Overspill
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
nonstandard analysis The history of calculus is fraught with philosophical debates about the meaning and logical validity of fluxions or infinitesimal numbers. The standard way to resolve these debates is to define the operations of calculus using (ε, δ)-definitio ...
, a branch of mathematics, overspill (referred to as ''overflow'' by Goldblatt (1998, p. 129)) is a widely used proof technique. It is based on the fact that the set of standard
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country"). Numbers used for counting are called ''cardinal ...
s N is not an internal subset of the internal set *N of
hypernatural In nonstandard analysis, a hyperinteger ''n'' is a hyperreal number that is equal to its own integer part. A hyperinteger may be either finite or infinite. A finite hyperinteger is an ordinary integer. An example of an infinite hyperinteger is ...
numbers. By applying the induction principle for the standard integers N and the
transfer principle In model theory, a transfer principle states that all statements of some language that are true for some structure are true for another structure. One of the first examples was the Lefschetz principle, which states that any sentence in the first- ...
we get the principle of internal induction: For any ''internal'' subset ''A'' of *N, if :# 1 is an element of ''A'', and :# for every element ''n'' of ''A'', ''n'' + 1 also belongs to ''A'', then :''A'' = *N If N were an internal set, then instantiating the internal induction principle with N, it would follow N = *N which is known not to be the case. The overspill principle has a number of useful consequences: * The set of standard hyperreals is not internal. * The set of bounded hyperreals is not internal. * The set of infinitesimal hyperreals is not internal. In particular: * If an internal set contains all infinitesimal non-negative hyperreals, it contains a positive ''non-infinitesimal'' (or ''appreciable'') hyperreal. * If an internal set contains N it contains an unlimited (infinite) element of *N.


Example

These facts can be used to prove the equivalence of the following two conditions for an ''internal'' hyperreal-valued function ƒ defined on *R. : \forall \epsilon\in \mathbb^+, \exists \delta \in\mathbb^+, , h, \leq \delta \implies , f(x+h) - f(x), \leq \varepsilon and : \forall h \cong 0, \ , f(x+h) - f(x), \cong 0 The proof that the second fact implies the first uses overspill, since given a non-infinitesimal positive ''ε'', : \forall \mbox \delta \cong 0, \ (, h, \leq \delta \implies , f(x+h) - f(x), < \varepsilon). Applying overspill, we obtain a positive appreciable δ with the requisite properties. These equivalent conditions express the property known in nonstandard analysis as S-continuity (or
microcontinuity In nonstandard analysis, a discipline within classical mathematics, microcontinuity (or ''S''-continuity) of an internal function ''f'' at a point ''a'' is defined as follows: :for all ''x'' infinitely close to ''a'', the value ''f''(''x'') is in ...
) of ƒ at ''x''. S-continuity is referred to as an external property. The first definition is external because it involves quantification over standard values only. The second definition is external because it involves the external relation of being infinitesimal.


References

*
Robert Goldblatt __notoc__ Robert Ian Goldblatt (born 1949) is a mathematical logician who is Emeritus Professor in the School of Mathematics and Statistics at Victoria University, Wellington, New Zealand. His most popular books are ''Logics of Time and Computatio ...
(1998). ''Lectures on the hyperreals. An introduction to nonstandard analysis.'' Springer. {{Infinitesimals Nonstandard analysis