Reducibility Relation
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
computability theory Computability theory, also known as recursion theory, is a branch of mathematical logic, computer science, and the theory of computation that originated in the 1930s with the study of computable functions and Turing degrees. The field has since e ...
, many reducibility relations (also called reductions, reducibilities, and notions of reducibility) are studied. They are motivated by the question: given sets A and B of natural numbers, is it possible to effectively convert a method for deciding membership in B into a method for deciding membership in A? If the answer to this question is affirmative then A is said to be reducible to B. The study of reducibility notions is motivated by the study of
decision problems In computability theory and computational complexity theory, a decision problem is a computational problem that can be posed as a yes–no question of the input values. An example of a decision problem is deciding by means of an algorithm whethe ...
. For many notions of reducibility, if any noncomputable set is reducible to a set A then A must also be noncomputable. This gives a powerful technique for proving that many sets are noncomputable.


Reducibility relations

A reducibility relation is a binary relation on sets of natural numbers that is * Reflexive: Every set is reducible to itself. * Transitive: If a set A is reducible to a set B and B is reducible to a set C then A is reducible to C. These two properties imply that reducibility is a
preorder In mathematics, especially in order theory, a preorder or quasiorder is a binary relation that is reflexive and transitive. Preorders are more general than equivalence relations and (non-strict) partial orders, both of which are special c ...
on the powerset of the natural numbers. Not all preorders are studied as reducibility notions, however. The notions studied in computability theory have the informal property that A is reducible to B if and only if any (possibly noneffective) decision procedure for B can be effectively converted to a decision procedure for A. The different reducibility relations vary in the methods they permit such a conversion process to use.


Degrees of a reducibility relation

Every reducibility relation (in fact, every preorder) induces an equivalence relation on the powerset of the natural numbers in which two sets are equivalent if and only if each one is reducible to the other. In computability theory, these equivalence classes are called the degrees of the reducibility relation. For example, the Turing degrees are the equivalence classes of sets of naturals induced by Turing reducibility. The degrees of any reducibility relation are partially ordered by the relation in the following manner. Let \leq be a reducibility relation and let C and D be two of its degrees. Then C\leq D if and only if there is a set A in C and a set B in D such that A\leq B. This is equivalent to the property that for every set A in C and every set B in D, A\leq B, because any two sets in ''C'' are equivalent and any two sets in D are equivalent. It is common, as shown here, to use boldface notation to denote degrees.


Turing reducibility

The most fundamental reducibility notion is
Turing reducibility In computability theory, a Turing reduction from a decision problem A to a decision problem B is an oracle machine which decides problem A given an oracle for B (Rogers 1967, Soare 1987). It can be understood as an algorithm that could be used to s ...
. A set A of natural numbers is ''Turing reducible'' to a set B if and only if there is an
oracle Turing machine In complexity theory and computability theory, an oracle machine is an abstract machine used to study decision problems. It can be visualized as a Turing machine with a black box, called an oracle, which is able to solve certain problems in a s ...
that, when run with B as its oracle set, will compute the
indicator function In mathematics, an indicator function or a characteristic function of a subset of a set is a function that maps elements of the subset to one, and all other elements to zero. That is, if is a subset of some set , one has \mathbf_(x)=1 if x\i ...
(characteristic function) of A. Equivalently, A is Turing reducible to B if and only if there is an algorithm for computing the indicator function for A provided that the algorithm is provided with a means to correctly answer questions of the form "Is n in B?". Turing reducibility serves as a dividing line for other reducibility notions because, according to the Church-Turing thesis, it is the most general reducibility relation that is effective. Reducibility relations that imply Turing reducibility have come to be known as strong reducibilities, while those that are implied by Turing reducibility are weak reducibilities. Equivalently, a strong reducibility relation is one whose degrees form a finer equivalence relation than the Turing degrees, while a weak reducibility relation is one whose degrees form a coarser equivalence relation than Turing equivalence.


Reductions stronger than Turing reducibility

The strong reducibilities include * One-one reducibility: A is one-one reducible to B if there is a computable one-to-one function f with A(x) = B(f(x)) for all x. * Many-one reducibility: A is many-one reducible to B if there is a computable function f with A(x) = B(f(x)) for all x. * Truth-table reducible: A is truth-table reducible to B if A is Turing reducible to B via a single (oracle) Turing machine which produces a total function relative to every oracle. * Weak truth-table reducible: A is weak truth-table reducible to B if there is a Turing reduction from B to A and a computable function f which bounds the
use Use may refer to: * Use (law), an obligation on a person to whom property has been conveyed * Use (liturgy), a special form of Roman Catholic ritual adopted for use in a particular diocese * Use–mention distinction, the distinction between using ...
. Whenever A is truth-table reducible to B, A is also weak truth-table reducible to B, since one can construct a computable bound on the use by considering the maximum use over the tree of all oracles, which will exist if the reduction is total on all oracles. *Positive reducible: A is positive reducible to B if and only if A is truth-table reducible to B in a way that one can compute for every x a formula consisting of atoms of the form B(0), B(1), ... such that these atoms are combined by and's and or's, where the and of a and b is 1 if a = 1 and b = 1 and so on. *
Enumeration reducibility In computability theory and computational complexity theory, enumeration reducibility is a method of reduction that determines if there is some effective procedure for determining enumerability between sets of natural numbers. An enumeration in the ...
: Similar to positive reducibility, relating to the effective procedure of
enumerability In computability theory, a set ''S'' of natural numbers is called computably enumerable (c.e.), recursively enumerable (r.e.), semidecidable, partially decidable, listable, provable or Turing-recognizable if: *There is an algorithm such that th ...
from A to B''.'' *Disjunctive reducible: Similar to positive reducible with the additional constraint that only or's are permitted. *Conjunctive reducibility: Similar to positive reducibility with the additional constraint that only and's are permitted. *Linear reducibility: Similar to positive reducibility but with the constraint that all atoms of the form B(n) are combined by exclusive or's. In other words, A is linear reducible to B if and only if a computable function computes for each x a finite set F(x) given as an explicit list of numbers such that x \in A if and only if F(x) contains an odd number of elements of B. Many of these were introduced by Post (1944). Post was searching for a non-
computable Computability is the ability to solve a problem in an effective manner. It is a key topic of the field of computability theory within mathematical logic and the theory of computation within computer science. The computability of a problem is close ...
, computably enumerable set which the
halting problem In computability theory, the halting problem is the problem of determining, from a description of an arbitrary computer program and an input, whether the program will finish running, or continue to run forever. Alan Turing proved in 1936 that a g ...
could not be Turing reduced to. As he could not construct such a set in 1944, he instead worked on the analogous problems for the various reducibilities that he introduced. These reducibilities have since been the subject of much research, and many relationships between them are known.


Bounded reducibilities

A bounded form of each of the above strong reducibilities can be defined. The most famous of these is bounded truth-table reduction, but there are also bounded Turing, bounded weak truth-table, and others. These first three are the most common ones and they are based on the number of queries. For example, a set A is bounded truth-table reducible to B if and only if the Turing machine M computing A relative to B computes a list of up to n numbers, queries B on these numbers and then terminates for all possible oracle answers; the value n is a constant independent of x. The difference between bounded weak truth-table and bounded Turing reduction is that in the first case, the up to n queries have to be made at the same time while in the second case, the queries can be made one after the other. For that reason, there are cases where A is bounded Turing reducible to B but not weak truth-table reducible to B.


Strong reductions in computational complexity

The strong reductions listed above restrict the manner in which oracle information can be accessed by a decision procedure but do not otherwise limit the computational resources available. Thus if a set A is decidable then A is reducible to any set B under any of the strong reducibility relations listed above, even if A is not polynomial-time or exponential-time decidable. This is acceptable in the study of computability theory, which is interested in theoretical computability, but it is not reasonable for
computational complexity theory In theoretical computer science and mathematics, computational complexity theory focuses on classifying computational problems according to their resource usage, and relating these classes to each other. A computational problem is a task solved by ...
, which studies which sets can be decided under certain asymptotical resource bounds. The most common reducibility in computational complexity theory is polynomial-time reducibility; a set ''A'' is polynomial-time reducible to a set B if there is a polynomial-time function ''f'' such that for every n, n is in A if and only if f(n) is in B. This reducibility is, essentially, a resource-bounded version of many-one reducibility. Other resource-bounded reducibilities are used in other contexts of computational complexity theory where other resource bounds are of interest.


Reductions weaker than Turing reducibility

Although Turing reducibility is the most general reducibility that is effective, weaker reducibility relations are commonly studied. These reducibilities are related to the relative definability of sets over arithmetic or set theory. They include: *
Arithmetical reducibility In mathematical logic, the arithmetical hierarchy, arithmetic hierarchy or Kleene–Mostowski hierarchy (after mathematicians Stephen Cole Kleene and Andrzej Mostowski) classifies certain Set (mathematics), sets based on the complexity of formul ...
: A set A is arithmetical in a set B if A is definable over the standard model of
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly u ...
with an extra predicate for B. Equivalently, according to Post's theorem, ''A'' is arithmetical in B if and only if A is Turing reducible to B^, the nth
Turing jump In computability theory, the Turing jump or Turing jump operator, named for Alan Turing, is an operation that assigns to each decision problem a successively harder decision problem with the property that is not decidable by an oracle machine w ...
of B, for some natural number n. The arithmetical hierarchy gives a finer classification of arithmetical reducibility. *
Hyperarithmetical reducibility In recursion theory, hyperarithmetic theory is a generalization of Computable function, Turing computability. It has close connections with definability in second-order arithmetic and with weak systems of set theory such as Kripke–Platek set theo ...
: A set A is hyperarithmetical in a set B if A is \Delta^1_1 definable (see analytical hierarchy) over the standard model of Peano arithmetic with a predicate for B. Equivalently, A is hyperarithmetical in B if and only if A is Turing reducible to B^, the ath
Turing jump In computability theory, the Turing jump or Turing jump operator, named for Alan Turing, is an operation that assigns to each decision problem a successively harder decision problem with the property that is not decidable by an oracle machine w ...
of B, for some B-
recursive ordinal In mathematics, specifically computability and set theory, an ordinal \alpha is said to be computable or recursive if there is a computable well-ordering of a subset of the natural numbers having the order type \alpha. It is easy to check that \om ...
a. * Relative constructibility: A set A is relatively constructible from a set B if A is in L(B), the smallest transitive model of ZFC set theory containing B and all the ordinals.


References

* K. Ambos-Spies and P. Fejer, 2006.
Degrees of Unsolvability
" Unpublished preprint. * P. Odifreddi, 1989. ''Classical Recursion Theory'', North-Holland. * P. Odifreddi, 1999. ''Classical Recursion Theory, Volume II'', Elsevier. *E. Post, 1944, "Recursively enumerable sets of positive integers and their decision problems", ''Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society'', volume 50, pages 284–316. * H. Rogers, Jr., 1967. ''The Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability'', second edition 1987, MIT Press. (paperback), * G. Sacks, 1990. ''Higher Recursion Theory'', Springer-Verlag. {{isbn, 3-540-19305-7


Internet Resources


Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Recursive Functions