HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The sorites paradox (; sometimes known as the paradox of the heap) is a paradox that results from vague predicates. A typical formulation involves a heap of
sand Sand is a granular material composed of finely divided mineral particles. Sand has various compositions but is defined by its grain size. Sand grains are smaller than gravel and coarser than silt. Sand can also refer to a textural class ...
, from which grains are removed individually. With the assumption that removing a single grain does not cause a heap to become a non-heap, the paradox is to consider what happens when the process is repeated enough times that only one grain remains: is it still a heap? If not, when did it change from a heap to a non-heap?


The original formulation and variations


Paradox of the heap

The word ''sorites'' ('' grc-gre, σωρείτης'') derives from the Greek word for 'heap' ('' grc-gre, σωρός''). The paradox is so named because of its original characterization, attributed to Eubulides of Miletus. The paradox is as follows: consider a heap of sand from which
grain A grain is a small, hard, dry fruit ( caryopsis) – with or without an attached hull layer – harvested for human or animal consumption. A grain crop is a grain-producing plant. The two main types of commercial grain crops are cereals and legum ...
s are removed individually. One might construct the argument, using premises, as follows: :'' grains of sand is a heap of sand'' (Premise 1) :''A heap of sand minus one grain is still a heap.'' (Premise 2) Repeated applications of Premise 2 (each time starting with one fewer grain) eventually forces one to accept the conclusion that a heap may be composed of just one grain of sand. Read (1995) observes that "the argument is itself a heap, or sorites, of steps of ''
modus ponens In propositional logic, ''modus ponens'' (; MP), also known as ''modus ponendo ponens'' (Latin for "method of putting by placing") or implication elimination or affirming the antecedent, is a deductive argument form and rule of inference ...
''":Read, Stephen (1995). ''Thinking About Logic'', p.174. Oxford. . :'' grains is a heap.'' :''If grains is a heap then grains is a heap.'' :''So grains is a heap.'' :''If grains is a heap then grains is a heap.'' :''So grains is a heap.'' :''If ...'' :''... So grain is a heap.''


Variations

Another formulation is to start with a grain of sand, which is clearly not a heap, and then assume that adding a single grain of sand to something that is not a heap does not cause it to become a heap. Inductively, this process can be repeated as much as one wants without ever constructing a heap. A more natural formulation of this variant is to assume a set of colored chips exists such that two adjacent chips vary in color too little for human eyesight to be able to distinguish between them. Then by induction on this premise, humans would not be able to distinguish between any colors. The removal of one drop from the ocean, will not make it 'not an ocean' (it is still an ocean), but since the volume of water in the ocean is finite, eventually, after enough removals, even a litre of water left is still an ocean. This paradox can be reconstructed for a variety of predicates, for example, with "tall", "rich", "old", "blue", "bald", and so on.
Bertrand Russell Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British mathematician, philosopher, logician, and public intellectual. He had a considerable influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, linguistics, a ...
argued that all of natural language, even logical connectives, is vague; moreover, representations of propositions are vague.


Continuum fallacy

The continuum fallacy (also known as the fallacy of the beard, line-drawing fallacy, or decision-point fallacy) is an
informal fallacy Informal fallacies are a type of incorrect argument in natural language. The source of the error is not just due to the ''form'' of the argument, as is the case for formal fallacies, but can also be due to their ''content'' and ''context''. Fall ...
related to the sorites paradox. Both fallacies cause one to erroneously reject a vague claim simply because it is not as precise as one would like it to be. Vagueness alone does not necessarily imply invalidity. The fallacy is the argument that two states or conditions cannot be considered distinct (or do not
exist eXist-db (or eXist for short) is an open source software project for NoSQL databases built on XML technology. It is classified as both a NoSQL document-oriented database system and a native XML database (and it provides support for XML, JSON, ...
at all) because between them there exists a continuum of states. Strictly, the sorites paradox refers to situations where there are many ''discrete'' states (classically between 1 and 1,000,000 grains of sand, hence 1,000,000 possible states), while the continuum fallacy refers to situations where there is (or appears to be) a ''continuum'' of states, such as temperature. Whether any continua exist in the physical world is the classic question of
atomism Atomism (from Greek , ''atomon'', i.e. "uncuttable, indivisible") is a natural philosophy proposing that the physical universe is composed of fundamental indivisible components known as atoms. References to the concept of atomism and its atom ...
, and while both Newtonian physics and
quantum physics Quantum mechanics is a fundamental theory in physics that provides a description of the physical properties of nature at the scale of atoms and subatomic particles. It is the foundation of all quantum physics including quantum chemistry, qua ...
model the world as continuous, there are some proposals in
quantum gravity Quantum gravity (QG) is a field of theoretical physics that seeks to describe gravity according to the principles of quantum mechanics; it deals with environments in which neither gravitational nor quantum effects can be ignored, such as in the vi ...
, such as
loop quantum gravity Loop quantum gravity (LQG) is a theory of quantum gravity, which aims to merge quantum mechanics and general relativity, incorporating matter of the Standard Model into the framework established for the pure quantum gravity case. It is an attem ...
, that suggest that notions of continuous length do not apply at the Planck length, and thus what appear to be continua may simply be as-yet undistinguishable discrete states. For the purpose of the continuum fallacy, one assumes that there is in fact a continuum, though this is generally a minor distinction: in general, any argument against the sorites paradox can also be used against the continuum fallacy. One argument against the fallacy is based on the simple counterexample: there do exist bald people and people who are not bald. Another argument is that for each degree of change in states, the degree of the condition changes slightly, and these slight changes build up to shift the state from one category to another. For example, perhaps the addition of a grain of rice causes the total group of rice to be "slightly more" of a heap, and enough slight changes will certify the group's heap status – see
fuzzy logic Fuzzy logic is a form of many-valued logic in which the truth value of variables may be any real number between 0 and 1. It is employed to handle the concept of partial truth, where the truth value may range between completely true and completel ...
.


Proposed resolutions


Denying the existence of heaps

One may object to the first premise by denying that grains of sand makes a heap. But is just an arbitrary large number, and the argument will apply with any such number. So the response must deny outright that there are such things as heaps.
Peter Unger Peter K. Unger (; born April 25, 1942) is a contemporary American philosopher and professor in the Department of Philosophy at New York University. His main interests lie in the fields of metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and the philos ...
defends this solution.


Setting a fixed boundary

A common first response to the paradox is to term any set of grains that has more than a certain number of grains in it a heap. If one were to define the "fixed boundary" at grains then one would claim that for fewer than , it is not a heap; for or more, then it is a heap. Collins argues that such solutions are unsatisfactory as there seems little significance to the difference between grains and grains. The boundary, wherever it may be set, remains arbitrary, and so its precision is misleading. It is objectionable on both philosophical and linguistic grounds: the former on account of its arbitrariness and the latter on the ground that it is simply not how natural language is used.


Unknowable boundaries (or epistemicism)

Timothy Williamson Timothy Williamson (born 1955) is a British philosopher whose main research interests are in philosophical logic, philosophy of language, epistemology and metaphysics. He is the Wykeham Professor of Logic at the University of Oxford, and fe ...
and Roy Sorensen claim that there are fixed boundaries but that they are necessarily unknowable.


Supervaluationism

Supervaluationism In philosophical logic, supervaluationism is a semantics for dealing with irreferential singular terms and vagueness. It allows one to apply the tautologies of propositional logic in cases where truth values are undefined. According to super ...
is a method for dealing with irreferential singular terms and
vagueness In linguistics and philosophy, a vague predicate is one which gives rise to borderline cases. For example, the English adjective "tall" is vague since it is not clearly true or false for someone of middling height. By contrast, the word "prime" is ...
. It allows one to retain the usual tautological laws even when dealing with undefined truth values. As an example of a proposition about an irreferential singular term, consider the sentence "''
Pegasus Pegasus ( grc-gre, Πήγασος, Pḗgasos; la, Pegasus, Pegasos) is one of the best known creatures in Greek mythology. He is a winged divine stallion usually depicted as pure white in color. He was sired by Poseidon, in his role as hor ...
likes
licorice Liquorice (British English) or licorice ( American English) ( ; also ) is the common name of ''Glycyrrhiza glabra'', a flowering plant of the bean family Fabaceae, from the root of which a sweet, aromatic flavouring can be extracted. The l ...
''". Since the name "''Pegasus''" fails to refer, no
truth value In logic and mathematics, a truth value, sometimes called a logical value, is a value indicating the relation of a proposition to truth, which in classical logic has only two possible values ('' true'' or '' false''). Computing In some pro ...
can be assigned to the sentence; there is nothing in the myth that would justify any such assignment. However, there are some statements about "''Pegasus''" which have definite truth values nevertheless, such as "''Pegasus likes licorice or Pegasus doesn't like licorice''". This sentence is an instance of the tautology "p \vee \neg p", i.e. the valid schema "''p or not-p''". According to supervaluationism, it should be true regardless of whether or not its components have a truth value. By admitting sentences without defined truth values, supervaluationism avoids adjacent cases such that ''n'' grains of sand is a heap of sand, but ''n''-1 grains is not; for example, "'' grains of sand is a heap''" may be considered a border case having no defined truth value. Nevertheless, supervaluationism is able to handle a sentence like "'' grains of sand is a heap, or grains of sand is not a heap''" as a tautology, i.e. to assign it the value ''true''.


Mathematical explanation

Let v be a classical valuation defined on every
atomic sentence In logic and analytic philosophy, an atomic sentence is a type of declarative sentence which is either true or false (may also be referred to as a proposition, statement or truthbearer) and which cannot be broken down into other simpler sentences ...
of the language L, and let At(x) be the number of distinct atomic sentences in x. Then for every sentence x, at most 2^ distinct classical valuations can exist. A supervaluation V is a function from sentences to truth values such that, a sentence x is super-true (i.e. V(x) = \text) if and only if v(x) = \text for every classical valuation v; likewise for super-false. Otherwise, V(x) is undefined—i.e. exactly when there are two classical valuations v and v' such that v(x)=\text and v'(x) = \text. For example, let L \; p be the formal translation of "''Pegasus likes licorice''". Then there are exactly two classical valuations v and v' on L \; p, viz. v(L \; p) = \text and v'(L \; p) = \text. So L \; p is neither super-true nor super-false. However, the tautology L \; p \lor \lnot L \; p is evaluated to \text by every classical valuation; it is hence super-true. Similarly, the formalization of the above heap proposition H \; 1000 is neither super-true nor super-false, but H \; 1000 \lor \lnot H \; 1000 is super-true.


Truth gaps, gluts, and multi-valued logics

Another method is to use a multi-valued logic. In this context, the problem is with the principle of bivalence: the sand is either a heap or is not a heap, without any shades of gray. Instead of two logical states, ''heap'' and ''not-heap'', a three value system can be used, for example ''heap'', ''indeterminate'' and ''not-heap''. A response to this proposed solution is that three valued systems do not truly resolve the paradox as there is still a dividing line between ''heap'' and ''indeterminate'' and also between ''indeterminate'' and ''not-heap''. The third truth-value can be understood either as a ''truth-value gap'' or as a ''truth-value glut''. Alternatively,
fuzzy logic Fuzzy logic is a form of many-valued logic in which the truth value of variables may be any real number between 0 and 1. It is employed to handle the concept of partial truth, where the truth value may range between completely true and completel ...
offers a continuous spectrum of logical states represented in the
unit interval In mathematics, the unit interval is the closed interval , that is, the set of all real numbers that are greater than or equal to 0 and less than or equal to 1. It is often denoted ' (capital letter ). In addition to its role in real analysis ...
of real numbers ,1��it is a many-valued logic with infinitely-many truth-values, and thus the sand transitions gradually from "definitely heap" to "definitely not heap", with shades in the intermediate region. Fuzzy hedges are used to divide the continuum into regions corresponding to classes like ''definitely heap'', ''mostly heap'', ''partly heap'', ''slightly heap'', and ''not heap''. Though the problem remains of where these borders occur; e.g. at what number of grains sand starts being 'definitely' a heap.


Hysteresis

Another method, introduced by Raffman, is to use
hysteresis Hysteresis is the dependence of the state of a system on its history. For example, a magnet may have more than one possible magnetic moment in a given magnetic field, depending on how the field changed in the past. Plots of a single component of ...
, that is, knowledge of what the collection of sand started as. Equivalent amounts of sand may be termed heaps or not based on how they got there. If a large heap (indisputably described as a heap) is diminished slowly, it preserves its "heap status" to a point, even as the actual amount of sand is reduced to a smaller number of grains. For example, grains is a pile and grains is a heap. There will be an overlap for these states. So if one is reducing it from a heap to a pile, it is a heap going down until . At that point, one would stop calling it a heap and start calling it a pile. But if one replaces one grain, it would not instantly turn back into a heap. When going up it would remain a pile until grains. The numbers picked are arbitrary; the point is, that the same amount can be either a heap or a pile depending on what it was before the change. A common use of hysteresis would be the thermostat for air conditioning: the AC is set at 77 °F and it then cools the air to just below 77 °F, but does not activate again instantly when the air warms to 77.001 °F—it waits until almost 78 °F, to prevent instant change of state over and over again.


Group consensus

One can establish the meaning of the word "heap" by appealing to consensus. Williamson, in his epistemic solution to the paradox, assumes that the meaning of vague terms must be determined by group usage. The consensus method typically claims that a collection of grains is as much a "heap" as the proportion of people in a group who believe it to be so. In other words, the ''
probability Probability is the branch of mathematics concerning numerical descriptions of how likely an event is to occur, or how likely it is that a proposition is true. The probability of an event is a number between 0 and 1, where, roughly speaking, ...
'' that any collection is considered a heap is the
expected value In probability theory, the expected value (also called expectation, expectancy, mathematical expectation, mean, average, or first moment) is a generalization of the weighted average. Informally, the expected value is the arithmetic mean of a ...
of the distribution of the group's opinion. A group may decide that: *One grain of sand on its own is not a heap. *A large collection of grains of sand is a heap. Between the two extremes, individual members of the group may disagree with each other over whether any particular collection can be labelled a "heap". The collection can then not be definitively claimed to ''be'' a "heap" or "not a heap". This can be considered an appeal to descriptive linguistics rather than prescriptive linguistics, as it resolves the issue of definition based on how the population uses natural language. Indeed, if a precise prescriptive definition of "heap" is available then the group consensus will always be unanimous and the paradox does not occur.


Resolutions in utility theory

In the economics field of
utility theory As a topic of economics, utility is used to model worth or value. Its usage has evolved significantly over time. The term was introduced initially as a measure of pleasure or happiness as part of the theory of utilitarianism by moral philosopher ...
, the sorites paradox arises when a person's preferences patterns are investigated. As an example by Robert Duncan Luce, it is easy to find a person, say Peggy, who prefers in her coffee 3
gram The gram (originally gramme; SI unit symbol g) is a unit of mass in the International System of Units (SI) equal to one one thousandth of a kilogram. Originally defined as of 1795 as "the absolute weight of a volume of pure water equal to th ...
s (that is, 1
cube In geometry, a cube is a three-dimensional solid object bounded by six square faces, facets or sides, with three meeting at each vertex. Viewed from a corner it is a hexagon and its net is usually depicted as a cross. The cube is the only ...
) of sugar to 15 grams (5 cubes), however, she will usually be indifferent between 3.00 and 3.03 grams, as well as between 3.03 and 3.06 grams, and so on, as well as finally between 14.97 and 15.00 grams. Here: p.179 Two measures were taken by economists to avoid the sorites paradox in such a setting. *
Comparative general linguistics, the comparative is a syntactic construction that serves to express a comparison between two (or more) entities or groups of entities in quality or degree - see also comparison (grammar) for an overview of comparison, as well ...
, rather than positive, forms of properties are used. The above example deliberately does not make a statement like "Peggy likes a cup of coffee with 3 grams of sugar", or "Peggy does not like a cup of coffee with 15 grams of sugar". Instead, it states "Peggy likes a cup of coffee with 3 grams of sugar more than one with 15 grams of sugar". * Economists distinguish preference ("Peggy likes ... more than ...") from indifference ("Peggy likes ... as much as ... "), and do not consider the latter relation to be transitive. In the above example, abbreviating "a cup of coffee with x grams of sugar" by "''c''''x''", and "Peggy is indifferent between ''c''''x'' and ''c''''y''" as the facts and and ... and do not imply Several kinds of relations were introduced to describe preference and indifference without running into the sorites paradox. Luce defined semi-orders and investigated their mathematical properties;
Amartya Sen Amartya Kumar Sen (; born 3 November 1933) is an Indian economist and philosopher, who since 1972 has taught and worked in the United Kingdom and the United States. Sen has made contributions to welfare economics, social choice theory, economi ...
performed a similar task for quasitransitive relations. Abbreviating "Peggy likes ''c''''x'' more than ''c''''y''" as and abbreviating or by it is reasonable that the relation ">" is a semi-order while ≥ is quasitransitive. Conversely, from a given semi-order > the indifference relation ≈ can be reconstructed by defining if neither nor Similarly, from a given quasitransitive relation ≥ the indifference relation ≈ can be reconstructed by defining if both and These reconstructed ≈ relations are usually not transitive. The table to the right shows how the above color example can be modelled as a quasi-transitive relation ≥. Color differences overdone for readability. A color ''X'' is said to be more or equally red than a color ''Y'' if the table cell in row ''X'' and column ''Y'' is not empty. In that case, if it holds a "≈", then ''X'' and ''Y'' look indistinguishably equal, and if it holds a ">", then ''X'' looks clearly more red than ''Y''. The relation ≥ is the disjoint union of the symmetric relation ≈ and the transitive relation >. Using the transitivity of >, the knowledge of both > and > allows one to infer that > . However, since ≥ is not transitive, a "paradoxical" inference like " ≥ and ≥ , hence ≥ " is no longer possible. For the same reason, e.g. " ≈ and ≈ , hence ≈ " is no longer a valid inference. Similarly, to resolve the original heap variation of the paradox with this approach, the relation "''X'' grains are more a heap than ''Y'' grains" could be considered quasitransitive rather than transitive.


See also

*
Ambiguity Ambiguity is the type of meaning in which a phrase, statement or resolution is not explicitly defined, making several interpretations plausible. A common aspect of ambiguity is uncertainty. It is thus an attribute of any idea or statement ...
* Boiling frog * Closed concept * Fuzzy concept *
I know it when I see it The phrase "I know it when I see it" is a colloquial expression by which a speaker attempts to categorize an observable fact or event, although the category is subjective or lacks clearly defined parameters. The phrase was used in 1964 by United St ...
*
Imprecise language Imprecise language, informal spoken language, or everyday language is less precise than any more formal or academic languages. Language might be said to be imprecise because it exhibits one or more of the following features: * ambiguity – when ...
* List of fallacies * Loki's Wager * Ring species *
Ship of Theseus The Ship of Theseus is a thought experiment about whether an object that has had all of its original components replaced remains the same object. According to legend, Theseus, the mythical Greek founder-king of Athens, had rescued the children o ...
* Slippery slope * Straw that broke the camel's back


References


Bibliography

* * * * * * * * * * *; Sect.3


External links

* by Dominic Hyde. * Sandra LaFave
Open and Closed Concepts and the Continuum Fallacy
{{DEFAULTSORT:Sorites Paradox Logical paradoxes Semantics Ambiguity