LL Fuller
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Lon Luvois Fuller (June 15, 1902 – April 8, 1978) was an American legal
philosopher A philosopher is a person who practices or investigates philosophy. The term ''philosopher'' comes from the grc, φιλόσοφος, , translit=philosophos, meaning 'lover of wisdom'. The coining of the term has been attributed to the Greek th ...
, who criticized legal positivism and defended a secular and procedural form of
natural law theory Natural law ( la, ius naturale, ''lex naturalis'') is a system of law based on a close observation of human nature, and based on values intrinsic to human nature that can be deduced and applied independently of positive law (the express enacted ...
. Fuller was a professor of Law at Harvard University for many years, and is noted in American law for his contributions to both jurisprudence and the law of contracts. His debate in 1958 with the prominent British legal philosopher H. L. A. Hart in the ''
Harvard Law Review The ''Harvard Law Review'' is a law review published by an independent student group at Harvard Law School. According to the ''Journal Citation Reports'', the ''Harvard Law Review''s 2015 impact factor of 4.979 placed the journal first out of 143 ...
'' (Vol. 71) was important in framing the modern conflict between legal positivism and
natural law theory Natural law ( la, ius naturale, ''lex naturalis'') is a system of law based on a close observation of human nature, and based on values intrinsic to human nature that can be deduced and applied independently of positive law (the express enacted ...
. In his widely discussed 1964 book ''The Morality of Law'', Fuller argues that all systems of law contain an "internal morality" that imposes on individuals a presumptive obligation of obedience.
Robert S. Summers Robert Samuel Summers (September 19, 1933 – March 1, 2019) was an American legal scholar who was the former William G. McRoberts Research Professor in the Administration of the Law at the Cornell Law School. He retired in 2011. Early life and ...
said in 1984: "Fuller was one of the four most important American legal theorists of the last hundred years".


Personal life

Fuller was born in Hereford, Texas, and graduated from Stanford Law School. He started teaching at the University of Oregon Law School, later at
Duke University Duke University is a private research university in Durham, North Carolina. Founded by Methodists and Quakers in the present-day city of Trinity in 1838, the school moved to Durham in 1892. In 1924, tobacco and electric power industrialist James ...
Law School, where one of his students was the later President
Richard M. Nixon Richard Milhous Nixon (January 9, 1913April 22, 1994) was the 37th president of the United States, serving from 1969 to 1974. A member of the Republican Party, he previously served as a representative and senator from California and was t ...
, and joined
Harvard Law School Harvard Law School (Harvard Law or HLS) is the law school of Harvard University, a private research university in Cambridge, Massachusetts. Founded in 1817, it is the oldest continuously operating law school in the United States. Each class ...
in 1940. He held the Carter chair of jurisprudence at Harvard from 1948 until his retirement in 1972, and also practiced law with the Boston firm of Ropes, Gray, Best, Coolidge & Rugg. Fuller died at age 75 at his home in Cambridge, Massachusetts. He was survived by his wife, Marjorie, two children from a previous marriage – Prof. F. Brock Fuller ( Altadena, California), and Cornelia F. Hopfield ( Princeton, New Jersey) – and two stepchildren, Prof.
William D. Chapple William D. Chapple (August 6, 1868 – May 3, 1956) was a Massachusetts lawyer and politician who served as President of the Massachusetts Senate. Early life and education Chapple was born on August 6, 1868, in Salem. He graduated from Salem H ...
(
Storrs, Connecticut Storrs is a village and census-designated place (CDP) in the New England town, town of Mansfield, Connecticut, Mansfield in eastern Tolland County, Connecticut, Tolland County, Connecticut, United States. The population was 15,344 at the 2010 Unite ...
), and Mimi Hinnawi ( London). He had eight grandchildren.


The internal morality of law

In his 1958 debate with Hart and more fully in ''The Morality of Law'' (1964), Fuller sought to steer a middle course between traditional natural law theory and legal positivism. Like most legal academics of his day, Fuller rejected traditional religious forms of natural law theory, which view human law as rooted in a rationally knowable and universally binding "higher law" that derives from God. Fuller accepted the idea, found in the writings of some traditional natural law theorists, that in some cases unjust laws or legal systems are not law. In his famous Reply to Professor Hart in the
Hart–Fuller debate The Hart–Fuller debate is an exchange between the American law professor Lon L. Fuller and his English counterpart H. L. A. Hart, published in the '' Harvard Law Review'' in 1958 on morality and law, which demonstrated the divide between the posi ...
, he wrote:
I would like to ask the reader whether he can actually share Professor Hart's indignation that, in the perplexities of the postwar re-construction, the German courts saw fit to declare this thing not a law. Can it be argued seriously that it would have been more beseeming to the judicial process if the postwar courts had undertaken a study of "the interpretative principles" in force during Hitler's rule and had then solemnly applied those "principles" to ascertain the meaning of this statute? On the other hand, would the courts really have been showing respect for Nazi law if they had constructed the Nazi statutes on their own, quite different, standards of interpretation? (p. 655)
Professor Hart castigates the German courts and Radbruch, not so much for what they believed had to be done, but because they failed to see that they were confronted by a moral dilemma of a sort that would have been immediately apparent to Bentham and Austin. By the simple dodge of saying, "When a statute is sufficiently evil it ceases to be law," they ran away from the problem they should have faced. This criticism is, I believe, without justification. So far as the courts are concerned, matters certainly would not have been helped if, instead of saying, "This is not law," they had said, "This is law but it is so evil we will refuse to apply it." (p. 655)
To me there is nothing shocking in saying that a dictatorship which clothes itself with a tinsel of legal form can so far depart from the morality of order, from the inner morality of law itself, that it ceases to be a legal system. When a system calling itself law is predicated upon a general disregard by judges of the terms of the laws they purport to enforce, when this system habitually cures its legal irregularities, even the grossest, by retroactive statutes, when it has only to resort to forays of terror in the streets, which no one dares challenge, in order to escape even those scant restraints imposed by the pretence of legality - when all these things have become true of a dictatorship, it is not hard for me, at least, to deny to it the name of law. (p. 660)
Fuller also denied the core claim of legal positivism that there is no necessary connection between law and morality. According to Fuller, certain moral standards, which he calls "principles of legality," are built into the very concept of law, so that nothing counts as genuine law that fails to meet these standards. In virtue of these principles of legality, the law has an inner morality that imposes a minimal morality of fairness. Some laws, he admits, may be so wicked or unjust that they should not be obeyed. But even in these cases, he argues, there are positive features of the law that impose a defensible moral duty to obey them. According to Fuller, all purported legal rules must meet eight minimal conditions in order to count as genuine laws. The rules must be (1) sufficiently general, (2) publicly promulgated, (3) prospective (i.e., applicable only to future behavior, not past), (4) at least minimally clear and intelligible, (5) free of contradictions, (6) relatively constant, so that they don't continuously change from day to day, (7) possible to obey, and (8) administered in a way that does not wildly diverge from their obvious or apparent meaning. These are Fuller's "principles of legality." Together, he argues, they guarantee that all law will embody certain moral standards of respect, fairness, and predictability that constitute important aspects of the rule of law. Fuller presents these issues in ''The Morality of Law'' with an entertaining story about an imaginary king named Rex who attempts to rule but finds he is unable to do so in any meaningful way when any of these conditions are not met. Fuller contends that the purpose of law is to subject "human conduct to the governance of rules". If any of the eight principles is flagrantly lacking in a system of governance, the system will not be a legal one. The more closely a system is able to adhere to them, the nearer it will be to the rule-of-law ideal, though in reality all systems must make compromises and will fall short of perfect ideals of clarity, consistency, stability, and so forth. In a review of ''The Morality of Law'', Hart criticises Fuller's work, saying that these principles are merely ones of means-ends efficiency; it is inappropriate, he says, to call them a morality. Employing Fuller's eight principles of legality, one could just as well have an inner morality of poisoning as an inner morality of law, which Hart claims is absurd. In this phase of the argument, the positions of the disputants are transposed. Fuller proposes principles that would easily fit into a positivistic account of law and Hart points out that Fuller's principles could easily accommodate an immoral morality. Other critics have challenged Fuller's claim that there is a ''
prima facie ''Prima facie'' (; ) is a Latin expression meaning ''at first sight'' or ''based on first impression''. The literal translation would be 'at first face' or 'at first appearance', from the feminine forms of ''primus'' ('first') and ''facies'' (' ...
'' obligation to obey all laws. Some laws, it is claimed, are so unjust and oppressive that there is not even a presumptive moral duty to obey them.Andrew Altman. ''Arguing about Law: An Introduction to Legal Philosophy'', 2nd ed. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 2001, p. 57.


Works

* ''Law in Quest of Itself'', 1940 * ''Basic Contract Law'', 1947 (second edition, 1964) * ''Problems of Jurisprudence'', 1949 * ''The Morality of Law'', 1964 (second edition, 1969) * ''Legal Fictions'', 1967 * ''Anatomy of Law'', 1968


See also

* The Case of the Speluncean Explorers *
Hart–Fuller debate The Hart–Fuller debate is an exchange between the American law professor Lon L. Fuller and his English counterpart H. L. A. Hart, published in the '' Harvard Law Review'' in 1958 on morality and law, which demonstrated the divide between the posi ...
* The Rule of Law


References


Further reading

* W. J. Witteveen and Wibren van der Burg
''Rediscovering Fuller: Essays on Implicit Law and Institutional Design''
(Amsterdam University Press, Amsterdam, 1999). *L. L. Fuller and W. R. Perdue, "The Reliance Interest in Contract Damages" (1936) 46
Yale Law Journal The ''Yale Law Journal'' (YLJ), known also as the ''Yale Law Review'', is a student-run law review affiliated with the Yale Law School. Published continuously since 1891, it is the most widely known of the eight law reviews published by students ...
52–96


External links


Finding Aid for Lon L. Fuller, Papers, 1926-1977
from Harvard University Library
Entry on Fuller from the IVR encyclopaedia
* Nicola Laceybr>Philosophy, Political Morality, and History: Explaining the Enduring Resonance of the Hart–Fuller Debate
(2008) 83 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1059 * Colleen Murph
'Lon Fuller and the Moral Value of the Rule of Law'
(2005) 24 Law and Philosophy 239. * Jeremy Waldro
‘Positivism and Legality: Hart’s Equivocal Response to Fuller’
(2008) 83 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1135

obituary in the New York Times, 10 April 1978 {{DEFAULTSORT:Fuller, Lon L. 1902 births 1978 deaths Philosophers of law Harvard Law School faculty Scholars of contract law People from Hereford, Texas