SD-efficiency
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Ordinal Pareto efficiency refers to several adaptations of the concept of
Pareto-efficiency Pareto efficiency or Pareto optimality is a situation where no action or allocation is available that makes one individual better off without making another worse off. The concept is named after Vilfredo Pareto (1848–1923), Italian civil engin ...
to settings in which the agents only express
ordinal utilities In economics, an ordinal utility function is a function representing the preferences of an agent on an ordinal scale. Ordinal utility theory claims that it is only meaningful to ask which option is better than the other, but it is meaningless to ask ...
over items, but not over bundles. That is, agents rank the items from best to worst, but they do not rank the subsets of items. In particular, they do not specify a numeric value for each item. This may cause an ambiguity regarding whether certain allocations are Pareto-efficient or not. As an example, consider an economy with three items and two agents, with the following rankings: * Alice: x > y > z. * George: x > z > y. Consider the allocation lice: x, George: y,z Whether or not this allocation is Pareto-efficient depends on the agents' numeric valuations. For example: * It is possible that Alice prefers to and George prefers to (for example: Alice's valuations for x,y,z are 8,7,6 and George's valuations are 7,1,2, so the utility profile is 8,3). Then the allocation is not Pareto-efficient, since both Alice and George would be better-off by exchanging their bundles (the utility profile would be 13,7). * In contrast, it is possible that Alice prefers to and George prefers to (for example: Alice's valuations are 12,4,2 and George's valuations are 6,3,4). Then the allocation is Pareto-efficient: in any other allocation, if Alice still gets x, then George's utility is lower; if Alice does not get x, then Alice's utility is lower. Moreover, the allocation is Pareto-efficient even if the items are divisible (that is, it is fractionally Pareto efficient): if Alice yields any amount ''r'' of x to George, then George would have to give her at least 3''r'' of y or 6''r'' of z in order to keep her utility at the same level. But then George's utility would change by 6''r''-9''r'' or 6''r''-24''r'', which is negative. Since the Pareto-efficiency of an allocation depends on the rankings of bundles, it is a-priori not clear how to determine the efficiency of an allocation when only rankings of items are given.


Definitions

An allocation X = (X1,...,Xn) Pareto-dominates another allocation Y = (Y1,...,Yn), if every agent ''i'' weakly prefers the bundle Xi to the bundle Yi, and at least one agent ''j'' strictly prefers Xj to Yj. An allocation X is Pareto-efficient if no other allocation Pareto-dominates it. Sometimes, a distinction is made between discrete-Pareto-efficiency, which means that an allocation is not dominated by a discrete allocation, and the stronger concept of Fractional Pareto efficiency, which means that an allocation is not dominated even by a fractional allocation. The above definitions depend on the agents' ranking of ''bundles'' (sets of items). In our setting, agents report only their rankings of ''items''. A bundle ranking is called consistent with an item ranking if it ranks the singleton bundles in the same order as the items they contain. For example, if Alice's ranking is , then any consistent bundle ranking must have < < < {z]. Often, one makes additional assumptions on the set of allowed bundle rankings, which imposes additional restrictions on consistency. Example assumptions are: * Monotonicity: adding an item to a bundle always improves the bundle. This corresponds to the assumption that all items are Goods, good. Thus, Alice's bundle ranking must have e.g. {y} < {y,x}. * Responsivity: replacing an item with a better item always improves the bundle. Thus, Alice's bundle ranking must have e.g. {w,x} < {w,y} < {x,y} < {x,z}. This is stronger than consistency. *
Additivity Additive may refer to: Mathematics * Additive function, a function in number theory * Additive map, a function that preserves the addition operation * Additive set-functionn see Sigma additivity * Additive category, a preadditive category with fi ...
: the agent assigns a value to each item, and values each bundle at the sum of its contents. This assumption is stronger than responsivity. For example, if Alice ranks {x,y}<{z} then she must rank {w,x,y}<{w,z}. * Lexicographic:the agent always ranks a bundle that contains some item x above any bundle that contains only items ranked lower than x. In the above example, Alice must rank {w,x,y} < {z}.


Necessary Pareto-efficiency

Brams, Edelman and
Fishburn Fishburn is a village and civil parish in County Durham, in England. It is situated about 12 miles west of Hartlepool. It had a population of 2,454, increasing to 2,588 at the 2011 Census. Location The village lies scattered along a dry swell ...
call an allocation Pareto-ensuring if it is Pareto-efficient for ''all'' bundle rankings that are consistent with the agents' item rankings (they allow all ''monotonic'' and ''responsive'' bundle rankings). For example: * If agents' valuations are assumed to be positive, then every allocation giving all items to a single agent is Pareto-ensuring. * If Alice's ranking is x>y and George's ranking is y>x, then the allocation lice:x, George:yis Pareto-ensuring. * If Alice's ranking is x>y>z and George's ranking is x>z>y and the allocations must be discrete, then the allocation lice: x,y; George: zis Pareto-ensuring. * With the above rankings, the allocation lice: x, George: y,zis not Pareto-ensuring. As explained in the introduction, it is not Pareto-efficient e.g. when Alice's valuations for x,y,z are 8,7,6 and George's valuations are 7,1,2. Note that both these valuations are consistent with the agents' rankings. Bouveret, Endriss and Lang. use an equivalent definition. They say that an allocation X possibly Pareto-dominates an allocation Y if there exists some bundle rankings consistent with the agents' item rankings, for which X Pareto-dominates Y. An allocation is called Necessarily-Pareto-efficient (NecPE) if no other allocation possibly-Pareto-dominates it. The two definitions are logically equivalent: * "X is Pareto-ensuring" is equivalent to "For every consistent bundle ranking, for every other allocation Y, Y does not Pareto-dominate X". * "X is NecPE" is equivalent to "For every other allocation Y, for every consistent bundle ranking, Y does not Pareto-dominate X". Exchanging the order of "for all" quantifiers does not change the logical meaning. The NecPE condition remains the same whether we allow ''all'' additive bundle rankings, or we allow only rankings that are based on additive valuations with diminishing differences.


Existence

NecPE is a very strong requirement, which often cannot be satisfied. For example, suppose two agents have the same item ranking. One of them, say Alice, necessarily receives the lowest-ranked item. There are consistent additive bundle-rankings in which Alices values this item at 0 while George values it at 1. Hence, giving it to Alice is not Pareto-efficient. If we require that all items have a strictly positive value, then giving all items to a single agent is trivially NecPE, but it very unfair. If fractional allocations are allowed, then there may be no NecPE allocation which gives both agents a positive value. For example, suppose Alice and George both have the ranking x>y. If both get a positive value, then either Alice gets some x and George gets some y, or vice-versa. In the former case, it is possible that Alice's valuations are e.g. 4,2 and George's valuations are 8,1, so Alice can exchange a small amount ''r'' of x for a small amount 3''r'' of y. Alice gains 6''r''-4''r'' and George gains 8''r''-3''r'', so both gains are positive. In the latter case, an analogous argument holds.


Possible Pareto-efficiency

Brams, Edelman and Fishburn call an allocation Pareto-possible if it is Pareto-efficient for ''some'' bundle rankings that are consistent with the agents' item rankings. Obviously, every Pareto-ensuring allocation is Pareto-possible. In addition: * If Alice's ranking is x>y>z and George's ranking is x>z>y, then the allocation lice: x, George: y,zis Pareto-possible. As explained in the introduction, it is Pareto-efficient e.g. when Alice's valuations for x,y,z are 12,4,2 and George's valuations are 6,3,4. Note that both these valuations are consistent with the agents' rankings. * If Alice's ranking is x>y and George's ranking is y>x, then the allocation lice:y, George:xis not Pareto-possible, since it is always Pareto-dominated by the allocation lice:x, George:y Bouveret, Endriss and Lang. use a different definition. They say that an allocation X necessarily Pareto-dominates an allocation Y if for ''all'' bundle rankings consistent with the agents' item rankings, X Pareto-dominates Y. An allocation is called Possibly-Pareto-efficient (PosPE) if no other allocation necessarily-Pareto-dominates it. The two definitions are ''not'' logically equivalent: * "X is Pareto-possible" is equivalent to "There exist a consistent bundle ranking for which, for every other allocation Y, Y does not dominate X". It must be ''the same'' bundle ranking for all other allocations Y. * "X is PosPE" is equivalent to "For every other allocation Y, there exists a consistent bundle ranking, for which Y does not dominate X". There can be ''a different'' bundle ranking for every other allocation Y. If X is Pareto-possible then it is PosPE, but the other implication is not (logically) true. The Pareto-possible condition remains the same whether we allow ''all'' additive bundle rankings, or we allow only rankings that are based on additive valuations with ''diminishing differences''.


Stochastic-dominance Pareto-efficiency

Bogomolnaia and Moulin present an efficiency notion for the setting of
fair random assignment Fair random assignment (also called probabilistic one-sided matching) is a kind of a fair division problem. In an ''assignment problem'' (also called '' house-allocation problem'' or '' one-sided matching''), there ''m'' objects and they have to be ...
(where the bundle rankings are ''additive'', the allocations are ''fractional'', and the sum of fractions given to each agent must be ''at most 1''). It is based on the notion of
stochastic dominance Stochastic dominance is a partial order between random variables. It is a form of stochastic ordering. The concept arises in decision theory and decision analysis in situations where one gamble (a probability distribution over possible outcomes, ...
. For each agent ''i'', A bundle ''Xi'' weakly-stochastically dominates (wsd) a bundle ''Yi'' if for every item z, the total fraction of items better than ''z'' in ''Xi'' is at least as large as in ''Yi'' (if the allocations are discrete, then Xi sd Yi means that for every item z, the number of items better than ''z'' in ''Xi'' is at least as large as in ''Yi''). The sd relation has several equivalent definitions; see
responsive set extension In utility theory, the responsive set (RS) extension is an extension of a preference-relation on individual items, to a partial preference-relation of item-bundles. Example Suppose there are four items: w,x,y,z. A person states that he ranks the ...
. In particular, Xi sd Yi if-and-only-if, for every bundle ranking consistent with the item ranking, Xi is at least as good as Yi. A bundle ''Xi'' strictly-stochastically dominates (ssd) a bundle ''Yi'' if Xi wsd Yi and Xi ≠ Yi. Equivalently, for at least one item z, the "at least as large as in Yi" becomes "strictly larger than in Yi". In the ssd relation is written as ''"Xi'' ''>> Yi".'' An allocation X = (X1,...,Xn) stochastically dominates another allocation Y = (Y1,...,Yn), if for every agent ''i'': Xi wsd Yi, and Y≠X (equivalently: for at least one agent i, Xi ssd Yi). In the stochastic domination relation between allocations is also written as ''"X'' ''>> Y".'' This is equivalent to necessary Pareto-domination. An allocation is called sd-efficient (also called: ordinally efficient or O-efficient) if there no allocation that stochastically dominates it. This is similar to PosPE, but emphasizes that the bundle rankings must be based on ''additive'' utility functions, and the allocations may be ''fractional''.


Equivalences

As noted above, Pareto-possible implies PosPE, but the other direction is not logically true. McLennan proves that they are equivalent in the
fair random assignment Fair random assignment (also called probabilistic one-sided matching) is a kind of a fair division problem. In an ''assignment problem'' (also called '' house-allocation problem'' or '' one-sided matching''), there ''m'' objects and they have to be ...
problem (with strict or weak item rankings). Particularly, he proves that the following are equivalent: * (a) X is sd-efficient (that is, X is PosPE); * (b) there exists additive bundle-rankings consistent with the agents' item-rankings for which X is fractionally-Pareto-efficient (that is, X is Pareto-possible); * (c) there exists additive bundle-rankings consistent with the agents' item-rankings for which X maximizes the sum of agents' utilities. The implications (c) → (b) → (a) are easy; the challenging part is to prove that (a) → (c). McLennan proves it using the polyhedral
separating hyperplane theorem In geometry, the hyperplane separation theorem is a theorem about disjoint convex sets in ''n''-dimensional Euclidean space. There are several rather similar versions. In one version of the theorem, if both these sets are closed and at least on ...
. Bogomolnaia and Moulin prove another useful characterization of sd-efficiency, for the same
fair random assignment Fair random assignment (also called probabilistic one-sided matching) is a kind of a fair division problem. In an ''assignment problem'' (also called '' house-allocation problem'' or '' one-sided matching''), there ''m'' objects and they have to be ...
setting but with strict item rankings. Define the exchange graph of a given fractional allocation as a
directed graph In mathematics, and more specifically in graph theory, a directed graph (or digraph) is a graph that is made up of a set of vertices connected by directed edges, often called arcs. Definition In formal terms, a directed graph is an ordered pa ...
in which the nodes are the items, and there is an arc x→y iff there exists an agent ''i'' that prefers x and receives a positive fraction of y. Define an allocation as acyclic if its exchange graph has no directed cycles. Then, an allocation sd-efficient iff it is acyclic.
Fishburn Fishburn is a village and civil parish in County Durham, in England. It is situated about 12 miles west of Hartlepool. It had a population of 2,454, increasing to 2,588 at the 2011 Census. Location The village lies scattered along a dry swell ...
proved the following equivalence on dominance relations of ''discrete'' bundles, with ''responsive'' bundle rankings: * If ''Xi'' ''>> Yi'' (that is: ''Xi'' ≠ ''Yi'' , and for every item z, ''Xi'' has at least as many items that are at least as good as z), then for every responsive bundle-ranking consistent with the item-ranking, ''Xi'' ''>Yi .'' * If ''not Xi'' ''>> Yi ,'' then there exists at least one responsive bundle-ranking consistent with the item-ranking, for which ''Xi'' ''i .'' Therefore, the following holds for dominance relations of discrete allocations: ''X'' ''>> Y'' iff ''X'' necessarily Pareto-dominates ''Y''.


Properties

If ''Xi'' wsd ''Yi'', then '', Xi'', ≥ '', Yi, '', that is, the total quantity of objects (discrete or fractional) in ''Xi'' must be at least as large as in ''Yi''. This is because, if '', Xi'', < '', Yi, '', then for the valuation which assigns almost the same value for all items, v(''Xi'') < v(''Yi''). This means that, if X wsd Y and both X and Y are complete allocations (all objects are allocated), then necessarily '', Xi'', = '', Yi, '' for all agents ''i''. In other words, a complete allocation X can be necessarily-dominated only by an allocation Y which assigns to every agent the same amount as X does. This means that, in particular, if X is sd-efficient in the set of all allocations that give exactly 1 unit to each agent, then X is sd-efficient in general.


Lexicographic-dominance Pareto-efficiency

Cho presents two other efficiency notions for the setting of
fair random assignment Fair random assignment (also called probabilistic one-sided matching) is a kind of a fair division problem. In an ''assignment problem'' (also called '' house-allocation problem'' or '' one-sided matching''), there ''m'' objects and they have to be ...
, based on
lexicographic dominance Lexicographic dominance is a total order between random variables. It is a form of stochastic ordering. It is defined as follows. Random variable A has lexicographic dominance over random variable B (denoted A \succ_ B) if one of the following hol ...
. An allocation X = (X1,...,Xn) downward-lexicographically (dl) dominates another allocation Y = (Y1,...,Yn), if for every agent ''i,'' Xi weakly-dl-dominates Yi, and for at least one agent ''j'', Xj strictly-dl-dominates Yj. An allocation is called dl-efficient if there is no other allocation that dl-dominates it. Similarly, based on the notion of upward-lexicographic (ul) domination, An allocation is called ul-efficient if there is no other allocation that ul-dominates it. In general, sd-domination implies dl-domination and ul-domination. Therefore, dl-efficiency and ul-efficiency imply sd-efficiency.


Equivalences

Consider the
fair random assignment Fair random assignment (also called probabilistic one-sided matching) is a kind of a fair division problem. In an ''assignment problem'' (also called '' house-allocation problem'' or '' one-sided matching''), there ''m'' objects and they have to be ...
setting (the bundle rankings are ''additive'', the allocations may be ''fractional'', and the total fraction given to each agent must be 1), with strict item rankings, where there can be more items than agents (so some items may remain unallocated). Cho and Dogan prove that, in this particular case, dl-efficiency and ul-efficiency are equivalent to sd-efficiency. In particular, they prove that if an allocation X is sd/ld/ul efficient, then: * The exchange graph of X is acyclic, and - * X is non-wasteful ("wasteful" means that some agent ''i'', who receives a positive fraction of an item ''x'', prefers another item ''y'' which is not entirely allocated). The equivalence does not hold if there are distributional constraints: there are allocations which are sd-efficient but not dl-efficient.


Further reading

* Aziz, Gaspers, Mackenzie and Walsh study computational issues related to ordinal fairness notions. In Section 7 they briefly study sd-Pareto-efficiency. * Dogan, Dogan and Yildiz study a different domination relation between allocations: an allocation X dominates an allocation Y if it is Pareto-efficient for a larger set of bundle-rankings consistent with the item rankings. * Abdulkadiroğlu and Sönmez{{Cite journal , last1=Abdulkadiroğlu , first1=Atila , last2=Sönmez , first2=Tayfun , date=2003-09-01 , title=Ordinal efficiency and dominated sets of assignments , url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0022053103000917 , journal=Journal of Economic Theory , language=en , volume=112 , issue=1 , pages=157–172 , doi=10.1016/S0022-0531(03)00091-7 , hdl=10161/1940 , issn=0022-0531, hdl-access=free investigate the relation between sd-efficiency and ex-post Pareto-efficiency (in the context of random assignment). They introduce a new notion of domination for sets of assignments, and show that a lottery is sd-efficient iff each subset of the support of the lottery is undominated.


References

Pareto efficiency Random variable ordering