HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In propositional logic, ''modus ponens'' (; MP), also known as ''modus ponendo ponens'' (
Latin Latin (, or , ) is a classical language belonging to the Italic languages, Italic branch of the Indo-European languages. Latin was originally a dialect spoken in the lower Tiber area (then known as Latium) around present-day Rome, but through ...
for "method of putting by placing") or implication elimination or affirming the antecedent, is a deductive argument form and rule of inference. It can be summarized as "''P implies Q.'' ''P'' is true. Therefore ''Q'' must also be true." ''Modus ponens'' is closely related to another valid form of argument, '' modus tollens''. Both have apparently similar but invalid forms such as affirming the consequent, denying the antecedent, and evidence of absence.
Constructive dilemma Constructive dilemmaCopi and Cohen is a valid rule of inference of propositional logic. It is the inference that, if ''P'' implies ''Q'' and ''R'' implies ''S'' and either ''P'' or ''R'' is true, then either ''Q or S'' has to be true. In sum, i ...
is the disjunctive version of ''modus ponens''. Hypothetical syllogism is closely related to ''modus ponens'' and sometimes thought of as "double ''modus ponens''." The history of ''modus ponens'' goes back to
antiquity Antiquity or Antiquities may refer to: Historical objects or periods Artifacts *Antiquities, objects or artifacts surviving from ancient cultures Eras Any period before the European Middle Ages (5th to 15th centuries) but still within the histo ...
. The first to explicitly describe the argument form ''modus ponens'' was
Theophrastus Theophrastus (; grc-gre, Θεόφραστος ; c. 371c. 287 BC), a Greek philosopher and the successor to Aristotle in the Peripatetic school. He was a native of Eresos in Lesbos.Gavin Hardy and Laurence Totelin, ''Ancient Botany'', Routle ...
. It, along with '' modus tollens'', is one of the standard patterns of inference that can be applied to derive chains of conclusions that lead to the desired goal.


Explanation

The form of a ''modus ponens'' argument resembles a
syllogism A syllogism ( grc-gre, συλλογισμός, ''syllogismos'', 'conclusion, inference') is a kind of logical argument that applies deductive reasoning to arrive at a conclusion based on two propositions that are asserted or assumed to be tru ...
, with two premises and a conclusion: # If ''P'', then ''Q''. # ''P''. # Therefore, ''Q''. The first premise is a
conditional Conditional (if then) may refer to: *Causal conditional, if X then Y, where X is a cause of Y *Conditional probability, the probability of an event A given that another event B has occurred *Conditional proof, in logic: a proof that asserts a co ...
("if–then") claim, namely that ''P'' implies ''Q''. The second premise is an assertion that ''P'', the antecedent of the conditional claim, is the case. From these two premises it can be logically concluded that ''Q'', the consequent of the conditional claim, must be the case as well. An example of an argument that fits the form ''modus ponens'': # If today is Tuesday, then John will go to work. # Today is Tuesday. # Therefore, John will go to work. This argument is valid, but this has no bearing on whether any of the statements in the argument are actually
true True most commonly refers to truth, the state of being in congruence with fact or reality. True may also refer to: Places * True, West Virginia, an unincorporated community in the United States * True, Wisconsin, a town in the United States * ...
; for ''modus ponens'' to be a
sound In physics, sound is a vibration that propagates as an acoustic wave, through a transmission medium such as a gas, liquid or solid. In human physiology and psychology, sound is the ''reception'' of such waves and their ''perception'' by ...
argument, the premises must be true for any true instances of the conclusion. An argument can be valid but nonetheless unsound if one or more premises are false; if an argument is valid ''and'' all the premises are true, then the argument is sound. For example, John might be going to work on Wednesday. In this case, the reasoning for John's going to work (because it is Wednesday) is unsound. The argument is only sound on Tuesdays (when John goes to work), but valid on every day of the week. A propositional argument using ''modus ponens'' is said to be deductive. In single-conclusion sequent calculi, ''modus ponens'' is the Cut rule. The cut-elimination theorem for a calculus says that every proof involving Cut can be transformed (generally, by a constructive method) into a proof without Cut, and hence that Cut is admissible. The Curry–Howard correspondence between proofs and programs relates ''modus ponens'' to
function application In mathematics, function application is the act of applying a function to an argument from its domain so as to obtain the corresponding value from its range. In this sense, function application can be thought of as the opposite of function abst ...
: if ''f'' is a function of type ''P'' → ''Q'' and ''x'' is of type ''P'', then ''f x'' is of type ''Q''. In
artificial intelligence Artificial intelligence (AI) is intelligence—perceiving, synthesizing, and inferring information—demonstrated by machines, as opposed to intelligence displayed by animals and humans. Example tasks in which this is done include speech ...
, ''modus ponens'' is often called forward chaining.


Formal notation

The ''modus ponens'' rule may be written in sequent notation as :P \to Q,\; P\;\; \vdash\;\; Q where ''P'', ''Q'' and ''P'' → ''Q'' are statements (or propositions) in a formal language and is a metalogical symbol meaning that ''Q'' is a syntactic consequence of ''P'' and ''P'' → ''Q'' in some
logical system A formal system is an abstract structure used for inferring theorems from axioms according to a set of rules. These rules, which are used for carrying out the inference of theorems from axioms, are the logical calculus of the formal system. A for ...
.


Justification via truth table

The validity of ''modus ponens'' in classical two-valued logic can be clearly demonstrated by use of a
truth table A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional arg ...
. In instances of ''modus ponens'' we assume as premises that ''p'' → ''q'' is true and ''p'' is true. Only one line of the truth table—the first—satisfies these two conditions (''p'' and ''p'' → ''q''). On this line, ''q'' is also true. Therefore, whenever ''p'' → ''q'' is true and ''p'' is true, ''q'' must also be true.


Status

While ''modus ponens'' is one of the most commonly used argument forms in logic it must not be mistaken for a logical law; rather, it is one of the accepted mechanisms for the construction of deductive proofs that includes the "rule of definition" and the "rule of substitution". ''Modus ponens'' allows one to eliminate a conditional statement from a logical proof or argument (the antecedents) and thereby not carry these antecedents forward in an ever-lengthening string of symbols; for this reason modus ponens is sometimes called the rule of detachment or the law of detachment. Enderton, for example, observes that "modus ponens can produce shorter formulas from longer ones", and Russell observes that "the process of the inference cannot be reduced to symbols. Its sole record is the occurrence of ⊦q he consequent... an inference is the dropping of a true premise; it is the dissolution of an implication".Whitehead and Russell 1927:9 A justification for the "trust in inference is the belief that if the two former assertions he antecedentsare not in error, the final assertion he consequentis not in error". In other words: if one statement or
proposition In logic and linguistics, a proposition is the meaning of a declarative sentence. In philosophy, " meaning" is understood to be a non-linguistic entity which is shared by all sentences with the same meaning. Equivalently, a proposition is the no ...
implies a second one, and the first statement or proposition is true, then the second one is also true. If ''P'' implies ''Q'' and ''P'' is true, then ''Q'' is true.


Correspondence to other mathematical frameworks


Algebraic semantics

In mathematical logic, algebraic semantics treats every sentence as a name for an element in an ordered set. Typically, the set can be visualized as a lattice-like structure with a single element (the “always-true”) at the top and another single element (the “always-false”) at the bottom. Logical equivalence becomes identity, so that when \neg and \neg \vee \neg, for instance, are equivalent (as is standard), then \neg = \neg \vee \neg. Logical implication becomes a matter of relative position: P logically implies Q just in case P \leq Q, i.e., when either P = Q or else P lies below Q and is connected to it by an upward path. In this context, to say that P and P \rightarrow Q together imply Q—that is, to affirm ''modus ponens'' as valid—is to say that P \wedge (P \rightarrow Q) \leq Q. In the semantics for basic propositional logic, the algebra is Boolean, with \rightarrow construed as the material conditional: P \rightarrow Q = \neg \vee Q. Confirming that P \wedge (P \rightarrow Q) \leq Q is then straightforward, because P \wedge (P \rightarrow Q) = P \wedge Q. With other treatments of \rightarrow, the semantics becomes more complex, the algebra may be non-Boolean, and the validity of modus ponens cannot be taken for granted.


Probability calculus

''Modus ponens'' represents an instance of the Law of total probability which for a binary variable is expressed as: \Pr(Q)=\Pr(Q\mid P)\Pr(P)+\Pr(Q\mid \lnot P)\Pr(\lnot P)\,, where e.g. \Pr(Q) denotes the probability of Q and the conditional probability \Pr(Q\mid P) generalizes the logical implication P \to Q. Assume that \Pr(Q) = 1 is equivalent to Q being TRUE, and that \Pr(Q) = 0 is equivalent to Q being FALSE. It is then easy to see that \Pr(Q) = 1 when \Pr(Q\mid P) = 1 and \Pr(P) = 1. Hence, the law of total probability represents a generalization of ''modus ponens''.


Subjective logic

''Modus ponens'' represents an instance of the binomial deduction operator in subjective logic expressed as: \omega^_= (\omega^_,\omega^_)\circledcirc \omega^_\,, where \omega^_ denotes the subjective opinion about P as expressed by source A, and the conditional opinion \omega^_ generalizes the logical implication P \to Q. The deduced marginal opinion about Q is denoted by \omega^_. The case where \omega^_ is an absolute TRUE opinion about P is equivalent to source A saying that P is TRUE, and the case where \omega^_ is an absolute FALSE opinion about P is equivalent to source A saying that P is FALSE. The deduction operator \circledcirc of subjective logic produces an absolute TRUE deduced opinion \omega^_ when the conditional opinion \omega^_ is absolute TRUE and the antecedent opinion \omega^_ is absolute TRUE. Hence, subjective logic deduction represents a generalization of both ''modus ponens'' and the Law of total probability.


Alleged cases of failure

Philosophers and linguists have identified a variety of cases where ''modus ponens'' appears to fail.
Vann McGee Vann may refer to: * ''Salvadora oleoides'' is a small bushy evergreen tree found in India, Pakistan, and southern Iran * Vann Peak, Marie Byrd Land, Antarctica People with the name * Vann (surname), an English surname (including a list of people w ...
, for instance, argued that ''modus ponens'' can fail for conditionals whose consequents are themselves conditionals. The following is an example: # Either
Shakespeare William Shakespeare ( 26 April 1564 – 23 April 1616) was an English playwright, poet and actor. He is widely regarded as the greatest writer in the English language and the world's pre-eminent dramatist. He is often called England's nation ...
or
Hobbes Thomas Hobbes ( ; 5/15 April 1588 – 4/14 December 1679) was an English philosopher, considered to be one of the founders of modern political philosophy. Hobbes is best known for his 1651 book ''Leviathan'', in which he expounds an influ ...
wrote ''
Hamlet ''The Tragedy of Hamlet, Prince of Denmark'', often shortened to ''Hamlet'' (), is a tragedy written by William Shakespeare sometime between 1599 and 1601. It is Shakespeare's longest play, with 29,551 words. Set in Denmark, the play depicts ...
''. # If either Shakespeare or Hobbes wrote ''Hamlet'', then if Shakespeare didn't do it, Hobbes did. # Therefore, if Shakespeare didn't write ''Hamlet'', Hobbes did it. Since Shakespeare did write ''Hamlet'', the first premise is true. The second premise is also true, since starting with a set of possible authors limited to just Shakespeare and Hobbes and eliminating one of them leaves only the other. However, the conclusion may seem false, since ruling out Shakespeare as the author of ''Hamlet'' would leave numerous possible candidates, many of them more plausible alternatives than Hobbes. The general form of McGee-type counterexamples to ''modus ponens'' is simply P, P \rightarrow (Q \rightarrow R), therefore Q \rightarrow R; it is not essential that P be a disjunction, as in the example given. That these kinds of cases constitute failures of ''modus ponens'' remains a controversial view among logicians, but opinions vary on how the cases should be disposed of. In deontic logic, some examples of conditional obligation also raise the possibility of ''modus ponens'' failure. These are cases where the conditional premise describes an obligation predicated on an immoral or imprudent action, e.g., “If Doe murders his mother, he ought to do so gently,” for which the dubious unconditional conclusion would be "Doe ought to gently murder his mother." ''
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (''SEP'') combines an online encyclopedia of philosophy with peer-reviewed publication of original papers in philosophy, freely accessible to Internet users. It is maintained by Stanford University. E ...
''.
It would appear to follow that if Doe is in fact gently murdering his mother, then by ''modus ponens'' he is doing exactly what he should, unconditionally, be doing. Here again, ''modus ponens'' failure is not a popular diagnosis but is sometimes argued for.


Possible fallacies

The fallacy of affirming the consequent is a common misinterpretation of the ''modus ponens''.


See also

* * * * * * *


References


Sources

*Herbert B. Enderton, 2001, ''A Mathematical Introduction to Logic Second Edition'', Harcourt Academic Press, Burlington MA, . * Audun Jøsang, 2016, ''Subjective Logic; A formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty'' Springer, Cham, *
Alfred North Whitehead Alfred North Whitehead (15 February 1861 – 30 December 1947) was an English mathematician and philosopher. He is best known as the defining figure of the philosophical school known as process philosophy, which today has found applica ...
and
Bertrand Russell Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British mathematician, philosopher, logician, and public intellectual. He had a considerable influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, linguistics, a ...
1927 ''Principia Mathematica to *56 (Second Edition)'' paperback edition 1962, Cambridge at the University Press, London UK. No ISBN, no LCCCN. * Alfred Tarski 1946 ''Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences'' 2nd Edition, reprinted by Dover Publications, Mineola NY. (pbk).


External links

* * *
Modus ponens
' at Wolfram MathWorld {{DEFAULTSORT:Modus Ponens Rules of inference Latin logical phrases Theorems in propositional logic Classical logic