HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In algebraic geometry, a proper morphism between schemes is an analog of a proper map between complex analytic spaces. Some authors call a proper variety over a field ''k'' a complete variety. For example, every projective variety over a field ''k'' is proper over ''k''. A scheme ''X'' of finite type over the
complex numbers In mathematics, a complex number is an element of a number system that extends the real numbers with a specific element denoted , called the imaginary unit and satisfying the equation i^= -1; every complex number can be expressed in the for ...
(for example, a variety) is proper over C if and only if the space ''X''(C) of complex points with the classical (Euclidean) topology is compact and Hausdorff. A closed immersion is proper. A morphism is
finite Finite is the opposite of infinite. It may refer to: * Finite number (disambiguation) * Finite set, a set whose cardinality (number of elements) is some natural number * Finite verb Traditionally, a finite verb (from la, fīnītus, past partici ...
if and only if it is proper and quasi-finite.


Definition

A morphism ''f'': ''X'' → ''Y'' of schemes is called universally closed if for every scheme ''Z'' with a morphism ''Z'' → ''Y'', the projection from the
fiber product In category theory, a branch of mathematics, a pullback (also called a fiber product, fibre product, fibered product or Cartesian square) is the limit of a diagram consisting of two morphisms and with a common codomain. The pullback is ofte ...
:X \times_Y Z \to Z is a closed map of the underlying
topological space In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a geometrical space in which closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric distance. More specifically, a topological space is a set whose elements are called po ...
s. A morphism of schemes is called proper if it is separated, of finite type, and universally closed ( GAII, 5.4.

. One also says that ''X'' is proper over ''Y''. In particular, a variety ''X'' over a field ''k'' is said to be proper over ''k'' if the morphism ''X'' → Spec(''k'') is proper.


Examples

For any natural number ''n'', projective space P''n'' over a commutative ring ''R'' is proper over ''R''. Projective morphisms are proper, but not all proper morphisms are projective. For example, there is a smooth proper complex variety of dimension 3 which is not projective over C. Affine varieties of positive dimension over a field ''k'' are never proper over ''k''. More generally, a proper affine morphism of schemes must be finite. For example, it is not hard to see that the affine line ''A''1 over a field ''k'' is not proper over ''k'', because the morphism ''A''1 → Spec(''k'') is not universally closed. Indeed, the pulled-back morphism :\mathbb^1 \times_k \mathbb^1 \to \mathbb^1 (given by (''x'',''y'') ↦ ''y'') is not closed, because the image of the closed subset ''xy'' = 1 in ''A''1 × ''A''1 = ''A''2 is ''A''1 − 0, which is not closed in ''A''1.


Properties and characterizations of proper morphisms

In the following, let ''f'': ''X'' → ''Y'' be a morphism of schemes. * The composition of two proper morphisms is proper. * Any base change of a proper morphism ''f'': ''X'' → ''Y'' is proper. That is, if ''g'': Z → ''Y'' is any morphism of schemes, then the resulting morphism ''X'' ×''Y'' ''Z'' → ''Z'' is proper. * Properness is a local property on the base (in the Zariski topology). That is, if ''Y'' is covered by some open subschemes ''Yi'' and the restriction of ''f'' to all ''f−1(Yi)'' is proper, then so is ''f''. * More strongly, properness is local on the base in the fpqc topology. For example, if ''X'' is a scheme over a field ''k'' and ''E'' is a field extension of ''k'', then ''X'' is proper over ''k'' if and only if the base change ''X''''E'' is proper over ''E''. * Closed immersions are proper. * More generally, finite morphisms are proper. This is a consequence of the going up theorem. * By Deligne, a morphism of schemes is finite if and only if it is proper and quasi-finite. This had been shown by Grothendieck if the morphism ''f'': ''X'' → ''Y'' is locally of finite presentation, which follows from the other assumptions if ''Y'' is noetherian. * For ''X'' proper over a scheme ''S'', and ''Y'' separated over ''S'', the image of any morphism ''X'' → ''Y'' over ''S'' is a closed subset of ''Y''. This is analogous to the theorem in topology that the image of a continuous map from a compact space to a Hausdorff space is a closed subset. * The
Stein factorization In algebraic geometry, the Stein factorization, introduced by for the case of complex spaces, states that a proper morphism can be factorized as a composition of a finite mapping and a proper morphism with connected fibers. Roughly speaking, Stein ...
theorem states that any proper morphism to a locally noetherian scheme can be factored as ''X'' → ''Z'' → ''Y'', where ''X'' → ''Z'' is proper, surjective, and has geometrically connected fibers, and ''Z'' → ''Y'' is finite. * Chow's lemma says that proper morphisms are closely related to projective morphisms. One version is: if ''X'' is proper over a quasi-compact scheme ''Y'' and ''X'' has only finitely many irreducible components (which is automatic for ''Y'' noetherian), then there is a projective surjective morphism ''g'': ''W'' → ''X'' such that ''W'' is projective over ''Y''. Moreover, one can arrange that ''g'' is an isomorphism over a dense open subset ''U'' of ''X'', and that ''g''−1(''U'') is dense in ''W''. One can also arrange that ''W'' is integral if ''X'' is integral. *
Nagata's compactification theorem In algebraic geometry, Nagata's compactification theorem, introduced by , implies that every abstract variety can be embedded in a complete variety, and more generally shows that a Glossary of scheme theory#separated, separated and Finite morphism#M ...
, as generalized by Deligne, says that a separated morphism of finite type between quasi-compact and quasi-separated schemes factors as an open immersion followed by a proper morphism. * Proper morphisms between locally noetherian schemes preserve coherent sheaves, in the sense that the
higher direct image In mathematics, the direct image functor is a construction in sheaf theory that generalizes the global sections functor to the relative case. It is of fundamental importance in topology and algebraic geometry. Given a sheaf ''F'' defined on a to ...
s ''Rif''(''F'') (in particular the direct image ''f''(''F'')) of a
coherent sheaf In mathematics, especially in algebraic geometry and the theory of complex manifolds, coherent sheaves are a class of sheaves closely linked to the geometric properties of the underlying space. The definition of coherent sheaves is made with ref ...
''F'' are coherent (EGA III, 3.2.1). (Analogously, for a proper map between complex analytic spaces, Grauert and Remmert showed that the higher direct images preserve coherent analytic sheaves.) As a very special case: the ring of regular functions on a proper scheme ''X'' over a field ''k'' has finite dimension as a ''k''-vector space. By contrast, the ring of regular functions on the affine line over ''k'' is the polynomial ring ''k'' 'x'' which does not have finite dimension as a ''k''-vector space. *There is also a slightly stronger statement of this: let f\colon X \to S be a morphism of finite type, ''S'' locally noetherian and F a \mathcal_X-module. If the support of ''F'' is proper over ''S'', then for each i \ge 0 the
higher direct image In mathematics, the direct image functor is a construction in sheaf theory that generalizes the global sections functor to the relative case. It is of fundamental importance in topology and algebraic geometry. Given a sheaf ''F'' defined on a to ...
R^i f_* F is coherent. *For a scheme ''X'' of finite type over the complex numbers, the set ''X''(C) of complex points is a complex analytic space, using the classical (Euclidean) topology. For ''X'' and ''Y'' separated and of finite type over C, a morphism ''f'': ''X'' → ''Y'' over C is proper if and only if the continuous map ''f'': ''X''(C) → ''Y''(C) is proper in the sense that the inverse image of every compact set is compact. * If ''f'': ''X''→''Y'' and ''g'': ''Y''→''Z'' are such that ''gf'' is proper and ''g'' is separated, then ''f'' is proper. This can for example be easily proven using the following criterion.


Valuative criterion of properness

There is a very intuitive criterion for properness which goes back to
Chevalley Claude Chevalley (; 11 February 1909 – 28 June 1984) was a French mathematician who made important contributions to number theory, algebraic geometry, class field theory, finite group theory and the theory of algebraic groups. He was a foundin ...
. It is commonly called the valuative criterion of properness. Let ''f'': ''X'' → ''Y'' be a morphism of finite type of noetherian schemes. Then ''f'' is proper if and only if for all
discrete valuation ring In abstract algebra, a discrete valuation ring (DVR) is a principal ideal domain (PID) with exactly one non-zero maximal ideal. This means a DVR is an integral domain ''R'' which satisfies any one of the following equivalent conditions: # ''R' ...
s ''R'' with fraction field ''K'' and for any ''K''-valued point ''x'' ∈ ''X''(''K'') that maps to a point ''f''(''x'') that is defined over ''R'', there is a unique lift of ''x'' to \overline \in X(R). (EGA II, 7.3.8). More generally, a quasi-separated morphism ''f'': ''X'' → ''Y'' of finite type (note: finite type includes quasi-compact) of *any* schemes ''X'', ''Y'' is proper if and only if for all
valuation ring In abstract algebra, a valuation ring is an integral domain ''D'' such that for every element ''x'' of its field of fractions ''F'', at least one of ''x'' or ''x''−1 belongs to ''D''. Given a field ''F'', if ''D'' is a subring of ''F'' such ...
s ''R'' with fraction field ''K'' and for any ''K''-valued point ''x'' ∈ ''X''(''K'') that maps to a point ''f''(''x'') that is defined over ''R'', there is a unique lift of ''x'' to \overline \in X(R). (Stacks project Tags 01KF and 01KY). Noting that ''Spec K'' is the generic point of ''Spec R'' and discrete valuation rings are precisely the
regular The term regular can mean normal or in accordance with rules. It may refer to: People * Moses Regular (born 1971), America football player Arts, entertainment, and media Music * "Regular" (Badfinger song) * Regular tunings of stringed instrum ...
local one-dimensional rings, one may rephrase the criterion: given a regular curve on ''Y'' (corresponding to the morphism ''s'': Spec ''R'' → ''Y'') and given a lift of the generic point of this curve to ''X'', ''f'' is proper if and only if there is exactly one way to complete the curve. Similarly, ''f'' is separated if and only if in every such diagram, there is at most one lift \overline \in X(R). For example, given the valuative criterion, it becomes easy to check that projective space P''n'' is proper over a field (or even over Z). One simply observes that for a discrete valuation ring ''R'' with fraction field ''K'', every ''K''-point 'x''0,...,''x''''n''of projective space comes from an ''R''-point, by scaling the coordinates so that all lie in ''R'' and at least one is a unit in ''R''.


Geometric interpretation with disks

One of the motivating examples for the valuative criterion of properness is the interpretation of \text(\mathbb t) as an infinitesimal disk, or complex-analytically, as the disk \Delta = \. This comes from the fact that every power series
f(t) = \sum_^\infty a_nt^n
converges in some disk of radius r around the origin. Then, using a change of coordinates, this can be expressed as a power series on the unit disk. Then, if we invert t, this is the ring \mathbb t ^= \mathbb((t)) which are the power series which may have a pole at the origin. This is represented topologically as the open disk \Delta^* = \ with the origin removed. For a morphism of schemes over \text(\mathbb), this is given by the commutative diagram
\begin \Delta^* & \to & X \\ \downarrow & & \downarrow \\ \Delta & \to & Y \end
Then, the valuative criterion for properness would be a filling in of the point 0 \in \Delta in the image of \Delta^*.


Example

It's instructive to look at a counter-example to see why the valuative criterion of properness should hold on spaces analogous to closed compact manifolds. If we take X = \mathbb^1 - \ and Y = \text(\mathbb), then a morphism \text(\mathbb((t))) \to X factors through an affine chart of X, reducing the diagram to
\begin \text(\mathbb((t))) & \to & \text(\mathbb ,t^ \\ \downarrow & & \downarrow \\ \text(\mathbb t) & \to & \text(\mathbb) \end
where \text(\mathbb ,t^ = \mathbb^1 - \ is the chart centered around \ on X. This gives the commutative diagram of commutative algebras
\begin \mathbb((t)) & \leftarrow & \mathbb ,t^\\ \uparrow & & \uparrow \\ \mathbb t & \leftarrow & \mathbb \end
Then, a lifting of the diagram of schemes, \text(\mathbb t) \to \text(\mathbb ,t^, would imply there is a morphism \mathbb ,t^\to \mathbb t sending t \mapsto t from the commutative diagram of algebras. This, of course, cannot happen. Therefore X is not proper over Y.


Geometric interpretation with curves

There is another similar example of the valuative criterion of properness which captures some of the intuition for why this theorem should hold. Consider a curve C and the complement of a point C-\. Then the valuative criterion for properness would read as a diagram
\begin C-\ & \rightarrow & X \\ \downarrow & & \downarrow \\ C & \rightarrow & Y \end
with a lifting of C \to X. Geometrically this means every curve in the scheme X can be completed to a compact curve. This bit of intuition aligns with what the scheme-theoretic interpretation of a morphism of topological spaces with compact fibers, that a sequence in one of the fibers must converge. Because this geometric situation is a problem locally, the diagram is replaced by looking at the local ring \mathcal_, which is a DVR, and its fraction field \text(\mathcal_). Then, the lifting problem then gives the commutative diagram
\begin \text(\text(\mathcal_) ) & \rightarrow & X \\ \downarrow & & \downarrow \\ \text(\mathcal_ ) & \rightarrow & Y \end
where the scheme \text(\text(\mathcal_)) represents a local disk around \mathfrak with the closed point \mathfrak removed.


Proper morphism of formal schemes

Let f\colon \mathfrak \to \mathfrak be a morphism between
locally noetherian formal scheme In mathematics, specifically in algebraic geometry, a formal scheme is a type of space which includes data about its surroundings. Unlike an ordinary scheme (mathematics), scheme, a formal scheme includes infinitesimal data that, in effect, points ...
s. We say ''f'' is proper or \mathfrak is proper over \mathfrak if (i) ''f'' is an
adic morphism In mathematics, specifically in algebraic geometry, a formal scheme is a type of space which includes data about its surroundings. Unlike an ordinary scheme, a formal scheme includes infinitesimal data that, in effect, points in a direction off of ...
(i.e., maps the ideal of definition to the ideal of definition) and (ii) the induced map f_0\colon X_0 \to S_0 is proper, where X_0 = (\mathfrak, \mathcal_\mathfrak/I), S_0 = (\mathfrak, \mathcal_\mathfrak/K), I = f^*(K) \mathcal_\mathfrak and ''K'' is the ideal of definition of \mathfrak. The definition is independent of the choice of ''K''. For example, if ''g'': ''Y'' → ''Z'' is a proper morphism of locally noetherian schemes, ''Z''0 is a closed subset of ''Z'', and ''Y''0 is a closed subset of ''Y'' such that ''g''(''Y''0) ⊂ ''Z''0, then the morphism \widehat\colon Y_ \to Z_ on formal completions is a proper morphism of formal schemes. Grothendieck proved the coherence theorem in this setting. Namely, let f\colon \mathfrak \to \mathfrak be a proper morphism of locally noetherian formal schemes. If ''F'' is a coherent sheaf on \mathfrak, then the higher direct images R^i f_* F are coherent.Grothendieck, EGA III, Part 1, Théorème 3.4.2.


See also

*
Proper base change theorem In mathematics, the base change theorems relate the direct image and the inverse image of sheaves. More precisely, they are about the base change map, given by the following natural transformation of sheaves: :g^*(R^r f_* \mathcal) \to R^r f'_ ...
*
Stein factorization In algebraic geometry, the Stein factorization, introduced by for the case of complex spaces, states that a proper morphism can be factorized as a composition of a finite mapping and a proper morphism with connected fibers. Roughly speaking, Stein ...


References

* *, section 5.3. (definition of properness), section 7.3. (valuative criterion of properness) * *, section 15.7. (generalizations of valuative criteria to not necessarily noetherian schemes) * * *


External links

* *{{Citation , author1=The Stacks Project Authors , title=The Stacks Project , url=http://stacks.math.columbia.edu/ Morphisms of schemes