HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

This article gives a sketch of a proof of Gödel's first incompleteness theorem. This theorem applies to any formal theory that satisfies certain technical hypotheses, which are discussed as needed during the sketch. We will assume for the remainder of the article that a fixed theory satisfying these hypotheses has been selected. Throughout this article the word "number" refers to a
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country"). Numbers used for counting are called '' cardinal ...
. The key property these numbers possess is that any natural number can be obtained by starting with the number 0 and adding 1 a finite number of times.


Hypotheses of the theory

Gödel's theorem applies to any formal theory that satisfies certain properties. Each formal theory has a
signature A signature (; from la, signare, "to sign") is a Handwriting, handwritten (and often Stylization, stylized) depiction of someone's name, nickname, or even a simple "X" or other mark that a person writes on documents as a proof of identity and ...
that specifies the nonlogical symbols in the language of the theory. For simplicity, we will assume that the language of the theory is composed from the following collection of 15 (and only 15) symbols: * A constant symbol for zero. * A unary function symbol for the successor operation and two binary function symbols + and × for addition and multiplication. * Three symbols for logical conjunction, , disjunction, , and negation, ¬. * Two symbols for universal, , and existential, , quantifiers. * Two symbols for binary relations, = and <, for equality and order (less than). * Two symbols for left, and right, parentheses for establishing precedence of quantifiers. * A single variable symbol, and a distinguishing symbol that can be used to construct additional variables of the form ''x*'', ''x**'', ''x***'', ... This is the language of
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearl ...
. A
well-formed formula In mathematical logic, propositional logic and predicate logic, a well-formed formula, abbreviated WFF or wff, often simply formula, is a finite sequence of symbols from a given alphabet that is part of a formal language. A formal language can ...
is a sequence of these symbols that is formed so as to have a well-defined reading as a mathematical formula. Thus is well formed while is not well formed. A theory is a set of well-formed formulas with no
free variable In mathematics, and in other disciplines involving formal languages, including mathematical logic and computer science, a free variable is a notation (symbol) that specifies places in an expression where substitution may take place and is not ...
s. A theory is
consistent In classical deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. The lack of contradiction can be defined in either semantic or syntactic terms. The semantic definition states that a theory is consistent ...
if there is no formula such that both and its negation are provable. ω-consistency is a stronger property than consistency. Suppose that is a formula with one free variable . In order to be ω-consistent, the theory cannot prove both while also proving for each natural number . The theory is assumed to be effective, which means that the set of axioms must be
recursively enumerable In computability theory, a set ''S'' of natural numbers is called computably enumerable (c.e.), recursively enumerable (r.e.), semidecidable, partially decidable, listable, provable or Turing-recognizable if: *There is an algorithm such that the ...
. This means that it is theoretically possible to write a finite-length computer program that, if allowed to run forever, would output the axioms of the theory (necessarily including every well-formed instance of the axiom schema of induction) one at a time and not output anything else. This requirement is necessary; there are theories that are
complete Complete may refer to: Logic * Completeness (logic) * Completeness of a theory, the property of a theory that every formula in the theory's language or its negation is provable Mathematics * The completeness of the real numbers, which implies t ...
, consistent, and include elementary arithmetic, but no such theory can be effective.


Outline of the proof

: ''For a simplified outline of the proof, see
Gödel's incompleteness theorems Gödel's incompleteness theorems are two theorems of mathematical logic that are concerned with the limits of in formal axiomatic theories. These results, published by Kurt Gödel in 1931, are important both in mathematical logic and in the phil ...
'' The sketch here is broken into three parts. In the first part, each formula of the theory is assigned a number, known as a Gödel number, in a manner that allows the formula to be effectively recovered from the number. This numbering is extended to cover finite sequences of formulas. In the second part, a specific formula is constructed such that for any two numbers and holds if and only if represents a sequence of formulas that constitutes a proof of the formula that represents. In the third part of the proof, we construct a self-referential formula that, informally, says "I am not provable", and prove that this sentence is neither provable nor disprovable within the theory. Importantly, all the formulas in the proof can be defined by
primitive recursive function In computability theory, a primitive recursive function is roughly speaking a function that can be computed by a computer program whose loops are all "for" loops (that is, an upper bound of the number of iterations of every loop can be determined ...
s, which themselves can be defined in
first-order In mathematics and other formal sciences, first-order or first order most often means either: * "linear" (a polynomial of degree at most one), as in first-order approximation and other calculus uses, where it is contrasted with "polynomials of hig ...
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearl ...
.


Gödel numbering

The first step of the proof is to represent (well-formed) formulas of the theory, and finite lists of these formulas, as natural numbers. These numbers are called the Gödel numbers of the formulas. Begin by assigning a natural number to each symbol of the language of arithmetic, similar to the manner in which the
ASCII ASCII ( ), abbreviated from American Standard Code for Information Interchange, is a character encoding standard for electronic communication. ASCII codes represent text in computers, telecommunications equipment, and other devices. Because ...
code assigns a unique binary number to each letter and certain other characters. This article will employ the following assignment, very similar to the one
Douglas Hofstadter Douglas Richard Hofstadter (born February 15, 1945) is an American scholar of cognitive science, physics, and comparative literature whose research includes concepts such as the sense of self in relation to the external world, consciousness, a ...
used in his ''
Gödel, Escher, Bach ''Gödel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid'', also known as ''GEB'', is a 1979 book by Douglas Hofstadter. By exploring common themes in the lives and works of logician Kurt Gödel, artist M. C. Escher, and composer Johann Sebastian Bach, t ...
'':Hofstadter, D. R. (1979). Gödel, escher, bach. Hassocks, Sussex: Harvester press. The Gödel number of a formula is obtained by concatenating the Gödel numbers of each symbol making up the formula. The Gödel numbers for each symbol are separated by a zero because by design, no Gödel number of a symbol includes a . Hence any formula may be correctly recovered from its Gödel number. Let denote the Gödel number of the formula . Given the above Gödel numbering, the sentence asserting that addition commutes, translates as the number: : (Spaces have been inserted on each side of every 0 only for readability; Gödel numbers are strict concatenations of decimal digits.) Not all natural numbers represent a formula. For example, the number : translates to "", which is not well-formed. Because each natural number can be obtained by applying the
successor Successor may refer to: * An entity that comes after another (see Succession (disambiguation)) Film and TV * ''The Successor'' (film), a 1996 film including Laura Girling * ''The Successor'' (TV program), a 2007 Israeli television program Musi ...
operation to a finite number of times, every natural number has its own Gödel number. For example, the Gödel number corresponding to , is: : . The assignment of Gödel numbers can be extended to finite lists of formulas. To obtain the Gödel number of a list of formulas, write the Gödel numbers of the formulas in order, separating them by two consecutive zeros. Since the Gödel number of a formula never contains two consecutive zeros, each formula in a list of formulas can be effectively recovered from the Gödel number for the list. It is crucial that the formal arithmetic be capable of proving a minimum set of facts. In particular, it must be able to prove that every number has a Gödel number . A second fact that the theory must prove is that given any Gödel number of a formula with one free variable and any number , there is a Gödel number of the formula obtained by replacing all occurrences of in with , and that this second Gödel number can be effectively obtained from the Gödel number of as a function of . To see that this is in fact possible, note that given the Gödel number of , one can recreate the original formula , make the substitution of with , and then find the Gödel number of the resulting formula . This is a uniform procedure.


The provability relation

Deduction rules can then be represented by binary relations on Gödel numbers of lists of formulas. In other words, suppose that there is a deduction rule , by which one can move from the formulas to a new formula . Then the relation corresponding to this deduction rule says that is related to (in other words, holds) if is the Gödel number of the list of formulas containing and and is the Gödel number of the list of formulas containing , and . Because each deduction rule is concrete, it is possible to effectively determine for any natural numbers and whether they are related by the relation. The second stage in the proof is to use the Gödel numbering, described above, to show that the notion of provability can be expressed within the formal language of the theory. Suppose the theory has deduction rules: . Let be their corresponding relations, as described above. Every provable statement is either an axiom itself, or it can be deduced from the axioms by a finite number of applications of the deduction rules. A proof of a formula is itself a string of mathematical statements related by particular relations (each is either an axiom or related to former statements by deduction rules), where the last statement is . Thus one can define the Gödel number of a proof. Moreover, one may define a statement form , which for every two numbers and is provable if and only if is the Gödel number of a proof of the statement and . is in fact an arithmetical relation, just as "" is, though a (much) more complicated one. Given such a relation , for any two specific numbers and , either the formula , or its negation , but not both, is provable. This is because the relation between these two numbers can be simply "checked". Formally this can be proven by induction, where all these possible relations (whose number is infinite) are constructed one by one. The detailed construction of the formula makes essential use of the assumption that the theory is effective; it would not be possible to construct this formula without such an assumption.


Self-referential formula

For every number and every formula , where is a free variable, we define , a relation between two numbers and , such that it corresponds to the statement " is not the Gödel number of a proof of ". Here, can be understood as with its own Gödel number as its argument. Note that takes as an argument , the Gödel number of . In order to prove either , or , it is necessary to perform number-theoretic operations on that mirror the following steps: decode the number into the formula , replace all occurrences of in with the number , and then compute the Gödel number of the resulting formula . Note that for every specific number and formula is a straightforward (though complicated) arithmetical relation between two numbers and , building on the relation defined earlier. Further, is provable if the finite list of formulas encoded by is not a proof of , and is provable if the finite list of formulas encoded by is a proof of . Given any numbers and , either or (but not both) is provable. Any proof of can be encoded by a Gödel number , such that does not hold. If holds for all natural numbers , then there is no proof of . In other words, , a formula about natural numbers, corresponds to "there is no proof of ". We now define the formula , where is a free variable. The formula itself has a Gödel number as does every formula. This formula has a free variable . Suppose we replace it with , the Gödel number of a formula , where is a free variable. Then, corresponds to "there is no proof of ", as we have seen. Consider the formula . This formula concerning the number corresponds to "there is no proof of ". We have here the self-referential feature that is crucial to the proof: A formula of the formal theory that somehow relates to its own provability within that formal theory. Very informally, says: "I am not provable". We will now show that neither the formula , nor its negation , is provable. Suppose is provable. Let be the Gödel number of a proof of . Then, as seen earlier, the formula is provable. Proving both and violates the
consistency In classical deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. The lack of contradiction can be defined in either semantic or syntactic terms. The semantic definition states that a theory is consistent ...
of the formal theory. We therefore conclude that is not provable. Consider any number . Suppose is provable. Then, must be the Gödel number of a proof of . But we have just proved that is not provable. Since either or must be provable, we conclude that, for all natural numbers is provable. Suppose the negation of , , is provable. Proving both , and , for all natural numbers , violates ω-consistency of the formal theory. Thus if the theory is ω-consistent, is not provable. We have sketched a proof showing that: For any formal, recursively enumerable (i.e. effectively generated) theory of
Peano Arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearl ...
, : if it is
consistent In classical deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. The lack of contradiction can be defined in either semantic or syntactic terms. The semantic definition states that a theory is consistent ...
, then there exists an unprovable formula (in the language of that theory). : if it is ω-consistent, then there exists a formula such that both it and its negation are unprovable.


The truth of the Gödel sentence

The proof of Gödel's incompleteness theorem just sketched is proof-theoretic (also called syntactic) in that it shows that if certain proofs exist (a proof of or its negation) then they can be manipulated to produce a proof of a contradiction. This makes no appeal to whether is "true", only to whether it is provable. Truth is a model-theoretic, or semantic, concept, and is not equivalent to provability except in special cases. By analyzing the situation of the above proof in more detail, it is possible to obtain a conclusion about the truth of in the standard model \mathbb of natural numbers. As just seen, is provable for each natural number , and is thus true in the model \mathbb. Therefore, within this model, : P(G(P)) = \forall y\,q(y, G(P)) holds. This is what the statement " is true" usually refers to—the sentence is true in the intended model. It is not true in every model, however: If it were, then by Gödel's completeness theorem it would be provable, which we have just seen is not the case.


Boolos's short proof

George Boolos George Stephen Boolos (; 4 September 1940 – 27 May 1996) was an American philosopher and a mathematical logician who taught at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Life Boolos is of Greek- Jewish descent. He graduated with an A.B. ...
(1989) vastly simplified the proof of the First Theorem, if one agrees that the
theorem In mathematics, a theorem is a statement that has been proved, or can be proved. The ''proof'' of a theorem is a logical argument that uses the inference rules of a deductive system to establish that the theorem is a logical consequence of t ...
is equivalent to:
"There is no
algorithm In mathematics and computer science, an algorithm () is a finite sequence of rigorous instructions, typically used to solve a class of specific problems or to perform a computation. Algorithms are used as specifications for performing ...
whose output contains all true sentences of arithmetic and no false ones."
"Arithmetic" refers to
Peano Giuseppe Peano (; ; 27 August 1858 – 20 April 1932) was an Italian mathematician and glottologist. The author of over 200 books and papers, he was a founder of mathematical logic and set theory, to which he contributed much notation. The sta ...
or
Robinson arithmetic In mathematics, Robinson arithmetic is a finitely axiomatized fragment of first-order Peano arithmetic (PA), first set out by R. M. Robinson in 1950. It is usually denoted Q. Q is almost PA without the axiom schema of mathematical induction. Q i ...
, but the proof invokes no specifics of either, tacitly assuming that these systems allow '<' and '×' to have their usual meanings. Boolos proves the theorem in about two pages. His proof employs the language of
first-order logic First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantifie ...
, but invokes no facts about the connectives or quantifiers. The
domain of discourse In the formal sciences, the domain of discourse, also called the universe of discourse, universal set, or simply universe, is the set of entities over which certain variables of interest in some formal treatment may range. Overview The doma ...
is the
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country"). Numbers used for counting are called '' cardinal ...
s. The Gödel sentence builds on
Berry's paradox The Berry paradox is a self-referential paradox arising from an expression like "The smallest positive integer not definable in under sixty letters" (a phrase with fifty-seven letters). Bertrand Russell, the first to discuss the paradox in print, ...
. Let abbreviate successive applications of the
successor function In mathematics, the successor function or successor operation sends a natural number to the next one. The successor function is denoted by ''S'', so ''S''(''n'') = ''n'' +1. For example, ''S''(1) = 2 and ''S''(2) = 3. The successor functio ...
, starting from . Boolos then asserts (the details are only sketched) that there exists a defined predicate that comes out true iff an arithmetic formula containing symbols names the number . This proof sketch contains the only mention of Gödel numbering; Boolos merely assumes that every formula can be so numbered. Here, a formula ''names'' the number iff the following is provable: : \forall x (F(x) \leftrightarrow x=n) Boolos then defines the related predicates: * . (English: comes out true if can be defined in fewer than symbols): * . (English: comes out true if is the smallest number not definable in fewer than symbols. More awkwardly, holds if cannot be defined in fewer than symbols, and all numbers less than can be defined using fewer than symbols); * . the number of symbols appearing in . formalizes Berry's paradox. The balance of the proof, requiring but 12 lines of text, shows that the sentence is true for some number , but no algorithm will identify it as true. Hence in arithmetic, truth outruns proof. QED. The above predicates contain the only
existential quantifier In predicate logic, an existential quantification is a type of quantifier, a logical constant which is interpreted as "there exists", "there is at least one", or "for some". It is usually denoted by the logical operator symbol ∃, which, w ...
s appearing in the entire proof. The '<' and '×' appearing in these predicates are the only defined arithmetical notions the proof requires. The proof nowhere mentions recursive functions or any facts from
number theory Number theory (or arithmetic or higher arithmetic in older usage) is a branch of pure mathematics devoted primarily to the study of the integers and integer-valued functions. German mathematician Carl Friedrich Gauss (1777–1855) said, "Ma ...
, and Boolos claims that his proof dispenses with diagonalization. For more on this proof, see
Berry's paradox The Berry paradox is a self-referential paradox arising from an expression like "The smallest positive integer not definable in under sixty letters" (a phrase with fifty-seven letters). Bertrand Russell, the first to discuss the paradox in print, ...
.


References

* 1931, "Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme, I." ''Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik 38'': 173–98. * English translations of the preceding: **
Jean van Heijenoort Jean Louis Maxime van Heijenoort (; July 23, 1912 – March 29, 1986) was a historian of mathematical logic. He was also a personal secretary to Leon Trotsky from 1932 to 1939, and an American Trotskyist until 1947. Life Van Heijenoort was born ...
, 1967. ''From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book on Mathematical Logic''. Harvard University Press: 596–616. ** Hirzel, Martin (trans.), 2000
"On formally undecidable propositions of Principia Mathematica and related systems I."
* 1951, "Some basic theorems on the foundations of mathematics and their implications" in
Solomon Feferman Solomon Feferman (December 13, 1928 – July 26, 2016) was an American philosopher and mathematician who worked in mathematical logic. Life Solomon Feferman was born in The Bronx in New York City to working-class parents who had immigrated to th ...
, ed., 1995. ''Collected works / Kurt Gödel, Vol. III''. Oxford University Press: 304–23. *
George Boolos George Stephen Boolos (; 4 September 1940 – 27 May 1996) was an American philosopher and a mathematical logician who taught at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Life Boolos is of Greek- Jewish descent. He graduated with an A.B. ...
, 1998, "A New Proof of the Gödel Incompleteness Theorem" in Boolos, G., ''Logic, Logic, and Logic''. Harvard Univ. Press.


Citations


External links


A concise proof of Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem.
{{Mathematical logic Mathematical logic Mathematical proofs