such that \Pr(C=c)>0, then A\preceq B.


Other properties

If A\preceq B and /math> then A \mathrel B (the random variables are equal in distribution).


Stochastic dominance

Stochastic dominance Stochastic dominance is a partial order between random variables. It is a form of stochastic ordering In probability theory and statistics, a stochastic order quantifies the concept of one random variable being "bigger" than another. These are us ...
relations are a family of stochastic orderings used in decision theory: * Zeroth-order stochastic dominance: A \prec_ B if and only if A \le B for all realizations of these random variables and A < B for at least one realization. * First-order stochastic dominance: A \prec_ B if and only if \Pr(A>x) \le \Pr(B>x) for all x and there exists x such that \Pr(A>x) < \Pr(B>x). * Second-order stochastic dominance: A \prec_ B if and only if \int_^x Pr(B>t) - \Pr(A>t)\, dt \geq 0 for all x, with strict inequality at some x. There also exist higher-order notions of stochastic dominance. With the definitions above, we have A \prec_ B \implies A \prec_ B.


Multivariate stochastic order

An \mathbb R^d-valued random variable A is less than an \mathbb R^d-valued random variable B in the "usual stochastic order" if : (A)\le (B)text f\colon\mathbb R^d\longrightarrow\mathbb R Other types of multivariate stochastic orders exist. For instance the upper and lower orthant order which are similar to the usual one-dimensional stochastic order. A is said to be smaller than B in upper orthant order if :\Pr(A>\mathbf x) \le \Pr(B>\mathbf x)\text \mathbf x \in \mathbb R^d and A is smaller than B in lower orthant order if :\Pr(A\le\mathbf x) \le \Pr(B\le\mathbf x)\text \mathbf x \in \mathbb R^d All three order types also have integral representations, that is for a particular order A is smaller than B if and only if (A)\le (B) for all f\colon\mathbb R^d\longrightarrow \mathbb R in a class of functions \mathcal G. \mathcal G is then called generator of the respective order.


Other dominance orders

The following stochastic orders are useful in the theory of
random social choice Fractional social choice is a branch of social choice theory in which the collective decision is not a single alternative, but rather a weighted sum of two or more alternatives. For example, if society has to choose between three candidates: A B or ...
. They are used to compare the outcomes of random social choice functions, in order to check them for efficiency or other desirable criteria. The dominance orders below are ordered from the most conservative to the least conservative. They are exemplified on random variables over the finite support . Deterministic dominance, denoted A\succeq_ B, means that every possible outcome of A is at least as good as every possible outcome of B: for all ''x''<''y'', \Pr =xcdot \Pr =y= 0. In other words: \Pr \geq B= 1. For example, 0.6 * 30 + 0.4 * 20 \succeq_ 0.5 * 20 + 0.5 * 10. Bilinear dominance, denoted A\succeq_ B, means that, for every possible outcome, the probability that A yields the better one and B yields the worse one is at least as large as the probability the other way around: for all x\Pr =xcdot \Pr =y\leq \Pr =ycdot \Pr =x/math> For example, 0.5 * 30 + 0.5 * 20 \succeq_ 0.33 * 30 + 0.33 * 20 + 0.34 * 10. Stochastic dominance (already mentioned above), denoted A\succeq_ B, means that, for every possible outcome ''x'', the probability that A yields at least ''x'' is at least as large as the probability that B yields at least ''x'': for all x, \Pr \geq xgeq \Pr \geq x/math>. For example, 0.5 * 30 + 0.5 * 10 \succeq_ 0.5 * 20 + 0.5*10. Pairwise-comparison dominance, denoted A\succeq_ B, means that the probability that that A yields a better outcome than B is larger than the other way around: \Pr \geq Bgeq\Pr \geq A/math>. For example, 0.67 * 30 + 0.33 * 10 \succeq_ 1.0 * 20. Downward-lexicographic dominance, denoted A\succeq_ B, means that A has a larger probability than B of returning the best outcome, or both A and B have the same probability to return the best outcome but A has a larger probability than B of returning the second-best best outcome, etc. Upward-lexicographic dominance is defined analogously based on the probability to return the ''worst'' outcomes. See
lexicographic dominance Lexicographic dominance is a total order between random variables. It is a form of stochastic ordering. It is defined as follows. Random variable A has lexicographic dominance over random variable B (denoted A \succ_ B) if one of the following hold ...
.


Other stochastic orders


Hazard rate order

The ''
hazard rate Survival analysis is a branch of statistics for analyzing the expected duration of time until one event occurs, such as death in biological organisms and failure in mechanical systems. This topic is called reliability theory or reliability analys ...
'' of a non-negative random variable X with absolutely continuous distribution function F and density function f is defined as :r(t) = \frac(-\log(1-F(t))) = \frac. Given two non-negative variables X and Y with absolutely continuous distribution F and G, and with hazard rate functions r and q, respectively, X is said to be smaller than Y in the hazard rate order (denoted as X \preceq_Y) if :r(t)\ge q(t) for all t\ge 0, or equivalently if :\frac is decreasing in t.


Likelihood ratio order

Let X and Y two continuous (or discrete) random variables with densities (or discrete densities) f \left( t \right) and g \left( t \right), respectively, so that \frac increases in t over the union of the supports of X and Y; in this case, X is smaller than Y in the ''likelihood ratio order'' (X \preceq _ Y).


Variability orders

If two variables have the same mean, they can still be compared by how "spread out" their distributions are. This is captured to a limited extent by the
variance In probability theory and statistics, variance is the expectation of the squared deviation of a random variable from its population mean or sample mean. Variance is a measure of dispersion, meaning it is a measure of how far a set of numbe ...
, but more fully by a range of stochastic orders.


Convex order

Convex order is a special kind of variability order. Under the convex ordering, A is less than B if and only if for all convex u, (A)\leq (B)/math>.


Laplace transform order

Laplace transform order compares both size and variability of two random variables. Similar to convex order, Laplace transform order is established by comparing the expectation of a function of the random variable where the function is from a special class: u(x) = -\exp(-\alpha x). This makes the Laplace transform order an integral stochastic order with the generator set given by the function set defined above with \alpha a positive real number.


Realizable monotonicity

Considering a family of probability distributions (_)_ on partially ordered space (E,\preceq) indexed with \alpha \in F (where (F,\preceq) is another partially ordered space, the concept of complete or realizable monotonicity may be defined. It means, there exists a family of random variables (X_\alpha)_ on the same probability space, such that the distribution of X_\alpha is _\alpha and X_\alpha \preceq X_\beta almost surely whenever \alpha \preceq \beta . It means the existence of a monotone coupling. SeeStochastic Monotonicity and Realizable Monotonicity James Allen Fill and Motoya Machida, The Annals of Probability, Vol. 29, No. 2 (Apr., 2001), pp. 938-978, Published by: Institute of Mathematical Statistics, Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2691998


See also

*
Stochastic dominance Stochastic dominance is a partial order between random variables. It is a form of stochastic ordering In probability theory and statistics, a stochastic order quantifies the concept of one random variable being "bigger" than another. These are us ...
*
Stochastic Stochastic (, ) refers to the property of being well described by a random probability distribution. Although stochasticity and randomness are distinct in that the former refers to a modeling approach and the latter refers to phenomena themselv ...
- meaning of the term


References


Bibliography

* M. Shaked and J. G. Shanthikumar, ''Stochastic Orders and their Applications'', Associated Press, 1994. * E. L. Lehmann. Ordered families of distributions. ''The Annals of Mathematical Statistics'', 26:399–419, 1955. {{DEFAULTSORT:Stochastic Ordering *