HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premises ...
, Peirce's law is named after the
philosopher A philosopher is a person who practices or investigates philosophy. The term ''philosopher'' comes from the grc, φιλόσοφος, , translit=philosophos, meaning 'lover of wisdom'. The coining of the term has been attributed to the Greek th ...
and
logician Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premises ...
Charles Sanders Peirce Charles Sanders Peirce ( ; September 10, 1839 – April 19, 1914) was an American philosopher, logician, mathematician and scientist who is sometimes known as "the father of pragmatism". Educated as a chemist and employed as a scientist for ...
. It was taken as an
axiom An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or f ...
in his first axiomatisation of
propositional logic Propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. It deals with propositions (which can be true or false) and relations b ...
. It can be thought of as the
law of excluded middle In logic, the law of excluded middle (or the principle of excluded middle) states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the so-called three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontrad ...
written in a form that involves only one sort of connective, namely implication. In
propositional calculus Propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. It deals with propositions (which can be true or false) and relations b ...
, Peirce's law says that ((''P''→''Q'')→''P'')→''P''. Written out, this means that ''P'' must be true if there is a proposition ''Q'' such that the truth of ''P''
follows from Follows is a surname. Notable people with the surname include: * Dave Follows (1941–2003), British cartoonist * Denis Follows (1908–1983), British sports administrator * Geoffrey Follows (1896–1983), British colonial administrator * Mega ...
the truth of "if ''P'' then ''Q''". In particular, when ''Q'' is taken to be a false formula, the law says that if ''P'' must be true whenever it implies falsity,
then Then may refer to: * Then language The Then language (also known as Yánghuáng 佯僙语 in Chinese; alternate spellings: Tʻen and Ten) is a Kam–Sui language spoken in Pingtang County, southern Guizhou. It is spoken by the Yanghuang 佯 ...
''P'' is true. In this way Peirce's law implies the
law of excluded middle In logic, the law of excluded middle (or the principle of excluded middle) states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the so-called three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontrad ...
. Peirce's law does not hold in
intuitionistic logic Intuitionistic logic, sometimes more generally called constructive logic, refers to systems of symbolic logic that differ from the systems used for classical logic by more closely mirroring the notion of constructive proof. In particular, systems o ...
or
intermediate logic In mathematical logic, a superintuitionistic logic is a propositional logic extending intuitionistic logic. Classical logic is the strongest consistent superintuitionistic logic; thus, consistent superintuitionistic logics are called intermediate l ...
s and cannot be deduced from the
deduction theorem In mathematical logic, a deduction theorem is a metatheorem that justifies doing conditional proofs—to prove an implication ''A'' → ''B'', assume ''A'' as an hypothesis and then proceed to derive ''B''—in systems that do not have an ...
alone. Under the Curry–Howard isomorphism, Peirce's law is the type of
continuation In computer science, a continuation is an abstract representation of the control state of a computer program. A continuation implements ( reifies) the program control state, i.e. the continuation is a data structure that represents the computat ...
operators, e.g. call/cc in
Scheme A scheme is a systematic plan for the implementation of a certain idea. Scheme or schemer may refer to: Arts and entertainment * ''The Scheme'' (TV series), a BBC Scotland documentary series * The Scheme (band), an English pop band * ''The Schem ...
.Timothy G. Griffin, A Formulae-as-Types Notion of Control, 1990
- Griffin defines K on page 3 as an equivalent to Scheme's call/cc and then discusses its type being the equivalent of Peirce's law at the end of section 5 on page 9.


History

Here is Peirce's own statement of the law: : A ''fifth icon'' is required for the principle of
excluded middle In logic, the law of excluded middle (or the principle of excluded middle) states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the so-called three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontradi ...
and other propositions connected with it. One of the simplest formulae of this kind is: : This is hardly axiomatical. That it is true appears as follows. It can only be false by the final consequent ''x'' being false while its antecedent (''x'' → ''y'') → ''x'' is true. If this is true, either its consequent, ''x'', is true, when the whole formula would be true, or its antecedent ''x'' → ''y'' is false. But in the last case the antecedent of ''x'' → ''y'', that is ''x'', must be true. (Peirce, the ''Collected Papers'' 3.384). Peirce goes on to point out an immediate application of the law: : From the formula just given, we at once get: : where the ''a'' is used in such a sense that (''x'' → ''y'') → ''a'' means that from (''x'' → ''y'') every proposition follows. With that understanding, the formula states the principle of excluded middle, that from the falsity of the denial of ''x'' follows the truth of ''x''. (Peirce, the ''Collected Papers'' 3.384). Warning: ((''x''→''y'')→''a'')→''x'' is ''not'' a tautology. However, 'a''→''x''�� (''x''→''y'')→''a'')→''x''is a tautology.


Other proofs

Here is a simple proof of Peirce's law assuming double negation (\neg \neg P \iff P) and deriving the standard disjunction from an implication ((P \rightarrow Q) \Rightarrow (\neg P \vee Q)): \begin (p \rightarrow q) \rightarrow p \\ \neg (p \rightarrow q) \lor p \\ \neg (\neg p \lor q) \lor p \\ (p \land \neg q) \lor p \\ p \lor p \\ p. \\ \end


Using Peirce's law with the deduction theorem

Peirce's law allows one to enhance the technique of using the
deduction theorem In mathematical logic, a deduction theorem is a metatheorem that justifies doing conditional proofs—to prove an implication ''A'' → ''B'', assume ''A'' as an hypothesis and then proceed to derive ''B''—in systems that do not have an ...
to prove theorems. Suppose one is given a set of premises Γ and one wants to deduce a proposition ''Z'' from them. With Peirce's law, one can add (at no cost) additional premises of the form ''Z''→''P'' to Γ. For example, suppose we are given ''P''→''Z'' and (''P''→''Q'')→''Z'' and we wish to deduce ''Z'' so that we can use the deduction theorem to conclude that (''P''→''Z'')→(((''P''→''Q'')→''Z'')→''Z'') is a theorem. Then we can add another premise ''Z''→''Q''. From that and ''P''→''Z'', we get ''P''→''Q''. Then we apply modus ponens with (''P''→''Q'')→''Z'' as the major premise to get ''Z''. Applying the deduction theorem, we get that (''Z''→''Q'')→''Z'' follows from the original premises. Then we use Peirce's law in the form ((''Z''→''Q'')→''Z'')→''Z'' and modus ponens to derive ''Z'' from the original premises. Then we can finish off proving the theorem as we originally intended.


Completeness of the implicational propositional calculus

One reason that Peirce's law is important is that it can substitute for the law of excluded middle in the logic which only uses implication. The sentences which can be deduced from the axiom schemas: * ''P''→(''Q''→''P'') * (''P''→(''Q''→''R''))→((''P''→''Q'')→(''P''→''R'')) * ((''P''→''Q'')→''P'')→''P'' * from ''P'' and ''P''→''Q'' infer ''Q'' (where ''P'',''Q'',''R'' contain only "→" as a connective) are all the tautologies which use only "→" as a connective.


Failure in non-classical models of intuitionistic logic

Since Pierces law implies the law of the excluded middle, it must always fail in non-classical intuitionistic logics. A simple explicit counterexample is that of Gödel many valued logics, which are a
fuzzy logic Fuzzy logic is a form of many-valued logic in which the truth value of variables may be any real number between 0 and 1. It is employed to handle the concept of partial truth, where the truth value may range between completely true and complete ...
where truth values are real numbers between 0 and 1, with material implication defined by: : \begin u \mathrel v &= \begin 1, & \textu \leq v \\ v, & \textu > v \end \end and where Pierces law as a formula can be simplified to: : \begin ((u \mathrel v) \mathrel u) \mathrel u &= \begin 1, & \textu \leq v \\ u, & \textu > v \end \end{align} where it always being true would be equivalent to the statement that u > v implies u = 1, which is true only if 0 and 1 are the only allowed values. At the same time however, the expression cannot ever be equal to the bottom truth value of the logic and its double negation is always true.


See also

*
Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography This Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography consolidates numerous references to the writings of Charles Sanders Peirce, including letters, manuscripts, publications, and . For an extensive chronological list of Peirce's works (titled in English), se ...


Notes


Further reading

* Peirce, C.S., "On the Algebra of Logic: A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation", ''American Journal of Mathematics'' 7, 180–202 (1885). Reprinted, the ''Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce'' 3.359–403 and the ''Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition'' 5, 162–190. * Peirce, C.S., ''Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce'', Vols. 1–6,
Charles Hartshorne Charles Hartshorne (; June 5, 1897 – October 9, 2000) was an American philosopher who concentrated primarily on the philosophy of religion and metaphysics, but also contributed to ornithology. He developed the neoclassical idea of God and ...
and Paul Weiss (eds.), Vols. 7–8,
Arthur W. Burks Arthur Walter Burks (October 13, 1915 – May 14, 2008) was an American mathematician who worked in the 1940s as a senior engineer on the project that contributed to the design of the ENIAC, the first general-purpose electronic digital computer. ...
(ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935, 1958. Mathematical logic Charles Sanders Peirce Theorems in propositional logic Intuitionism