Super-proportional Division
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

A strongly-proportional division (sometimes called super-proportional division) is a kind of a
fair division Fair division is the problem in game theory of dividing a set of resources among several people who have an entitlement to them so that each person receives their due share. That problem arises in various real-world settings such as division of inh ...
. It is a division of resources among ''n'' partners, in which the value received by each partner is strictly more than his/her due share of 1/''n'' of the total value. Formally, in a strongly-proportional division of a resource ''C'' among ''n'' partners, each partner ''i'', with value measure ''Vi'', receives a share ''Xi'' such that
V_i(X_i) > V_i(C)/n.
Obviously, a strongly-proportional division does not exist when all partners have the same value measure. The best condition that can ''always'' be guaranteed is V_i(X_i) \geq V_i(C)/n, which is the condition for a plain
proportional division A proportional division is a kind of fair division in which a resource is divided among ''n'' partners with subjective valuations, giving each partner at least 1/''n'' of the resource by his/her own subjective valuation. Proportionality was the f ...
. However, one may hope that, when different agents have different valuations, it may be possible to use this fact for the benefit of all players, and give each of them strictly more than their due share.


Existence

In 1948,
Hugo Steinhaus Hugo Dyonizy Steinhaus ( ; ; January 14, 1887 – February 25, 1972) was a Polish mathematician and educator. Steinhaus obtained his PhD under David Hilbert at Göttingen University in 1911 and later became a professor at the Jan Kazimierz Unive ...
conjectured the existence of a super-proportional division of a cake:
It may be stated incidentally that if there are two (or more) partners with ''different'' estimations, there exists a division giving to everybody more than his due part ( Knaster); this fact disproves the common opinion that differences estimations make fair division difficult.
In 1961, Dubins and Spanier proved that the necessary condition for existence is also sufficient. That is, whenever the partners' valuations are additive and non-atomic, and there are at least ''two'' partners whose value function is even slightly different, then there is a super-proportional division in which ''all'' partners receive more than 1/''n''. The proof was a corollary to the Dubins–Spanier convexity theorem. This was a purely existential proof based on convexity arguments.


Algorithms

In 1986, Douglas R. Woodall published the first protocol for finding a super-proportional division. Let ''C'' be the entire cake. If the agents' valuations are different, then there must be a ''witness'' for that: a witness is a specific piece of cake, say ''X ⊆ C'', which is valued differently by some two partners, say Alice and Bob. Let ''Y'' := ''C \ X.'' Let ''ax=VAlice(X)'' and ''bx=VBob(X)'' and ''ay=VAlice(Y)'' and ''by=VBob(Y)'', and assume w.l.o.g. that:
''bx > ax'', which implies: by < ay.
The idea is to partition ''X'' and ''Y'' separately: when partitioning ''X'', we will give slightly more to Bob and slightly less to Alice; when partitioning ''Y'', we will give slightly more to Alice and slightly less to Bob.


Woodall's protocol for two agents

Find a rational number between ''b''x and ''ax'', say ''p/q'' such that ''bx > p/q > ax''. This implies ''by < (q-p)/q < ay''. Ask Bob to divide ''X'' into ''p'' equal parts, and divide ''Y'' to ''q-p'' equal parts. By our assumptions, Bob values each piece of ''X'' at bx/p > 1/''q'', and each piece of ''Y'' at by/(q-p) < 1/''q''. But for Alice, at least one piece of ''X'' (say X0) must have value less than 1/''q'' and at least one piece of ''Y'' (say Y0) must have value more than 1/''q''. So now we have two pieces, ''X0'' and ''Y0'', such that: :''VBob(X0)>VAlice(X0)'' :''VBob(Y0)Alice(Y0)'' Let Alice and Bob divide the remainder ''C \ X0 \ Y0'' between them in a proportional manner (e.g. using
divide and choose Divide and choose (also Cut and choose or I cut, you choose) is a procedure for fair division of a continuous resource, such as a cake, between two parties. It involves a heterogeneous good or resource ("the cake") and two partners who have differe ...
). Add ''Y0'' to the piece of Alice and add ''X0'' to the piece of Bob. Now, each partner thinks that his/her allocation is strictly better than the other allocation, so its value is strictly more than 1/2.


Woodall's protocol for ''n'' partners

The extension of this protocol to ''n'' partners is based on Fink's "Lone Chooser" protocol. Suppose we already have a strongly-proportional division to ''i''-1 partners (for ''i≥3''). Now partner #''i'' enters the party and we should give him a small piece from each of the first ''i''-1 partners, such that the new division is still strongly-proportional. Consider e.g. partner #1. Let ''d'' be the difference between partner #1's current value and (1/(''i''-1)). Because the current division is strongly-proportional, we know that ''d>0''. Choose a positive integer ''q'' such that: d > \frac Ask partner #1 to divide his share to qi-1 pieces which he considers of equal value and let the new partner choose the q pieces which he considers to be the most valuable. Partner #1 remains with a value of \frac = \frac of his previous value, which was \frac + d (by definition of ''d''). The first element becomes \frac and the ''d'' becomes \frac; summing them up gives that the new value is more than: \frac = \frac of the entire cake. As for the new partner, after having taken ''q'' pieces from each of the first ''i''-1 partners, his total value is at least: \frac > \frac of the entire cake. This proves that the new division is strongly-proportional too.


Barbanel's protocol

Julius Barbanel extended Woodall's algorithm to agents with different entitlements, including irrational entitlements. In this setting, the entitlement of each agent ''i'' is represented by a weight w_i, with W := \sum_i w_i. A strongly-proportional allocation is one in which, for each agent ''i'':
V_i(X_i) > w_i\cdot V_i(C)/ W.


Janko-Joo protocol

Janko and Joo presented a simpler algorithm for agents with different entitlements. In fact, they showed how to reduce a problem of strongly-proportional division (with equal or different entitlements) into two problems of proportional division with different entitlements: * For the piece ''X'', change the entitlement of Alice to w_A - 1/a_x and the entitlement of Bob to w_B + 1/b_x. Since ''bx > ax'', the sum of the new entitlements is strictly less than w_A + w_B, so the sum of all ''n'' entitlements (dentoed by ''WX'') is strictly less than ''W.'' * For the piece ''Y'', change the entitlement of Alice to w_A + 1/a_y and the entitlement of Bob to w_B - 1/b_y. Here, too, since ''by < ay'', the new sum of all entitlements (dentoed by ''WY'') is strictly less than ''W''. * Alice's value is at least \begin & (w_A - 1/a_x)\cdot a_x / W_X + (w_A + 1/b_y)\cdot b_x / W_Y = \\ =& (w_A a_x - 1) / W_X + (w_A a_y + 1) / W_Y \\ >& (w_A a_x - 1) / W + (w_A a_y + 1) / W \\ =& w_A V_A(C) / W \end * Similarly, Bob's value is at least\begin & (w_B + 1/b_x)\cdot b_x / W_X + (w_B - 1/b_y)\cdot b_y / W_Y = \\ =& (w_B b_x + 1) / W_X + (w_B b_y - 1) / W_Y \\ >& (w_B b_x - 1) / W + (w_B b_y + 1) / W \\ =& w_B V_B(C) / W \end * The value of every other agent ''i'' is at least\begin & w_i \cdot V_i(X) / W_X + w_i \cdot V_i(Y) / W_Y \\ >& w_i \cdot V_i(X) / W + w_i \cdot V_i(Y) / W \\ =& w_i V_i(C) / W \end So the division is strongly-proportional.


Related concepts

An allocation is called strongly envy-free if for every two partners ''i'',''j'':
V_i(X_i) > V_i(X_j).
An allocation is called super envy-free if for every two partners ''i'',''j'':
V_i(X_i) > 1/n > V_i(X_j).
Super envy-freeness implies strong envy-freeness, which implies strong proportionality.


References

{{reflist Fair division protocols Cake-cutting