HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The intentional stance is a term coined by
philosopher Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
Daniel Dennett Daniel Clement Dennett III (March 28, 1942 – April 19, 2024) was an American philosopher and cognitive scientist. His research centered on the philosophy of mind, the philosophy of science, and the philosophy of biology, particularly as those ...
for the level of
abstraction Abstraction is a process where general rules and concepts are derived from the use and classifying of specific examples, literal (reality, real or Abstract and concrete, concrete) signifiers, first principles, or other methods. "An abstraction" ...
in which we view the behavior of an entity in terms of mental properties. It is part of a theory of
mental content The mental world is an Ontology, ontological category in metaphysics, populated by nonmaterial mental objects, without physical Extension (metaphysics), extension (though possibly with mental extension as in a visual field, or possibly not, as in a ...
proposed by Dennett, which provides the underpinnings of his later works on
free will Free will is generally understood as the capacity or ability of people to (a) choice, choose between different possible courses of Action (philosophy), action, (b) exercise control over their actions in a way that is necessary for moral respon ...
,
consciousness Consciousness, at its simplest, is awareness of a state or object, either internal to oneself or in one's external environment. However, its nature has led to millennia of analyses, explanations, and debate among philosophers, scientists, an ...
,
folk psychology Folk psychology, commonsense psychology, or naïve psychology is the ordinary, intuitive, or non-expert understanding, explanation, and rationalization of people's behaviors and Cognitive psychology, mental states. In philosophy of mind and cognit ...
, and
evolution Evolution is the change in the heritable Phenotypic trait, characteristics of biological populations over successive generations. It occurs when evolutionary processes such as natural selection and genetic drift act on genetic variation, re ...
.


Dennett and intentionality

Dennett (1971, p. 87) states that he took the concept of "
intentionality Intentionality is the mental ability to refer to or represent something. Sometimes regarded as the ''mark of the mental'', it is found in mental states like perceptions, beliefs or desires. For example, the perception of a tree has intentionality ...
" from the work of the German philosopher
Franz Brentano Franz Clemens Honoratus Hermann Josef Brentano (; ; 16 January 1838 – 17 March 1917) was a German philosopher and psychologist. His 1874 '' Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint'', considered his magnum opus, is credited with having reintrod ...
. When clarifying the distinction between mental phenomena (viz., mental activity) and physical phenomena, Brentano (p. 97) argued that, in contrast with physical phenomena, the "distinguishing characteristic of all mental phenomena" was "the reference to something as an object" – a characteristic he called "''intentional inexistence''". Dennett constantly speaks of the "''
aboutness Aboutness is a term used in library and information science (LIS), linguistics, philosophy of language, and philosophy of mind. In general, the term refers to the concept that a text, utterance, image, or action is or something. In LIS, it is of ...
''" of ''intentionality''; for example: "the aboutness of the pencil marks composing a shopping list is derived from the intentions of the person whose list it is" (Dennett, 1995, p. 240).
John Searle John Rogers Searle (; born July 31, 1932) is an American philosopher widely noted for contributions to the philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, and social philosophy. He began teaching at UC Berkeley in 1959 and was Willis S. and Mario ...
(1999, pp. 85) stresses that "competence" in predicting/explaining human behaviour involves being able to both recognize others as "''intentional''" beings, and interpret others' minds as having "intentional states" (e.g., beliefs and desires): :"The primary evolutionary role of the mind is to relate us in certain ways to the environment, and especially to other people. My subjective states relate me to the rest of the world, and the general name of that relationship is "intentionality." These subjective states include beliefs and desires, intentions and perceptions, as well as loves and hates, fears and hopes. "Intentionality," to repeat, is the general term for all the various forms by which the mind can be directed at, or be about, or of, objects and states of affairs in the world." (p.85) According to Dennett (1987, pp. 48–49),
folk psychology Folk psychology, commonsense psychology, or naïve psychology is the ordinary, intuitive, or non-expert understanding, explanation, and rationalization of people's behaviors and Cognitive psychology, mental states. In philosophy of mind and cognit ...
provides a systematic, "reason-giving explanation" for a particular action, and an account of the historical origins of that action, based on deeply embedded assumptions about the agent; namely that: This approach is also consistent with the earlier work of
Fritz Heider Fritz Heider (19 February 1896 – 2 January 1988) was an Austrian psychologist whose work was related to the Gestalt school. In 1958 he published ''The Psychology of Interpersonal Relations'', which expanded upon his creations of balance theory ...
and Marianne Simmel, whose joint study revealed that, when subjects were presented with an animated display of 2-dimensional shapes, they were inclined to ascribe intentions to the shapes. Further, Dennett (1987, p. 52) argues that, based on our fixed personal views of what all humans ought to believe, desire and do, we predict (or explain) the beliefs, desires and actions of others "by calculating in a normative system"; and, driven by the reasonable assumption that all humans are rational beings – who do ''have'' specific beliefs and desires and do ''act'' on the basis of those beliefs and desires in order to get what they want – these predictions/explanations are based on four simple rules: # The agent's ''beliefs'' are those a rational individual ought to have (i.e., given their "perceptual capacities", "epistemic needs" and "biography"); # In general, these beliefs "are both true and relevant to
heir Inheritance is the practice of receiving private property, titles, debts, entitlements, privileges, rights, and obligations upon the death of an individual. The rules of inheritance differ among societies and have changed over time. Offi ...
life; # The agent's ''desires'' are those a rational individual ought to have (i.e., given their "biological needs", and "the most practicable means of satisfying them") in order to further their "survival" and "procreation" needs; and # The agent's behaviour will be composed of those acts a rational individual holding those ''beliefs'' (and having those ''desires'') ought to perform.


Dennett's three levels

The core idea is that, when understanding, explaining, and/or predicting the behavior of an object, we can choose to view it at varying levels of abstraction. The more concrete the level, the more accurate ''in principle'' our predictions are; the more abstract, the greater the computational power we gain by zooming out and skipping over the irrelevant details. Dennett defines three levels of abstraction, attained by adopting one of three entirely different "stances", or intellectual strategies: the physical stance; the design stance; and the intentional stance: * The most concrete is the ''physical stance'', the domain of physics and chemistry, which makes predictions from knowledge of the physical constitution of the system and the physical laws that govern its operation; and thus, given a particular set of physical laws and initial conditions, and a particular configuration, a specific future state is predicted (this could also be called the "''structure stance''"). At this level, we are concerned with such things as mass, energy, velocity, and chemical composition. When we predict where a ball is going to land based on its current trajectory, we are taking the physical stance. Another example of this stance comes when we look at a strip made up of two types of metal bonded together and predict how it will bend as the temperature changes, based on the physical properties of the two metals. * Somewhat more abstract is the ''design stance'', the domain of biology and engineering, which requires no knowledge of the physical constitution or the physical laws that govern a system's operation. Based on an implicit assumption that there is no malfunction in the system, predictions are made from knowledge of the purpose of the system's design (this could also be called the "''teleological stance''"). At this level, we are concerned with such things as purpose, function and design. When we predict that a bird will fly when it flaps its wings on the basis that wings are made for flying, we are taking the design stance. Likewise, we can understand the bimetallic strip as a particular type of thermometer, not concerning ourselves with the details of how this type of thermometer happens to work. We can also recognize the purpose that this thermometer serves inside a thermostat and even generalize to other kinds of thermostats that might use a different sort of thermometer. We can even explain the thermostat in terms of what it's good for, saying that it keeps track of the temperature and turns on the heater whenever it gets below a minimum, turning it off once it reaches a maximum. * Most abstract is the ''intentional stance'', the domain of software and minds, which requires no knowledge of either structure or design, and " larifiesthe logic of mentalistic explanations of behaviour, their predictive power, and their relation to other forms of explanation" (Bolton & Hill, 1996, p. 24). Predictions are made on the basis of ''explanations'' expressed in terms of meaningful mental states; and, given the task of predicting or explaining the behaviour of a specific agent (a person, animal, corporation, artifact, nation, etc.), it is implicitly assumed that the agent will always act on the basis of its ''beliefs'' and ''desires'' in order to get precisely what it wants (this could also be called the "''folk psychology stance''"). At this level, we are concerned with such things as belief, thinking and intent. When we predict that the bird will fly away because it knows the cat is coming and is afraid of getting eaten, we are taking the intentional stance. Another example would be when we predict that Mary will leave the theater and drive to the restaurant because she sees that the movie is over and is hungry. * In 1971, Dennett also postulated that, whilst "the intentional stance ''presupposes'' neither lower stance", there may well be a fourth, higher level: a "truly moral stance toward the system" – the "''personal stance''" – which not only "presupposes the intentional stance" (viz., treats the system as ''rational'') but also "views it as a person" (1971/1978, p. 240). A key point is that switching to a higher level of abstraction has its risks as well as its benefits. For example, when we view both a bimetallic strip and a tube of mercury as thermometers, we can lose track of the fact that they differ in accuracy and temperature range, leading to false predictions as soon as the thermometer is used outside the circumstances for which it was designed. The actions of a mercury thermometer heated to 500 °C can no longer be predicted on the basis of treating it as a thermometer; we have to sink down to the physical stance to understand it as a melted and boiled piece of junk. For that matter, the "actions" of a dead bird are not predictable in terms of beliefs or desires. Even when there is no immediate error, a higher-level stance can simply fail to be useful. If we were to try to understand the thermostat at the level of the intentional stance, ascribing to it beliefs about how hot it is and a desire to keep the temperature just right, we would gain no traction over the problem as compared to staying at the design stance, but we would generate theoretical commitments that expose us to absurdities, such as the possibility of the thermostat not being in the mood to work today because the weather is so nice. Whether to take a particular stance, then, is determined by how successful that stance is when applied. Dennett argues that it is best to understand human behavior at the level of the intentional stance, without making any specific commitments to any deeper reality of the artifacts of
folk psychology Folk psychology, commonsense psychology, or naïve psychology is the ordinary, intuitive, or non-expert understanding, explanation, and rationalization of people's behaviors and Cognitive psychology, mental states. In philosophy of mind and cognit ...
. In addition to the controversy inherent in this, there is also some dispute about the extent to which Dennett is committing to realism about mental properties. Initially, Dennett's interpretation was seen as leaning more towards
instrumentalism In philosophy of science and in epistemology, instrumentalism is a methodological view that ideas are useful instruments, and that the worth of an idea is based on how effective it is in explaining and predicting natural phenomena. According to in ...
, but over the years, as this idea has been used to support more extensive theories of
consciousness Consciousness, at its simplest, is awareness of a state or object, either internal to oneself or in one's external environment. However, its nature has led to millennia of analyses, explanations, and debate among philosophers, scientists, an ...
, it has been taken as being more like Realism. His own words hint at something in the middle, as he suggests that the self is as real as a center of gravity, "an
abstract object In philosophy and the arts, a fundamental distinction exists between abstract and concrete entities. While there is no universally accepted definition, common examples illustrate the difference: numbers, sets, and ideas are typically classif ...
, a theorist's fiction", but operationally valid. As a way of thinking about things, Dennett's intentional stance is entirely consistent with everyday commonsense understanding; and, thus, it meets
Eleanor Rosch Eleanor Rosch (once known as Eleanor Rosch Heider;"Natural Categories", Cognitive Psychology, Vol. 4, No. 3, (May 1973), p. 328. born 9 July 1938) is an American psychologist. She is a professor of psychology at the University of California, Berk ...
's (1978, p. 28) criterion of the "maximum information with the least cognitive effort". Rosch argues that, implicit within any system of categorization, are the assumptions that: :(a) the major purpose of any system of categorization is to reduce the randomness of the universe by providing "maximum information with the least cognitive effort", and :(b) the real world is structured and systematic, rather than being arbitrary or unpredictable. Thus, if a particular way of categorizing information does, indeed, "provide maximum information with the least cognitive effort", ''it can only do so because the structure of that particular system of categories corresponds with the perceived structure of the real world''. Also, the intentional stance meets the criteria Dennett specified (1995, pp. 50–51) for algorithms: :(1) ''Substrate Neutrality'': It is a "mechanism" that produces results regardless of the material used to perform the procedure ("the power of the procedure is due to its logical structure, not the causal powers of the materials used in the instantiation"). :(2) ''Underlying Mindlessness'': Each constituent step, and each transition between each step, is so utterly simple, that they can be performed by a "dutiful idiot". :(3) ''Guaranteed Results'': "Whatever it is that an algorithm does, it always does it, if it is executed without misstep. An algorithm is a foolproof recipe."


Variants of Dennett's three stances

The general notion of a three level system was widespread in the late 1970s/early 1980s; for example, when discussing the mental representation of information from a
cognitive psychology Cognitive psychology is the scientific study of human mental processes such as attention, language use, memory, perception, problem solving, creativity, and reasoning. Cognitive psychology originated in the 1960s in a break from behaviorism, whi ...
perspective, Glass and his colleagues (1979, p. 24) distinguished three important aspects of representation: :(a) the ''content'' ("what is being represented"); :(b) the ''code'' ("the format of the representation"); and :(c) the ''medium'' ("the physical realization of the code"). Other significant cognitive scientists who also advocated a three level system were
Allen Newell Allen Newell (March 19, 1927 – July 19, 1992) was an American researcher in computer science and cognitive psychology at the RAND Corporation and at Carnegie Mellon University's School of Computer Science, Tepper School of Business, and D ...
, Zenon Pylyshyn, and David Marr. The parallels between the four representations (each of which implicitly assumed that computers ''and'' human minds displayed each of the three distinct levels) are detailed in the following table:


Objections and replies

The most obvious objection to Dennett is the intuition that it "matters" to us whether an object has an inner life or not. The claim is that we don't just imagine the intentional states of other people in order to predict their behaviour; the fact that they have thoughts and feelings just like we do is central to notions such as trust, friendship and love. The Blockhead argument proposes that someone, Jones, has a twin who is in fact not a person but a very sophisticated robot which looks and acts like Jones in every way, but who (it is claimed) somehow does not have any thoughts or feelings at all, just a chip which controls his behaviour; in other words, "the lights are on but no one's home". According to the intentional systems theory (IST), Jones and the robot have precisely the same beliefs and desires, but this is claimed to be false. The IST expert assigns the same mental states to Blockhead as he does to Jones, "whereas in fact lockheadhas not a thought in his head." Dennett has argued against this by denying the premise, on the basis that the robot is a
philosophical zombie A philosophical zombie (or "p-zombie") is a being in a thought experiment in the philosophy of mind that is physically identical to a normal human being but does not have conscious experience. For example, if a philosophical zombie were poked ...
and therefore metaphysically impossible. In other words, if something acts in all ways conscious, it necessarily is, as consciousness is defined in terms of behavioral capacity, not ineffable
qualia In philosophy of mind, qualia (; singular: quale ) are defined as instances of subjective, conscious experience. The term ''qualia'' derives from the Latin neuter plural form (''qualia'') of the Latin adjective '' quālis'' () meaning "of what ...
. Another objection attacks the premise that treating people as ideally rational creatures will yield the best predictions. Stephen Stich argues that people often have beliefs or desires which are irrational or bizarre, and IST doesn't allow us to say anything about these. If the person's "environmental niche" is examined closely enough, and the possibility of malfunction in their brain (which might affect their reasoning capacities) is looked into, it may be possible to formulate a predictive strategy specific to that person. Indeed this is what we often do when someone is behaving unpredictably — we look for the reasons why. In other words, we can only deal with irrationality by contrasting it against the background assumption of rationality. This development significantly undermines the claims of the intentional stance argument. The rationale behind the intentional stance is based on evolutionary theory, particularly the notion that the ability to make quick predictions of a system's behaviour based on what we think it might be thinking was an evolutionary adaptive advantage. The fact that our predictive powers are not perfect is a further result of the advantages sometimes accrued by acting contrary to expectations.


Neural evidence

Philip Robbins and Anthony I. Jack suggest that "Dennett's philosophical distinction between the physical and intentional stances has a lot going for it" from the perspective of psychology and neuroscience. They review studies on abilities to adopt an intentional stance (variously called "mindreading", "mentalizing", or "theory of mind") as distinct from adopting a physical stance ("folk physics", "intuitive physics", or "theory of body").
Autism Autism, also known as autism spectrum disorder (ASD), is a neurodevelopmental disorder characterized by differences or difficulties in social communication and interaction, a preference for predictability and routine, sensory processing d ...
seems to be a deficit in the intentional stance with preservation of the physical stance, while
Williams syndrome Williams syndrome (WS), also Williams–Beuren syndrome (WBS), is a genetic disorder that affects many parts of the body. Facial features frequently include a broad forehead, underdeveloped chin, short nose, and full cheeks. Mild to moderate int ...
can involve deficits in the physical stance with preservation of the intentional stance. This tentatively suggests a double dissociation of intentional and physical stances in the brain. However, most studies have found no evidence of impairment in autistic individuals' ability to understand other people's basic intentions or goals; instead, data suggests that impairments are found in understanding more complex social emotions or in considering others' viewpoints. Robbins and Jack point to a 2003 study in which participants viewed animated geometric shapes in different "vignettes," some of which could be interpreted as constituting social interaction, while others suggested mechanical behavior. Viewing social interactions elicited activity in brain regions associated with identifying faces and biological objects (posterior temporal cortex), as well as emotion processing (right amygdala and ventromedial prefrontal cortex). Meanwhile, the mechanical interactions activated regions related to identifying objects like tools that can be manipulated (posterior temporal lobe). The authors suggest "that these findings reveal putative 'core systems' for social and mechanical understanding that are divisible into constituent parts or elements with distinct processing and storage capabilities."


Phenomenal stance

Robbins and Jack argue for an additional stance beyond the three that Dennett outlined. They call it the ''phenomenal stance'': Attributing consciousness, emotions, and inner experience to a mind. The
explanatory gap In the philosophy of mind, the explanatory gap is the difficulty that physicalist philosophies have in explaining how physical properties give rise to the way things feel subjectively when they are experienced. It is a term introduced by philoso ...
of the
hard problem of consciousness In the philosophy of mind, the hard problem of consciousness is to explain why and how humans and other organisms have qualia, phenomenal consciousness, or subjective experience. It is contrasted with the "easy problems" of explaining why and how ...
illustrates this tendency of people to see phenomenal experience as different from physical processes. The authors suggest that psychopathy may represent a deficit in the phenomenal but not intentional stance, while people with autism appear to have intact moral sensibilities, just not mind-reading abilities. These examples suggest a double dissociation between the intentional and phenomenal stances. In a follow-up paper, Robbins and Jack describe four experiments about how the intentional and phenomenal stances relate to feelings of moral concern. The first two experiments showed that talking about lobsters as strongly emotional led to a much greater sentiment that lobsters deserved welfare protections than did talking about lobsters as highly intelligent. The third and fourth studies found that perceiving an agent as vulnerable led to greater attributions of phenomenal experience. Also, people who scored higher on the empathetic-concern subscale of the
Interpersonal Reactivity Index The Interpersonal Reactivity Index (IRI) is a published measurement tool for the multi-dimensional assessment of empathy. It was developed by Mark H. Davis, a professor of psychology at Eckerd College. This version was used to measure empathy in C ...
had generally higher absolute attributions of mental experience. Bryce Huebner (2010) performed two experimental philosophy studies to test students' ascriptions of various mental states to humans compared with cyborgs and robots. Experiment 1 showed that while students attributed both beliefs and pains most strongly to humans, they were more willing to attribute beliefs than pains to robots and cyborgs. " ese data seem to confirm that commonsense psychology does draw a distinction between phenomenal and non-phenomenal states—and this distinction seems to be dependent on the structural properties of an entity in a way that ascriptions of non-phenomenal states are not." However, this conclusion is only tentative in view of the high variance among participants. Experiment 2 showed analogous results: Both beliefs and happiness were ascribed most strongly to biological humans, and ascriptions of happiness to robots or cyborgs were less common than ascriptions of beliefs.


See also

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *


Footnotes


References

* Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Jackson, F. ''Philosophy of Mind and Cognition'', Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1996 * Bolton, D. & Hill, J., ''Mind, Meaning, and Mental Disorder: The Nature of Causal Explanation in Psychology and Psychiatry'', Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 1996. * Brentano, F., (1973/1924) ''Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (Second Edition)'', Routledge & Kegan Paul, (London) 1973 (The German version of the Second Edition was published in 1924). * Dennett, D.C., (1971
"Intentional Systems", ''The Journal of Philosophy'', Vol.68, No. 4, (25 February 1971), pp.87-106.
* Dennett, D.C., (1971/1978) "Mechanism and Responsibility", reprinted in pp. 233–255 in Dennett, D.C., ''Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology'', Bradford Books, (Montgomery), 1978 (originally published in 1971). * Dennett, D.C., (1975
"Brain Writing and Mind Reading", ''Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science'', 7: 403-415.
* Dennett, D., (1987) "True Believers" in Dennett, D. ''The Intentional Stance'', The MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1987 * (First published 1987). * Dennett, D.C., (1995) ''Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life'', Simon & Schuster, (New York), 1995. * Daniel C. Dennett (1997)
"Chapter 3. True Believers: The Intentional Strategy and Why it Works"
in John Haugeland
''Mind Design II: Philosophy, Psychology, Artificial Intelligence''
Massachusetts: Massachusetts Institute of Technology. (first published in ''Scientific Explanation'', 1981, edited by A.F. Heath, Oxford: Oxford University Press; originally presented as a Herbert Spencer lecture at Oxford in November 1979; also published as chapter 2 in Dennett's book ''The Intentional Stance''). * Dennett, D. "Three kinds of intentional psychology" (IP) in Heil, J. - ''Philosophy of Mind: A guide and anthology'', Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2004
Falk, R. & Konold, C., "Making Sense of Randomness: Implicit Encoding as a Basis for Judgement", ''Psychological Review'', Vol.104, No.2, (April 1997), pp.301-318.
* Falk, R. & Konold, C., "Subjective Randomness", pp. 653–659, in Kotz, S., Read, C.B. & Banks, D.L., ''Encyclopedia of Statistical Sciences: Update Volume 2'', John Wiley & Sons, (New York), 1988. * Fano, Vincenzo. "Holism and the naturalization of consciousness" in ''Holism'', Massimo Dell'Utri. Quodlibet. 2002. * Fodor, J. ''Psychosemantics'', MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1987. * Foss, C.L. & Bow, G.H., "Understanding Actions in Relation to Goals", pp. 94–124 in Sharkey, N.E. (ed.), ''Advances in Cognitive Science 1'', Ellis Horwood, (Chichester), 1986. * Glass, A.L., Holyoak, K.J. & Santa, J.L., ''Cognition'', Addison-Wesley Publishing Company, (Reading), 1979. * Heider, F. & Simmel, M.
"An Experimental Study of Apparent Behavior", ''American Journal of Psychology'', Vol.57, (1944), pp.243-259.
* Lisanby, S.H. & Lockhead, G., "Subjective Randomness, Aesthetics, and Structure", pp. 97–114 in Lockhead, G.R. & Pomerantz, J.R. (eds.), ''The Perception of Structure'', American Psychological Association, (Washington), 1991. * Lycan, W. ''Mind & Cognition'', Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1990 * Marr, D., ''Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation of Visual Information'', W.H. Freeman & Company, (New York), 1982. * Newell, A., (1982
"The Knowledge Level", ''Artificial Intelligence'', Vol.18, No.1, (January 1982), pp.87-127.
* Newell, A. (1988), "The intentional stance and the knowledge level", ''Behavioral and Brain Sciences'', Vol.11, No.3, (September 1988), pp. 520–522. * Papineau, D., "Instrumentalism", p. 410 in Honderich, T. (ed.), ''The Oxford Companion to Philosophy'', Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 1995. * Perkins, David N., "Why the Human Perceiver is a Bad Machine", pp. 341–364 in Beck, J. Hope, B. & Rosenfeld, A. (eds.), ''Human and Machine Vision'', Academic Press, (New York), 1983. * Piaget, J. & Inhelder, B. Leake, L., Burrell, P. & Fishbein, H.D. eds.), ''The Origin of the Idea of Chance in Children'', Routledge & Kegan Paul, (London), 1975 [French original 1951 * Pylyshyn, Z.W.
"Computing in Cognitive Science", pp.51-91 in Posner, M.I.(ed.), ''Foundations of Cognitive Science'', The MIT Press, (Cambridge), 1989.
* Rosch, E., "Principles of Categorization", pp. 27–48 in Rosch, E. & Lloyd, B.B. (eds), ''Cognition and Categorization'', Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publishers, (Hillsdale), 1978. * Searle, J., ''Mind, Language and Society: Philosophy in the Real World'', Phoenix, (London), 1999. * Siegert, R.J., "Culture, Cognition, and Schizophrenia", pp. 171–189 in Schumaker, J.F. & Ward, T. (eds.), ''Cultural Cognition and Psychopathology'', Praeger, (Westport), 2001. * Swinburne, R., ''Epistemic Justification'', Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 2001. {{Dennett Abstraction Cognitive psychology Cognitive science Consciousness Intention Concepts in the philosophy of mind Psycholinguistics