In the
mathematical study of logic and the
physical analysis of
quantum foundations, quantum logic is a set of rules for manipulation of
proposition
A proposition is a statement that can be either true or false. It is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields. Propositions are the object s denoted by declarative sentences; for example, "The sky ...
s inspired by the structure of
quantum theory. The formal system takes as its starting point an observation of
Garrett Birkhoff
Garrett Birkhoff (January 19, 1911 – November 22, 1996) was an American mathematician. He is best known for his work in lattice theory.
The mathematician George Birkhoff (1884–1944) was his father.
Life
The son of the mathematician Ge ...
and
John von Neumann, that the structure of experimental tests in classical mechanics forms a
Boolean algebra, but the structure of experimental tests in quantum mechanics forms a much more complicated structure.
A number of other logics have also been proposed to analyze quantum-mechanical phenomena, unfortunately also under the name of "quantum logic(s)". They are not the subject of this article. For discussion of the similarities and differences between quantum logic and some of these competitors, see '.
Quantum logic has been proposed as the correct logic for propositional inference generally, most notably by the philosopher
Hilary Putnam
Hilary Whitehall Putnam (; July 31, 1926 – March 13, 2016) was an American philosopher, mathematician, computer scientist, and figure in analytic philosophy in the second half of the 20th century. He contributed to the studies of philosophy of ...
, at least at one point in his career. This thesis was an important ingredient in Putnam's 1968 paper "
Is Logic Empirical?" in which he analysed the
epistemological
Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that examines the nature, origin, and limits of knowledge. Also called "the theory of knowledge", it explores different types of knowledge, such as propositional knowledge about facts, practical knowled ...
status of the rules of propositional logic. Modern philosophers reject quantum logic as a basis for reasoning, because it lacks a
material conditional
The material conditional (also known as material implication) is a binary operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol \to is interpreted as material implication, a formula P \to Q is true unless P is true and Q is false.
M ...
; a common alternative is the system of
linear logic, of which quantum logic is a fragment.
Mathematically, quantum logic is formulated by weakening the
distributive law for a Boolean algebra, resulting in an
orthocomplemented lattice. Quantum-mechanical
observables and
states can be defined in terms of functions on or to the lattice, giving an alternate
formalism for quantum computations.
Introduction
The most notable difference between quantum logic and
classical logic
Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy.
Characteristics
Each logical system in this c ...
is the failure of the
propositional distributive law:
: ''p'' and (''q'' or ''r'') = (''p'' and ''q'') or (''p'' and ''r''),
where the symbols ''p'', ''q'' and ''r'' are propositional variables.
To illustrate why the distributive law fails, consider a particle moving on a line and (using some system of units where the
reduced Planck constant is 1) let
[Due to technical reasons, it is not possible to represent these propositions as quantum-mechanical operators. They are presented here because they are simple enough to enable intuition, and can be considered as limiting cases of operators that ''are'' feasible. See ''et seq.'' for details.]
: ''p'' = "the particle has
momentum in the interval "
: ''q'' = "the particle is in the interval "
: ''r'' = "the particle is in the interval "
We might observe that:
: ''p'' and (''q'' or ''r'') = ''true''
in other words, that the state of the particle is a weighted
superposition of momenta between 0 and +1/6 and positions between −1 and +3.
On the other hand, the propositions "''p'' and ''q''" and "''p'' and ''r''" each assert tighter restrictions on simultaneous values of position and momentum than are allowed by the
uncertainty principle
The uncertainty principle, also known as Heisenberg's indeterminacy principle, is a fundamental concept in quantum mechanics. It states that there is a limit to the precision with which certain pairs of physical properties, such as position a ...
(they each have uncertainty 1/3, which is less than the allowed minimum of 1/2). So there are no states that can support either proposition, and
: (''p'' and ''q'') or (''p'' and ''r'') = ''false''
History and modern criticism
In his classic 1932 treatise ''
Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'',
John von Neumann noted that
projections on a
Hilbert space can be viewed as propositions about physical observables; that is, as potential ''yes-or-no questions'' an observer might ask about the state of a physical system, questions that could be settled by some measurement. Principles for manipulating these quantum propositions were then called ''quantum logic'' by von Neumann and Birkhoff in a 1936 paper.
George Mackey, in his 1963 book (also called ''Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics''), attempted to axiomatize quantum logic as the structure of an
orthocomplemented lattice, and recognized that a physical observable could be ''defined'' in terms of quantum propositions. Although Mackey's presentation still assumed that the orthocomplemented lattice is the
lattice of
closed linear subspace
In mathematics, the term ''linear'' is used in two distinct senses for two different properties:
* linearity of a ''function (mathematics), function'' (or ''mapping (mathematics), mapping'');
* linearity of a ''polynomial''.
An example of a li ...
s of a
separable Hilbert space,
Constantin Piron, Günther Ludwig and others later developed axiomatizations that do not assume an underlying Hilbert space.
Inspired by
Hans Reichenbach
Hans Reichenbach (; ; September 26, 1891 – April 9, 1953) was a leading philosopher of science, educator, and proponent of logical empiricism. He was influential in the areas of science, education, and of logical empiricism. He founded the ''G ...
's then-recent defence of
general relativity
General relativity, also known as the general theory of relativity, and as Einstein's theory of gravity, is the differential geometry, geometric theory of gravitation published by Albert Einstein in 1915 and is the current description of grav ...
, the philosopher
Hilary Putnam
Hilary Whitehall Putnam (; July 31, 1926 – March 13, 2016) was an American philosopher, mathematician, computer scientist, and figure in analytic philosophy in the second half of the 20th century. He contributed to the studies of philosophy of ...
popularized Mackey's work in two papers in 1968 and 1975, in which he attributed the idea that anomalies associated to quantum measurements originate with a failure of logic itself to his coauthor, physicist
David Finkelstein. Putnam hoped to develop a possible alternative to
hidden variables or
wavefunction collapse in the problem of
quantum measurement, but
Gleason's theorem presents severe difficulties for this goal. Later, Putnam retracted his views, albeit with much less fanfare, but the damage had been done. While Birkhoff and von Neumann's original work only attempted to organize the calculations associated with the
Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, a school of researchers had now sprung up, either hoping that quantum logic would provide a viable hidden-variable theory, or obviate the need for one. Their work proved fruitless, and now lies in poor repute.
Most philosophers would agree that quantum logic is not a competitor to
classical logic
Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy.
Characteristics
Each logical system in this c ...
. It is far from evident (albeit true) that quantum logic is a ''logic'', in the sense of describing a process of reasoning, as opposed to a particularly convenient language to summarize the measurements performed by quantum apparatuses. In particular, some modern
philosophers of science argue that quantum logic attempts to substitute metaphysical difficulties for unsolved problems in physics, rather than properly solving the physics problems.
Tim Maudlin writes that quantum "logic 'solves' the
problem">easurementproblem by making the problem impossible to state."
Quantum logic remains in use among logicians and interests are expanding through the recent development of
quantum computing
A quantum computer is a computer that exploits quantum mechanical phenomena. On small scales, physical matter exhibits properties of wave-particle duality, both particles and waves, and quantum computing takes advantage of this behavior using s ...
, which has engendered a proliferation of new logics for formal analysis of quantum protocols and algorithms (see also ). The logic may also find application in (computational) linguistics.
Algebraic structure
Quantum logic can be axiomatized as the theory of propositions modulo the following identities:
* ''a'' ¬¬''a''
* ∨ is
commutative
In mathematics, a binary operation is commutative if changing the order of the operands does not change the result. It is a fundamental property of many binary operations, and many mathematical proofs depend on it. Perhaps most familiar as a pr ...
and
associative.
* There is a maximal element ⊤, and ⊤ ''b''∨¬''b'' for any ''b''.
* ''a''∨¬(¬''a''∨''b'') ''a''.
("¬" is the traditional notation for "
not", "∨" the notation for "
or", and "∧" the notation for "
and".)
Some authors restrict to
orthomodular lattices, which additionally satisfy the orthomodular law:
* If ⊤ ¬(¬''a''∨¬''b'')∨¬(''a''∨''b'') then ''a'' ''b''.
("⊤" is the traditional notation for
truth
Truth or verity is the Property (philosophy), property of being in accord with fact or reality.Merriam-Webster's Online Dictionarytruth, 2005 In everyday language, it is typically ascribed to things that aim to represent reality or otherwise cor ...
and ""⊥" the traditional notation for
falsity.)
Alternative formulations include propositions derivable via a
natural deduction,
sequent calculus or
tableaux system. Despite the relatively developed
proof theory, quantum logic is not known to be
decidable.
Quantum logic as the logic of observables
The remainder of this article assumes the reader is familiar with the
spectral theory
In mathematics, spectral theory is an inclusive term for theories extending the eigenvector and eigenvalue theory of a single square matrix to a much broader theory of the structure of operator (mathematics), operators in a variety of mathematical ...
of
self-adjoint operators on a Hilbert space. However, the main ideas can be understood in the
finite-dimensional case.
Logic of classical mechanics
The
Hamiltonian
Hamiltonian may refer to:
* Hamiltonian mechanics, a function that represents the total energy of a system
* Hamiltonian (quantum mechanics), an operator corresponding to the total energy of that system
** Dyall Hamiltonian, a modified Hamiltonian ...
formulations of
classical mechanics
Classical mechanics is a Theoretical physics, physical theory describing the motion of objects such as projectiles, parts of Machine (mechanical), machinery, spacecraft, planets, stars, and galaxies. The development of classical mechanics inv ...
have three ingredients:
states,
observables and
dynamics. In the simplest case of a single particle moving in R
3, the state space is the position–momentum space R
6. An observable is some
real-valued function ''f'' on the state space. Examples of observables are position, momentum or energy of a particle. For classical systems, the value ''f''(''x''), that is the value of ''f'' for some particular system state ''x'', is obtained by a process of measurement of ''f''.
The
proposition
A proposition is a statement that can be either true or false. It is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields. Propositions are the object s denoted by declarative sentences; for example, "The sky ...
s concerning a classical system are generated from basic statements of the form
: "Measurement of ''f'' yields a value in the interval
'a'', ''b''for some real numbers ''a'', ''b''."
through the conventional arithmetic operations and
pointwise limits. It follows easily from this characterization of propositions in classical systems that the corresponding logic is identical to the
Boolean algebra of
Borel subsets of the state space. They thus obey the laws of
classical propositional logic (such as
de Morgan's laws) with the set operations of union and intersection corresponding to the
Boolean conjunctives and subset inclusion corresponding to
material implication.
In fact, a stronger claim is true: they must obey the
infinitary logic .
We summarize these remarks as follows: The proposition system of a classical system is a lattice with a distinguished ''orthocomplementation'' operation: The lattice operations of ''meet'' and ''join'' are respectively set intersection and set union. The orthocomplementation operation is set complement. Moreover, this lattice is ''sequentially complete'', in the sense that any sequence
''i''∈N of elements of the lattice has a
least upper bound, specifically the set-theoretic union:
Propositional lattice of a quantum mechanical system
In the
Hilbert space formulation of quantum mechanics as presented by von Neumann, a physical observable is represented by some (possibly
unbounded) densely defined
self-adjoint operator ''A'' on a Hilbert space ''H''. ''A'' has a
spectral decomposition, which is a
projection-valued measure E defined on the Borel subsets of R. In particular, for any bounded
Borel function ''f'' on R, the following extension of ''f'' to operators can be made:
In case ''f'' is the indicator function of an interval
'a'', ''b'' the operator ''f''(''A'') is a self-adjoint projection onto the subspace of
generalized eigenvectors of ''A'' with eigenvalue in . That subspace can be interpreted as the quantum analogue of the classical proposition
* Measurement of ''A'' yields a value in the interval
'a'', ''b''
This suggests the following quantum mechanical replacement for the orthocomplemented lattice of propositions in classical mechanics, essentially Mackey's ''Axiom VII'':
* The propositions of a quantum mechanical system correspond to the lattice of closed subspaces of ''H''; the negation of a proposition ''V'' is the orthogonal complement ''V''
⊥.
The space ''Q'' of quantum propositions is also sequentially complete: any pairwise-disjoint sequence
''i'' of elements of ''Q'' has a least upper bound. Here disjointness of ''W''
1 and ''W''
2 means ''W''
2 is a subspace of ''W''
1⊥. The least upper bound of
''i'' is the closed internal
direct sum.
Standard semantics
The standard semantics of quantum logic is that quantum logic is the logic of
projection operators in a
separable Hilbert
David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician and philosophy of mathematics, philosopher of mathematics and one of the most influential mathematicians of his time.
Hilbert discovered and developed a broad ...
or
pre-Hilbert space, where an observable ''p'' is associated with the
set of quantum states for which ''p'' (when measured) has
eigenvalue 1. From there,
* ''¬p'' is the
orthogonal complement of ''p'' (since for those states, the probability of observing ''p'', P(''p'') = 0),
* ''p''∧''q'' is the intersection of ''p'' and ''q'', and
* ''p''∨''q'' = ¬(¬''p''∧¬''q'') refers to states that
superpose ''p'' and ''q''.
This semantics has the nice property that the pre-Hilbert space is complete (i.e., Hilbert) if and only if the propositions satisfy the orthomodular law, a result known as the
Solèr theorem. Although much of the development of quantum logic has been motivated by the standard semantics, it is not characterized by the latter; there are additional properties satisfied by that lattice that need not hold in quantum logic.
Differences with classical logic
The structure of ''Q'' immediately points to a difference with the partial order structure of a classical proposition system. In the classical case, given a proposition ''p'', the equations
: ⊤ = ''p''∨''q'' and
: ⊥ = ''p''∧''q''
have exactly one solution, namely the set-theoretic complement of ''p''. In the case of the lattice of projections there are infinitely many solutions to the above equations (any closed, algebraic complement of ''p'' solves it; it need not be the orthocomplement).
More generally,
propositional valuation has unusual properties in quantum logic. An orthocomplemented lattice admitting a
total lattice homomorphism to must be Boolean. A standard workaround is to study maximal partial homomorphisms ''q'' with a filtering property:
: if ''a''≤''b'' and ''q''(''a'') = ⊤, then ''q''(''b'') = ⊤.
Failure of distributivity
Expressions in quantum logic describe observables using a syntax that resembles classical logic. However, unlike classical logic, the distributive law ''a'' ∧ (''b'' ∨ ''c'') = (''a'' ∧ ''b'') ∨ (''a'' ∧ ''c'') fails when dealing with
noncommuting observables, such as position and momentum. This occurs because measurement affects the system, and measurement of whether a disjunction holds does not measure which of the disjuncts is true.
For example, consider a simple one-dimensional particle with position denoted by ''x'' and momentum by ''p'', and define observables:
* ''a'' — , ''p'', ≤ 1 (in some units)
* ''b'' — x ≤ 0
* ''c'' — x ≥ 0
Now, position and momentum are Fourier transforms of each other, and the
Fourier transform of a
square-integrable nonzero function with a
compact support
In mathematics, the support of a real-valued function f is the subset of the function domain of elements that are not mapped to zero. If the domain of f is a topological space, then the support of f is instead defined as the smallest closed ...
is
entire and hence does not have non-isolated zeroes. Therefore, there is no wave function that is both
normalizable in momentum space and vanishes on precisely ''x'' ≥ 0. Thus, ''a'' ∧ ''b'' and similarly ''a'' ∧ ''c'' are false, so (''a'' ∧ ''b'') ∨ (''a'' ∧ ''c'') is false. However, ''a'' ∧ (''b'' ∨ ''c'') equals ''a'', which is certainly not false (there are states for which it is a viable
measurement outcome). Moreover: if the relevant Hilbert space for the particle's dynamics only admits momenta no greater than 1, then ''a'' is true.
To understand more, let ''p''
1 and ''p''
2 be the momentum functions (Fourier transforms) for the projections of the particle wave function to ''x'' ≤ 0 and ''x'' ≥ 0 respectively. Let , ''p''
i, ↾
≥1 be the restriction of ''p''
i to momenta that are (in absolute value) ≥1.
(''a'' ∧ ''b'') ∨ (''a'' ∧ ''c'') corresponds to states with , ''p''
1, ↾
≥1 = , ''p''
2, ↾
≥1 = 0 (this holds even if we defined ''p'' differently so as to make such states possible; also, ''a'' ∧ ''b'' corresponds to , ''p''
1, ↾
≥1=0 and ''p''
2=0). Meanwhile, ''a'' corresponds to states with , ''p'', ↾
≥1 = 0. As an operator, ''p'' = ''p''
1 + ''p''
2, and nonzero , ''p''
1, ↾
≥1 and , ''p''
2, ↾
≥1 might interfere to produce zero , ''p'', ↾
≥1. Such interference is key to the richness of quantum logic and quantum mechanics.
Relationship to quantum measurement
Mackey observables
Given a
orthocomplemented lattice ''Q'', a Mackey observable φ is a
countably additive homomorphism from the orthocomplemented lattice of Borel subsets of R to ''Q''. In symbols, this means that for any sequence
''i'' of pairwise-disjoint Borel subsets of R,
''i'' are pairwise-orthogonal propositions (elements of ''Q'') and
:
Equivalently, a Mackey observable is a
projection-valued measure on R.
Theorem (
Spectral theorem). If ''Q'' is the lattice of closed subspaces of Hilbert ''H'', then there is a bijective correspondence between Mackey observables and densely-defined self-adjoint operators on ''H''.
Quantum probability measures
A ''quantum probability measure'' is a function P defined on ''Q'' with values in
,1such that P("⊥)=0, P(⊤)=1 and if
''i'' is a sequence of pairwise-orthogonal elements of ''Q'' then
:
Every quantum probability measure on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space is induced by a
density matrix — a
nonnegative operator of
trace 1. Formally,
: Theorem. Suppose ''Q'' is the lattice of closed subspaces of a separable Hilbert space of complex dimension at least 3. Then for any quantum probability measure ''P'' on ''Q'' there exists a unique
trace class operator ''S'' such that
for any self-adjoint projection ''E'' in ''Q''.
Relationship to other logics
Quantum logic embeds into
linear logic[Vaughan Pratt,]
Linear logic for generalized quantum mechanics
" in ''Workshop on Physics and Computation (PhysComp '92)'' proceedings. See also the discussion at ''n''Lab
Revision 42
which cites G.D. Crown, "On some orthomodular posets of vector bundles," ''Journ. of Natural Sci. and Math.'', vol. 15 issue 1-2: pp. 11–25, 1975. and the
modal logic ''B''. Indeed, modern logics for the analysis of quantum computation often begin with quantum logic, and attempt to graft desirable features of an extension of classical logic thereonto; the results then necessarily embed quantum logic.
The orthocomplemented lattice of any set of quantum propositions can be embedded into a Boolean algebra, which is then amenable to classical logic.
Limitations
Although many treatments of quantum logic assume that the underlying lattice must be orthomodular, such logics cannot handle multiple interacting quantum systems. In an example due to Foulis and Randall, there are orthomodular propositions with finite-dimensional Hilbert models whose pairing admits no orthomodular model. Likewise, quantum logic with the orthomodular law falsifies the
deduction theorem.
Quantum logic admits no reasonable
material conditional
The material conditional (also known as material implication) is a binary operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol \to is interpreted as material implication, a formula P \to Q is true unless P is true and Q is false.
M ...
; any
connective that is
monotone in a certain technical sense reduces the class of propositions to a
Boolean algebra. Consequently, quantum logic struggles to represent the passage of time.
One possible workaround is the theory of
quantum filtrations developed in the late 1970s and 1980s by
Belavkin.
[
] It is known, however, that System
BV, a
deep inference fragment of
linear logic that is very close to quantum logic, can handle arbitrary
discrete spacetimes.
[Richard Blute, Alessio Guglielmi, Ivan T. Ivanov, Prakash Panangaden, Lutz Straßburger, "A Logical Basis for Quantum Evolution and Entanglement" in ''Categories and Types in Logic, Language, and Physics: Essays Dedicated to Jim Lambek on the Occasion of His 90th Birthday''; Springer, 2014. pp. 90-107. DOI:&nbs]
10.1007/978-3-642-54789-8_6
HAL&nbs
01092279
See also
*
Fuzzy logic
Fuzzy logic is a form of many-valued logic in which the truth value of variables may be any real number between 0 and 1. It is employed to handle the concept of partial truth, where the truth value may range between completely true and completely ...
*
HPO formalism (An approach to temporal quantum logic)
*
Linear logic
*
Mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics
*
Multi-valued logic
Many-valued logic (also multi- or multiple-valued logic) is a propositional calculus in which there are more than two truth values. Traditionally, in Aristotle's logical calculus, there were only two possible values (i.e., "true" and "false") ...
*
Quantum Bayesianism
*
Quantum cognition
*
Quantum contextuality
*
Quantum field theory
In theoretical physics, quantum field theory (QFT) is a theoretical framework that combines Field theory (physics), field theory and the principle of relativity with ideas behind quantum mechanics. QFT is used in particle physics to construct phy ...
*
Quantum probability
*
Quasi-set theory
*
Solèr's theorem
*
Vector logic
Notes
Citations
Sources
Historical works
: ''Arranged chronologically''
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
Modern philosophical perspectives
*
*
*
*
Mathematical study and computational applications
*
*
*
*
*
* N. Papanikolaou,
Reasoning Formally About Quantum Systems: An Overview, ''ACM SIGACT News'', 36(3), 2005. pp. 51–66. arXi
cs/0508005
Quantum foundations
* D. Cohen, ''An Introduction to Hilbert Space and Quantum Logic'', Springer-Verlag, 1989. Elementary and well-illustrated; suitable for advanced undergraduates.
*
*
*
{{DEFAULTSORT:Quantum Logic
Mathematical logic
Systems of formal logic
Non-classical logic
Applications of quantum mechanics