Ordinal Preferences
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
economics Economics () is the social science that studies the Production (economics), production, distribution (economics), distribution, and Consumption (economics), consumption of goods and services. Economics focuses on the behaviour and intera ...
, an ordinal utility function is a function representing the
preferences In psychology, economics and philosophy, preference is a technical term usually used in relation to choosing between alternatives. For example, someone prefers A over B if they would rather choose A than B. Preferences are central to decision theo ...
of an agent on an
ordinal scale Ordinal data is a categorical, statistical data type where the variables have natural, ordered categories and the distances between the categories are not known. These data exist on an ordinal scale, one of four levels of measurement described b ...
. Ordinal
utility theory As a topic of economics, utility is used to model worth or value. Its usage has evolved significantly over time. The term was introduced initially as a measure of pleasure or happiness as part of the theory of utilitarianism by moral philosopher ...
claims that it is only meaningful to ask which option is better than the other, but it is meaningless to ask ''how much'' better it is or how good it is. All of the theory of consumer decision-making under conditions of
certainty Certainty (also known as epistemic certainty or objective certainty) is the epistemic property of beliefs which a person has no rational grounds for doubting. One standard way of defining epistemic certainty is that a belief is certain if and ...
can be, and typically is, expressed in terms of ordinal utility. For example, suppose George tells us that "I prefer A to B and B to C". George's preferences can be represented by a function ''u'' such that: :u(A)=9, u(B)=8, u(C)=1 But critics of
cardinal utility In economics, a cardinal utility function or scale is a utility index that preserves preference orderings uniquely up to positive affine transformations. Two utility indices are related by an affine transformation if for the value u(x_i) of one ind ...
claim the only meaningful message of this function is the order u(A)>u(B)>u(C); the actual numbers are meaningless. Hence, George's preferences can also be represented by the following function ''v'': :v(A)=9, v(B)=2, v(C)=1 The functions ''u'' and ''v'' are ordinally equivalent – they represent George's preferences equally well. Ordinal utility contrasts with
cardinal utility In economics, a cardinal utility function or scale is a utility index that preserves preference orderings uniquely up to positive affine transformations. Two utility indices are related by an affine transformation if for the value u(x_i) of one ind ...
theory: the latter assumes that the differences between preferences are also important. In ''u'' the difference between A and B is much smaller than between B and C, while in ''v'' the opposite is true. Hence, ''u'' and ''v'' are ''not'' cardinally equivalent. The ordinal utility concept was first introduced by Pareto in 1906.


Notation

Suppose the set of all states of the world is X and an agent has a preference relation on X. It is common to mark the weak preference relation by \preceq, so that A \preceq B reads "the agent wants B at least as much as A". The symbol \sim is used as a shorthand to the indifference relation: A\sim B \iff (A\preceq B \land B\preceq A), which reads "The agent is indifferent between B and A". The symbol \prec is used as a shorthand to the strong preference relation: A\prec B \iff (A\preceq B \land B\not\preceq A), which reads "The agent strictly prefers B to A". A function u: X \to \mathbb is said to ''represent'' the relation \preceq if: :A \preceq B \iff u(A) \leq u(B)


Related concepts


Indifference curve mappings

Instead of defining a numeric function, an agent's preference relation can be represented graphically by indifference curves. This is especially useful when there are two kinds of goods, ''x'' and ''y''. Then, each indifference curve shows a set of points (x,y) such that, if (x_1,y_1) and (x_2,y_2) are on the same curve, then (x_1,y_1) \sim (x_2,y_2). An example indifference curve is shown below: Each indifference curve is a set of points, each representing a combination of quantities of two goods or services, all of which combinations the consumer is equally satisfied with. The further a curve is from the origin, the greater is the level of utility. The slope of the curve (the negative of the
marginal rate of substitution In economics, the marginal rate of substitution (MRS) is the rate at which a consumer can give up some amount of one good in exchange for another good while maintaining the same level of utility. At equilibrium consumption levels (assuming no exte ...
of X for Y) at any point shows the rate at which the individual is willing to trade off good X against good Y maintaining the same level of utility. The curve is convex to the origin as shown assuming the consumer has a diminishing marginal rate of substitution. It can be shown that consumer analysis with indifference curves (an ordinal approach) gives the same results as that based on
cardinal utility In economics, a cardinal utility function or scale is a utility index that preserves preference orderings uniquely up to positive affine transformations. Two utility indices are related by an affine transformation if for the value u(x_i) of one ind ...
theory — i.e., consumers will consume at the point where the marginal rate of substitution between any two goods equals the ratio of the prices of those goods (the equi-marginal principle).


Revealed preference

Revealed preference theory Revealed preference theory, pioneered by economist Paul Anthony Samuelson in 1938, is a method of analyzing choices made by individuals, mostly used for comparing the influence of policies on consumer behavior. Revealed preference models assume t ...
addresses the problem of how to observe ordinal preference relations in the real world. The challenge of revealed preference theory lies in part in determining what goods bundles were foregone, on the basis of them being less liked, when individuals are observed choosing particular bundles of goods.


Necessary conditions for existence of ordinal utility function

Some conditions on \preceq are necessary to guarantee the existence of a representing function: * Transitivity: if A \preceq B and B \preceq C then A \preceq C. * Completeness: for all bundles A,B\in X: either A\preceq B or B\preceq A or both. ** Completeness also implies reflexivity: for every A\in X: A \preceq A. When these conditions are met and the set X is finite, it is easy to create a function u which represents \prec by just assigning an appropriate number to each element of X, as exemplified in the opening paragraph. The same is true when X is
countably infinite In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbers; ...
. Moreover, it is possible to inductively construct a representing utility function whose values are in the range (-1,1).Ariel Rubinstein, Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory
Lecture 2 – Utility
/ref> When X is infinite, these conditions are insufficient. For example,
lexicographic preferences In economics, lexicographic preferences or lexicographic orderings describe comparative preferences where an agent prefers any amount of one good (X) to any amount of another (Y). Specifically, if offered several bundles of goods, the agent will cho ...
are transitive and complete, but they cannot be represented by any utility function. The additional condition required is continuity.


Continuity

A preference relation is called ''continuous'' if, whenever B is preferred to A, small deviations from B or A will not reverse the ordering between them. Formally, a preference relation on a set X is called continuous if it satisfies one of the following equivalent conditions: # For every A\in X, the set \ is
topologically closed In topology, the closure of a subset of points in a topological space consists of all points in together with all limit points of . The closure of may equivalently be defined as the union of and its boundary, and also as the intersection of ...
in X\times X with the
product topology In topology and related areas of mathematics, a product space is the Cartesian product of a family of topological spaces equipped with a natural topology called the product topology. This topology differs from another, perhaps more natural-seemin ...
(this definition requires X to be a
topological space In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a geometrical space in which closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric distance. More specifically, a topological space is a set whose elements are called points ...
). # For every sequence (A_i,B_i), if for all ''i'' A_i\preceq B_i and A_i \to A and B_i \to B, then A\preceq B. # For every A,B\in X such that A\prec B, there exists a ball around A and a ball around B such that, for every a in the ball around A and every b in the ball around B, a\prec b (this definition requires X to be a
metric space In mathematics, a metric space is a set together with a notion of ''distance'' between its elements, usually called points. The distance is measured by a function called a metric or distance function. Metric spaces are the most general settin ...
). If a preference relation is represented by a continuous utility function, then it is clearly continuous. By the theorems of Debreu (1954), the opposite is also true: ::Every continuous complete preference relation can be represented by a continuous ordinal utility function. Note that the
lexicographic preferences In economics, lexicographic preferences or lexicographic orderings describe comparative preferences where an agent prefers any amount of one good (X) to any amount of another (Y). Specifically, if offered several bundles of goods, the agent will cho ...
are not continuous. For example, (5,0)\prec (5,1), but in every ball around (5,1) there are points with x<5 and these points are inferior to (5,0). This is in accordance with the fact, stated above, that these preferences cannot be represented by a utility function.


Uniqueness

For every utility function ''v'', there is a unique preference relation represented by ''v''. However, the opposite is not true: a preference relation may be represented by many different utility functions. The same preferences could be expressed as ''any'' utility function that is a monotonically increasing transformation of ''v''. E.g., if :v(A) \equiv f(v(A)) where f: \mathbb\to \mathbb is ''any'' monotonically increasing function, then the functions ''v'' and ''v'' give rise to identical indifference curve mappings. This equivalence is succinctly described in the following way: ::An ordinal utility function is ''unique up to increasing monotone transformation''. In contrast, a
cardinal utility In economics, a cardinal utility function or scale is a utility index that preserves preference orderings uniquely up to positive affine transformations. Two utility indices are related by an affine transformation if for the value u(x_i) of one ind ...
function is unique up to increasing
affine transformation In Euclidean geometry, an affine transformation or affinity (from the Latin, ''affinis'', "connected with") is a geometric transformation that preserves lines and parallelism, but not necessarily Euclidean distances and angles. More generally, ...
. Every affine transformation is monotone; hence, if two functions are cardinally equivalent they are also ordinally equivalent, but not vice versa.


Monotonicity

Suppose, from now on, that the set X is the set of all non-negative real two-dimensional vectors. So an element of X is a pair (x,y) that represents the amounts consumed from two products, e.g., apples and bananas. Then under certain circumstances a preference relation \preceq is represented by a utility function v(x,y). Suppose the preference relation is ''monotonically increasing'', which means that "more is always better": :x :y Then, both partial derivatives, if they exist, of ''v'' are positive. In short: ::''If a utility function represents a monotonically increasing preference relation, then the utility function is monotonically increasing.''


Marginal rate of substitution

Suppose a person has a bundle (x_0,y_0) and claims that he is indifferent between this bundle and the bundle (x_0-\lambda\cdot\delta,y_0+\delta). This means that he is willing to give \lambda\cdot\delta units of x to get \delta units of y. If this ratio is kept as \delta\to 0, we say that \lambda is the ''
marginal rate of substitution In economics, the marginal rate of substitution (MRS) is the rate at which a consumer can give up some amount of one good in exchange for another good while maintaining the same level of utility. At equilibrium consumption levels (assuming no exte ...
(MRS)'' between ''x'' and ''y'' at the point (x_0,y_0). This definition of the MRS is based only on the ordinal preference relation – it does not depend on a numeric utility function. If the preference relation is represented by a utility function and the function is differentiable, then the MRS can be calculated from the derivatives of that function: :MRS = \frac. For example, if the preference relation is represented by v(x,y)=x^a\cdot y^b then MRS = \frac=\frac. The MRS is the same for the function v(x,y)=a\cdot \log + b\cdot \log. This is not a coincidence as these two functions represent the same preference relation – each one is an increasing monotone transformation of the other. In general, the MRS may be different at different points (x_0,y_0). For example, it is possible that at (9,1) the MRS is low because the person has a lot of ''x'' and only one ''y'', but at (9,9) or (1,1) the MRS is higher. Some special cases are described below.


Linearity

When the MRS of a certain preference relation does not depend on the bundle, i.e., the MRS is the same for all (x_0,y_0), the indifference curves are linear and of the form: :x+\lambda y = \text, and the preference relation can be represented by a linear function: :v(x,y)=x+\lambda y. (Of course, the same relation can be represented by many other non-linear functions, such as \sqrt or (x+\lambda y)^2, but the linear function is simplest.)


Quasilinearity

When the MRS depends on y_0 but not on x_0, the preference relation can be represented by a
quasilinear utility In economics and consumer theory, quasilinear utility functions are linear in one argument, generally the numeraire. Quasilinear preferences can be represented by the utility function u(x_1, x_2, \ldots, x_n) = x_1 + \theta (x_2, \ldots, x_n) whe ...
function, of the form :v(x,y)=x+\gamma v_Y(y) where v_Y is a certain monotonically increasing function. Because the MRS is a function \lambda(y), a possible function v_Y can be calculated as an integral of \lambda(y): :v_Y(y)=\int_^ In this case, all the indifference curves are parallel – they are horizontal transfers of each other.


Additivity with two goods

A more general type of utility function is an
additive function In number theory, an additive function is an arithmetic function ''f''(''n'') of the positive integer variable ''n'' such that whenever ''a'' and ''b'' are coprime, the function applied to the product ''ab'' is the sum of the values of the funct ...
: :v(x,y)=v_X(x)+v_Y(y) There are several ways to check whether given preferences are representable by an additive utility function.


Double cancellation property

If the preferences are additive then a simple arithmetic calculation shows that :(x_1,y_1)\succeq (x_2,y_2) and :(x_2,y_3)\succeq(x_3,y_1) implies :(x_1,y_3)\succeq(x_3,y_2) so this "double-cancellation" property is a necessary condition for additivity. Debreu (1960) showed that this property is also sufficient: i.e., if a preference relation satisfies the double-cancellation property then it can be represented by an additive utility function.


Corresponding tradeoffs property

If the preferences are represented by an additive function, then a simple arithmetic calculation shows that :MRS(x_2,y_2)=\frac so this "corresponding tradeoffs" property is a necessary condition for additivity. This condition is also sufficient.


Additivity with three or more goods

When there are three or more commodities, the condition for the additivity of the utility function is surprisingly ''simpler'' than for two commodities. This is an outcome of Theorem 3 of Debreu (1960). The condition required for additivity is preferential independence. A subset A of commodities is said to be ''preferentially independent'' of a subset B of commodities, if the preference relation in subset A, given constant values for subset B, is independent of these constant values. For example, suppose there are three commodities: ''x'' ''y'' and ''z''. The subset is preferentially-independent of the subset , if for all x_i,y_i,z,z': :(x_1,y_1, z)\preceq (x_2,y_2, z) \iff (x_1,y_1, z')\preceq (x_2,y_2, z'). In this case, we can simply say that: :(x_1,y_1)\preceq (x_2,y_2) for constant ''z''. Preferential independence makes sense in case of
independent goods Independent goods are goods that have a zero cross elasticity of demand. Changes in the price of one good will have no effect on the demand for an independent good. Thus independent goods are neither complements nor substitutes. For example, a ...
. For example, the preferences between bundles of apples and bananas are probably independent of the number of shoes and socks that an agent has, and vice versa. By Debreu's theorem, if all subsets of commodities are preferentially independent of their complements, then the preference relation can be represented by an additive value function. Here we provide an intuitive explanation of this result by showing how such an additive value function can be constructed. The proof assumes three commodities: ''x'', ''y'', ''z''. We show how to define three points for each of the three value functions v_x, v_y, v_z: the 0 point, the 1 point and the 2 point. Other points can be calculated in a similar way, and then continuity can be used to conclude that the functions are well-defined in their entire range. 0 point: choose arbitrary x_0,y_0,z_0 and assign them as the zero of the value function, i.e.: :v_x(x_0)=v_y(y_0)=v_z(z_0)=0 1 point: choose arbitrary x_1>x_0 such that (x_1,y_0,z_0)\succ(x_0,y_0,z_0). Set it as the unit of value, i.e.: :v_x(x_1)=1 Choose y_1 and z_1 such that the following indifference relations hold: :(x_1,y_0,z_0)\sim(x_0,y_1,z_0)\sim(x_0,y_0,z_1). This indifference serves to scale the units of ''y'' and ''z'' to match those of ''x''. The value in these three points should be 1, so we assign :v_y(y_1)=v_z(z_1)=1 2 point: Now we use the preferential-independence assumption. The relation between (x_1,y_0) and (x_0,y_1) is independent of ''z'', and similarly the relation between (y_1,z_0) and (y_0,z_1) is independent of ''x'' and the relation between (z_1,x_0) and (z_0,x_1) is independent of ''y''. Hence :(x_1,y_0,z_1)\sim(x_0,y_1,z_1)\sim(x_1,y_1,z_0). This is useful because it means that the function ''v'' can have the same value – 2 – in these three points. Select x_2, y_2, z_2 such that :(x_2,y_0,z_0)\sim(x_0,y_2,z_0)\sim(x_0,y_0,z_2)\sim(x_1,y_1,z_0) and assign :v_x(x_2)=v_y(y_2)=v_z(z_2)=2. 3 point: To show that our assignments so far are consistent, we must show that all points that receive a total value of 3 are indifference points. Here, again, the preferential independence assumption is used, since the relation between (x_2,y_0) and (x_1,y_1) is independent of ''z'' (and similarly for the other pairs); hence :(x_2,y_0,z_1)\sim(x_1,y_1,z_1) and similarly for the other pairs. Hence, the 3 point is defined consistently. We can continue like this by induction and define the per-commodity functions in all integer points, then use continuity to define it in all real points. An implicit assumption in point 1 of the above proof is that all three commodities are ''essential'' or ''preference relevant''. This means that there exists a bundle such that, if the amount of a certain commodity is increased, the new bundle is strictly better. The proof for more than 3 commodities is similar. In fact, we do not have to check that all subsets of points are preferentially independent; it is sufficient to check a linear number of pairs of commodities. E.g., if there are m different commodities, j=1,...,m, then it is sufficient to check that for all j=1,...,m-1, the two commodities \ are preferentially independent of the other m-2 commodities.


Uniqueness of additive representation

An additive preference relation can be represented by many different additive utility functions. However, all these functions are similar: they are not only increasing monotone transformations of each other ( as are all utility functions representing the same relation); they are increasing
linear transformation In mathematics, and more specifically in linear algebra, a linear map (also called a linear mapping, linear transformation, vector space homomorphism, or in some contexts linear function) is a mapping V \to W between two vector spaces that pre ...
s of each other. In short, ::An additive ordinal utility function is ''unique up to increasing linear transformation''.


Constructing additive and quadratic utility functions from ordinal data

The mathematical foundations of most common types of utility functions — quadratic and additive — laid down by
Gérard Debreu Gérard Debreu (; 4 July 1921 – 31 December 2004) was a French-born economist and mathematician. Best known as a professor of economics at the University of California, Berkeley, where he began work in 1962, he won the 1983 Nobel Memorial Prize ...
enabled
Andranik Tangian Andranik Semovich Tangian (Melik-Tangyan) (Russian: Андраник Семович Тангян (Мелик-Тангян)); born March 29, 1952) is a Soviet Armenian-German mathematician, political economist and music theorist. Tangian is known f ...
to develop methods for their construction from purely ordinal data. In particular, additive and quadratic utility functions in n variables can be constructed from interviews of decision makers, where questions are aimed at tracing totally n 2D-indifference curves in n - 1 coordinate planes without referring to cardinal utility estimates.


See also

*
Preference (economics) In economics and other social sciences, preference is the order that an agent gives to alternatives based on their relative utility. A process which results in an "optimal choice" (whether real or theoretical). Preferences are evaluations and conc ...
*
Multi-attribute utility In decision theory, a multi-attribute utility function is used to represent the preferences of an agent over bundles of goods either under conditions of certainty about the results of any potential choice, or under conditions of uncertainty. Preli ...
*
Consumer theory The theory of consumer choice is the branch of microeconomics that relates preferences to consumption expenditures and to consumer demand curves. It analyzes how consumers maximize the desirability of their consumption as measured by their pref ...
*
Marginal utility In economics, utility is the satisfaction or benefit derived by consuming a product. The marginal utility of a Goods (economics), good or Service (economics), service describes how much pleasure or satisfaction is gained by consumers as a result o ...
*
Lattice theory A lattice is an abstract structure studied in the mathematical subdisciplines of order theory and abstract algebra. It consists of a partially ordered set in which every pair of elements has a unique supremum (also called a least upper boun ...
*
Convex preferences In economics, convex preferences are an individual's ordering of various outcomes, typically with regard to the amounts of various goods consumed, with the property that, roughly speaking, "averages are better than the extremes". The concept roughly ...


References

{{Reflist


External links


Lexicographic preference relation cannot be represented by a utility function
In Economics.SE
Recognizing linear orders embeddable in R2 ordered lexicographically
In Math.SE. *
Murray N. Rothbard Murray Newton Rothbard (; March 2, 1926 – January 7, 1995) was an American economist of the Austrian School, economic historian, political theorist, and activist. Rothbard was a central figure in the 20th-century American libertarian m ...

"Towards a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics"
Utility