Responsive Set Extension
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
utility theory As a topic of economics, utility is used to model worth or value. Its usage has evolved significantly over time. The term was introduced initially as a measure of pleasure or happiness as part of the theory of utilitarianism by moral philosopher ...
, the responsive set (RS) extension is an extension of a preference-relation on individual items, to a partial preference-relation of item-bundles.


Example

Suppose there are four items: w,x,y,z. A person states that he ranks the items according to the following
total order In mathematics, a total or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( reflexive) ...
: :w \prec x \prec y \prec z (i.e., z is his best item, then y, then x, then w). Assuming the items are
independent goods Independent goods are goods that have a zero cross elasticity of demand. Changes in the price of one good will have no effect on the demand for an independent good. Thus independent goods are neither complements nor substitutes. For example, a ...
, one can deduce that: :\ \prec \ – the person prefers his two best items to his two worst items; :\ \prec \ – the person prefers his best and third-best items to his second-best and fourth-best items. But, one cannot deduce anything about the bundles \, \; we do not know which of them the person prefers. The RS extension of the ranking w \prec x \prec y \prec z is a
partial order In mathematics, especially order theory, a partially ordered set (also poset) formalizes and generalizes the intuitive concept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set. A poset consists of a set together with a binary ...
on the bundles of items, that includes all relations that can be deduced from the item-ranking and the independence assumption.


Definitions

Let O be a set of objects and \preceq a total order on O. The RS extension of \preceq is a partial order on 2^O. It can be defined in several equivalent ways.


Responsive set (RS)

The original RS extension is constructed as follows. For every bundle X\subseteq O, every item x\in X and every item y\notin X, take the following relations: *X\setminus\ \prec^ X (- adding an item improves the bundle) *If x\preceq y then X \preceq^ (X\setminus\)\cup \ (- replacing an item with a better item improves the bundle). The RS extension is the
transitive closure In mathematics, the transitive closure of a binary relation on a set is the smallest relation on that contains and is transitive. For finite sets, "smallest" can be taken in its usual sense, of having the fewest related pairs; for infinite s ...
of these relations.


Pairwise dominance (PD)

The PD extension is based on a ''pairing'' of the items in one bundle with the items in the other bundle. Formally, X \preceq^ Y if-and-only-if there exists an
Injective function In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements; that is, implies . (Equivalently, implies in the equivalent contrapositiv ...
f from X to Y such that, for each x\in X, x\preceq f(x).


Stochastic dominance (SD)

The SD extension (named after
stochastic dominance Stochastic dominance is a partial order between random variables. It is a form of stochastic ordering. The concept arises in decision theory and decision analysis in situations where one gamble (a probability distribution over possible outcomes, ...
) is defined not only on discrete bundles but also on fractional bundles (bundles that contains fractions of items). Informally, a bundle Y is SD-preferred to a bundle X if, for each item z, the bundle Y contains at least as many objects, that are at least as good as z, as the bundle X. Formally, X\preceq^ Y iff, for every item z: :\sum_ X \leq \sum_Y where X /math> is the fraction of item x in the bundle X. If the bundles are discrete, the definition has a simpler form. X\preceq^ Y iff, for every item z: :, \, \leq , \,


Additive utility (AU)

The AU extension is based on the notion of an
additive utility In economics, additive utility is a cardinal utility function with the sigma additivity property. Additivity (also called ''linearity'' or ''modularity'') means that "the whole is equal to the sum of its parts." That is, the utility of a set of ...
function. Many different utility functions are compatible with a given ordering. For example, the order w\prec x\prec y\prec z is compatible with the following utility functions: :u_1(w)=0, u_1(x)=2, u_1(y)=4, u_1(z)=7 :u_2(w)=0, u_2(x)=2, u_2(y)=4, u_2(z)=5 Assuming the items are independent, the utility function on bundles is additive, so the utility of a bundle is the sum of the utilities of its items, for example: :u_1(\)=2, u_1(\)=7, u_1(\)=6 :u_2(\)=2, u_2(\)=5, u_2(\)=6 The bundle \ has less utility than \ according to both utility functions. Moreover, for ''every'' utility function u compatible with the above ranking: :u(\). In contrast, the utility of the bundle \ can be either less or more than the utility of \. This motivates the following definition: X\preceq^ Y iff, for every additive utility function u compatible with \preceq: :u(X) \leq u(Y)


Equivalence

* X\preceq^ Y implies X\preceq^ Y. * X\preceq^ Y and X\preceq^ Y are equivalent. * X\preceq^ Y implies X\preceq^ Y. ''Proof'': If X\preceq^ Y, then there is an injection f: X\to Y such that, for all x\in X, x\preceq f(x). Therefore, for every utility function u compatible with \preceq, u(x) \leq u(f(x)). Therefore, if u is additive, then u(X) \leq u(Y). * It is known that \preceq^ and \preceq^ are equivalent, see e.g. Therefore, the four extensions \preceq^ and \preceq^ and \preceq^ and \preceq^ are all equivalent.


Responsive orders and valuations

A total order on bundles is called responsive if it is contains the responsive-set-extension of some total order on items. I.e., it contains all the relations that are implied by the underlying ordering of the items, and adds some more relations that are not implied nor contradicted. Similarly, a utility function on bundles is called responsive if it induces a responsive order. To be more explicit, a utility function ''u'' is responsive if for every bundle ''X'' and every two items ''y'',''z'' that are not in ''X'': u(y)\geq u(z) \implies u(X\cup \) \geq u(X\cup \). Responsiveness is implied by additivity, but not vice versa: * If a total order is additive (represented by an
additive function In number theory, an additive function is an arithmetic function ''f''(''n'') of the positive integer variable ''n'' such that whenever ''a'' and ''b'' are coprime, the function applied to the product ''ab'' is the sum of the values of the funct ...
) then by definition it contains the AU extension \preceq^, which is equivalent to \preceq^, so it is responsive. Similarly, if a utility function is additive, then u(X\cup \) - u(X\cup \) = u(y) - u(z), so responsiveness is satisfied. * On the other hand, a total order may responsive but not additive: it may contain the AU extension which is consistent with all additive functions, but may also contain other relations that are inconsistent with a single additive function. For example, suppose there are four items with w \prec x \prec y \prec z. Responsiveness constrains only the relation between bundles of the same size with one item replaced, or bundles of different sizes where the small is contained in the large. It says nothing about bundles of different sizes that are not subsets of each other. So, for example, a responsive order can have both \ \prec \ and \ \succ \. But this is incompatible with additivity: there is no additive function for which u(\) < u(\) while u(\) > u(\).


See also

*
Weakly additive In fair division, a topic in economics, a preference relation is weakly additive if the following condition is met: : If A is preferred to B, and C is preferred to D (and the contents of A and C do not overlap) then A together with C is preferabl ...
*
Picking sequence A picking sequence is a protocol for fair item assignment. Suppose ''m'' items have to be divided among ''n'' agents. One way to allocate the items is to let one agent select a single item, then let another agent select a single item, and so on. A p ...


References

{{reflist Utility function types