HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Info-gap decision theory seeks to optimize
robustness Robustness is the property of being strong and healthy in constitution. When it is transposed into a system, it refers to the ability of tolerating perturbations that might affect the system’s functional body. In the same line ''robustness'' ca ...
to failure under severe
uncertainty Uncertainty refers to epistemic situations involving imperfect or unknown information. It applies to predictions of future events, to physical measurements that are already made, or to the unknown. Uncertainty arises in partially observable or ...
,Yakov Ben-Haim, ''Information-Gap Theory: Decisions Under Severe Uncertainty,'' Academic Press, London, 2001.Yakov Ben-Haim, ''Info-Gap Theory: Decisions Under Severe Uncertainty,'' 2nd edition, Academic Press, London, 2006. in particular applying
sensitivity analysis Sensitivity analysis is the study of how the uncertainty in the output of a mathematical model or system (numerical or otherwise) can be divided and allocated to different sources of uncertainty in its inputs. A related practice is uncertainty anal ...
of the
stability radius In mathematics, the stability radius of an object (system, function, matrix, parameter) at a given nominal point is the radius of the largest ball, centered at the nominal point, all of whose elements satisfy pre-determined stability condition ...
type to perturbations in the value of a given estimate of the parameter of interest. It has some connections with
Wald's maximin model In decision theory and game theory, Wald's maximin model is a non-probabilistic decision-making model according to which decisions are ranked on the basis of their worst-case outcomes – the optimal decision is one with the least bad worst outco ...
; some authors distinguish them, others consider them instances of the same principle. It has been developed b
Yakov Ben-Haim
and has found many
applications Application may refer to: Mathematics and computing * Application software, computer software designed to help the user to perform specific tasks ** Application layer, an abstraction layer that specifies protocols and interface methods used in a c ...
and described as a theory for decision-making under "''severe'' uncertainty". It has been criticized as unsuited for this purpose, and
alternatives Founded in 1994, Alternatives, Action and Communication Network for International Development, is a non-governmental, international solidarity organization based in Montreal, Quebec, Canada. Alternatives works to promote justice and equality a ...
proposed, including such classical approaches as
robust optimization Robust optimization is a field of mathematical optimization theory that deals with optimization problems in which a certain measure of robustness is sought against uncertainty that can be represented as deterministic variability in the value of the ...
.


Summary

Info-gap is a theory: it assists in decisions under uncertainty. It does this by using models, each built on the last. One begins with a ''model'' for the situation, where some ''parameter'' or parameters are unknown. Then takes an ''estimate'' for the parameter, and one analyzes how ''sensitive'' the ''outcomes'' under the model are to the error in this estimate. ;Uncertainty model: Starting from the estimate, an uncertainty model measures how far away other values of the parameter are: as uncertainty increases, the set of values increase. ;Robustness/opportuneness model: Given an uncertainty model, then for each decision, how uncertain can you be and be confident succeeding? (robustness) Also, given a windfall, how uncertain must you be for this result to be plausible? (opportuneness) ;Decision-making model: One optimizes the robustness on the basis of the model. Given an outcome, which decision can stand the most uncertainty and give the outcome? Also, given a windfall, which decision requires the ''least'' uncertainty for the outcome?


Models

Info-gap theory models uncertainty as subsets \mathcal(\alpha, \tilde) around a
point estimate In statistics, point estimation involves the use of sample data to calculate a single value (known as a point estimate since it identifies a point in some parameter space) which is to serve as a "best guess" or "best estimate" of an unknown popu ...
\tilde: the estimate is accurate, and uncertainty increases, in general without bound. The uncertainty measures the "
distance Distance is a numerical or occasionally qualitative measurement of how far apart objects or points are. In physics or everyday usage, distance may refer to a physical length or an estimation based on other criteria (e.g. "two counties over"). ...
" between an estimate and a plausibility – providing an intermediate measure between a point (the
point estimate In statistics, point estimation involves the use of sample data to calculate a single value (known as a point estimate since it identifies a point in some parameter space) which is to serve as a "best guess" or "best estimate" of an unknown popu ...
) and all plausibilities, and giving a sensitivity measure: what is the
margin of error The margin of error is a statistic expressing the amount of random sampling error in the results of a survey. The larger the margin of error, the less confidence one should have that a poll result would reflect the result of a census of the e ...
? Info-gap analysis gives answers to such questions as: * under what level of uncertainty can specific requirements be reliably assured (robustness), and * what level of uncertainty is necessary to achieve certain windfalls (opportuneness). It can be used for
satisficing Satisficing is a decision-making strategy or cognitive heuristic that entails searching through the available alternatives until an acceptability threshold is met. The term ''satisficing'', a portmanteau of ''satisfy'' and ''suffice'', was introduc ...
, as an alternative to
optimizing Mathematical optimization (alternatively spelled ''optimisation'') or mathematical programming is the selection of a best element, with regard to some criterion, from some set of available alternatives. It is generally divided into two subfi ...
in the presence of
uncertainty Uncertainty refers to epistemic situations involving imperfect or unknown information. It applies to predictions of future events, to physical measurements that are already made, or to the unknown. Uncertainty arises in partially observable or ...
or
bounded rationality Bounded rationality is the idea that rationality is limited when individuals make decisions, and under these limitations, rational individuals will select a decision that is satisfactory rather than optimal. Limitations include the difficulty of ...
; see
robust optimization Robust optimization is a field of mathematical optimization theory that deals with optimization problems in which a certain measure of robustness is sought against uncertainty that can be represented as deterministic variability in the value of the ...
for an alternative approach.


Comparison with classical decision theory

In contrast to probabilistic
decision theory Decision theory (or the theory of choice; not to be confused with choice theory) is a branch of applied probability theory concerned with the theory of making decisions based on assigning probabilities to various factors and assigning numerical ...
, info-gap analysis does not use probability distributions: it measures the deviation of errors (differences between the parameter and the estimate), but not the probability of outcomes – in particular, the estimate \tilde is in no sense more or less likely than other points, as info-gap does not use probability. Info-gap, by not using probability distributions, is robust in that it is not sensitive to assumptions on probabilities of outcomes. However, the model of uncertainty does include a notion of "closer" and "more distant" outcomes, and thus includes some assumptions, and is not as robust as simply considering all possible outcomes, as in minimax. Further, it considers a fixed universe \mathfrak, so it is not robust to unexpected (not modeled) events. The connection to
minimax Minimax (sometimes MinMax, MM or saddle point) is a decision rule used in artificial intelligence, decision theory, game theory, statistics, and philosophy for ''mini''mizing the possible loss for a worst case (''max''imum loss) scenario. When de ...
analysis has occasioned some controversy: (Ben-Haim 1999, pp. 271–2) argues that info-gap's robustness analysis, while similar in some ways, is not minimax worst-case analysis, as it does not evaluate decisions over all possible outcomes, while (Sniedovich, 2007) argues that the robustness analysis can be seen as an example of maximin (not minimax). This is discussed in
criticism Criticism is the construction of a judgement about the negative qualities of someone or something. Criticism can range from impromptu comments to a written detailed response. , ''"the act of giving your opinion or judgment about the good or bad q ...
, below, and elaborated in the classical decision theory perspective.


Basic example: budget

As a simple example, consider a worker. They expect to make $20 per week, while if they make under $15 they will be unable to work and will sleep in the street, otherwise they can afford a night's entertainment. Using absolute error model: : where \tilde u = \$20, one can say the robustness is $15, and opportuneness is $20: if they make $20, they will not sleep rough nor feast, and if they make within $20 of $200. But, if they erred by $20, they may sleep rough, while for more than $30, they may find themselves dining in opulence. As stated, this example is only ''descriptive,'' and does not enable any decision making – in applications, one considers alternative decision rules, and often situations with more complex uncertainty. The worker is thinking of moving elsewhere, where accommodation is cheaper. They will earn $26 per week, but hostels costs $20, while entertainment still costs $170. In that case the robustness will be $24, and the opportuneness will be $43. The second case has less robustness and less opportuneness. But, measuring uncertainty by ''relative'' error, : robustness is 20% and opportuneness is 23%, while in the other robustness is 38% and opportuneness is 60%, so moving is less opportune.


Info-gap models

Info-gap can be applied to spaces of functions; in that case the uncertain parameter is a function u(x), with estimate (x), and the nested subsets are sets of functions. One way to describe such a set of functions is by requiring values of ''u'' to be close to values of for all ''x,'' using a family of info-gap models on the ''values.'' For example, the above fraction error model for values becomes the fractional error model for functions by adding a parameter ''x'' to the definition: : \mathcal(\alpha, ) = \left \ , \ \ \ \alpha \ge 0. More generally, if U(\alpha,y) is a family of info-gap models of values, then one obtains an info-gap model of functions in the same way: : \mathcal(\alpha, ) = \left \ , \ \ \ \alpha \ge 0.


Motivation

It is common to make decisions under uncertainty.Here are some examples: In many fields, including
engineering Engineering is the use of scientific method, scientific principles to design and build machines, structures, and other items, including bridges, tunnels, roads, vehicles, and buildings. The discipline of engineering encompasses a broad rang ...
,
economics Economics () is the social science that studies the Production (economics), production, distribution (economics), distribution, and Consumption (economics), consumption of goods and services. Economics focuses on the behaviour and intera ...
,
management Management (or managing) is the administration of an organization, whether it is a business, a nonprofit organization, or a government body. It is the art and science of managing resources of the business. Management includes the activities o ...
,
biological conservation Conservation biology is the study of the conservation of nature and of Earth's biodiversity with the aim of protecting species, their habitats, and ecosystems from excessive rates of extinction and the erosion of biotic interactions. It is an int ...
,
medicine Medicine is the science and practice of caring for a patient, managing the diagnosis, prognosis, prevention, treatment, palliation of their injury or disease, and promoting their health. Medicine encompasses a variety of health care pract ...
,
homeland security Homeland security is an American national security term for "the national effort to ensure a homeland that is safe, secure, and resilient against terrorism and other hazards where American interests, aspirations, and ways of life can thrive" t ...
, and more, analysts use models and data to evaluate and formulate decisions. An info-gap is the disparity between what ''is known'' and what ''needs to be known'' in order to make a reliable and responsible decision. Info-gaps are Knightian uncertainties: a lack of knowledge, an incompleteness of understanding. Info-gaps are non-probabilistic and cannot be insured against or modelled probabilistically. A common info-gap, though not the only kind, is uncertainty in the value of a parameter or of a vector of parameters, such as the durability of a new material or the future rates or return on stocks. Another common info-gap is uncertainty in the shape of a
probability distribution In probability theory and statistics, a probability distribution is the mathematical function that gives the probabilities of occurrence of different possible outcomes for an experiment. It is a mathematical description of a random phenomenon i ...
. Another info-gap is uncertainty in the functional form of a property of the system, such as
friction Friction is the force resisting the relative motion of solid surfaces, fluid layers, and material elements sliding against each other. There are several types of friction: *Dry friction is a force that opposes the relative lateral motion of t ...
force in engineering, or the
Phillips curve The Phillips curve is an economic model, named after William Phillips hypothesizing a correlation between reduction in unemployment and increased rates of wage rises within an economy. While Phillips himself did not state a linked relationship ...
in economics. Another info-gap is in the shape and size of a set of possible vectors or functions. For instance, one may have very little knowledge about the relevant set of cardiac waveforms at the onset of heart failure in a specific individual.
What can be done to make good (or at least the best possible) decisions under conditions of uncertainty? Info-gap robustness analysis evaluates each feasible decision by asking: how much deviation from an estimate of a parameter value, function, or set, is permitted and yet "guarantee" acceptable performance? In everyday terms, the "robustness" of a decision is set by the size of deviation from an estimate that still leads to performance within requirements when using that decision. It is sometimes difficult to judge how much robustness is needed or sufficient. However, according to info-gap theory, the ranking of feasible decisions in terms of their degree of robustness is independent of such judgments. Info-gap theory also proposes an opportuneness function which evaluates the potential for windfall outcomes resulting from favorable uncertainty.


Example: resource allocation


Resource allocation

Suppose you are a project manager, supervising two teams: orange and white. Some revenue at the end of the year will be achieved. You have a limited timescale, and you aim to decide how to space these resources between the orange and white, so that the total revenues are large.


Introducing uncertainty

The actual revenue may be different. For uncertainty level we can define an envelope. Lower uncertainty would correspond to a smaller envelope. These envelopes are called ''info-gap models of uncertainty'', since they describe one's understanding of the uncertainty surrounding the revenue functions. We can find a model for the total revenue. Figure 5 shows the info-gap model of the total revenue.


Robustness

High revenues would typically earn a project manager the senior management's respect, but if the total revenues are below a certain threshold, it will cost said project manager's job. We will define such a threshold as a ''critical revenue'', since total revenues beneath the critical revenue will be considered as failure. This is shown in Figure 6. If the uncertainty will increase, the envelope of uncertainty will become more inclusive, to include instances of the total revenue function that, for the specific allocation, yields a revenue smaller than the critical revenue. The robustness measures the immunity of a decision to failure. A ''robust satisficer'' is a decision maker that prefers choices with higher robustness. If, for some allocation q, the correlation between the critical revenue and the robustness is illustrated, the result is a graph somewhat similar to that in Figure 7. This graph, called ''robustness curve'' of allocation q, has two important features, that are common to (most) robustness curves: # The curve is non-increasing. This captures the notion that when higher requirements (higher critical revenue) are in place, failure to meet the target is more likely (lower robustness). This is the tradeoff between quality and robustness. # At the nominal revenue, that is, when the critical revenue equals the revenue under the nominal model (the estimate of the revenue functions), the robustness is zero. This is since a slight deviation from the estimate may decrease the total revenue. The decision depends on the value of failure.


Opportuneness

As well as the threat of losing your job, the senior management offers you a carrot: if the revenues are ''higher'' than some revenue, you will be rewarded. If the uncertainty will decrease, the envelope of uncertainty will become less inclusive, to exclude all instances of the total revenue function that, for the specific allocation, yields a revenue higher than the windfall revenue. If, for some allocation q, we will illustrate the correlation between the windfall revenue and the robustness, we will have a graph somewhat similar to Figure 10. This graph, called ''opportuneness curve'' of allocation q, has two important features, that are common to (most) opportuneness curves: # The curve is non-decreasing. This captures the notion that when we have higher requirements (higher windfall revenue), we are more immune to failure (higher opportuneness, which is less desirable). That is, we need a more substantial deviation from the estimate in order to achieve our ambitious goal. This is the tradeoff between quality and opportuneness. # At the nominal revenue, that is, when the critical revenue equals the revenue under the nominal model (our estimate of the revenue functions), the opportuneness is zero. This is since no deviation from the estimate is needed in order to achieve the windfall revenue.


Treatment of severe uncertainty

Note that in addition to the results generated by the estimate, two "possible" true values of the revenue are also displayed at a distance from the estimate. As indicated by the picture, since info-gap robustness model applies its Maximin analysis in an immediate neighborhood of the estimate, there is no assurance that the analysis is in fact conducted in the neighborhood of the true value of the revenue. In fact, under conditions of severe uncertainty this—methodologically speaking—is very unlikely. This raises the question: how valid/useful/meaningful are the results? Aren't we sweeping the severity of the uncertainty under the carpet? For example, suppose that a given allocation is found to be very fragile in the neighborhood of the estimate. Does this mean that this allocation is also fragile elsewhere in the region of uncertainty? Conversely, what guarantee is there that an allocation that is robust in the neighborhood of the estimate is also robust elsewhere in the region of uncertainty, indeed in the neighborhood of the true value of the revenue? More fundamentally, given that the results generated by info-gap are based on a local revenue/allocation analysis in the neighborhood of an estimate that is likely to be substantially wrong, we have no other choice—methodologically speaking—but to assume that the results generated by this analysis are equally likely to be substantially wrong. In other words, in accordance with the universal Garbage In - Garbage Out Axiom, we have to assume that the quality of the results generated by info-gap's analysis is only as good as the quality of the estimate on which the results are based. The picture speaks for itself. What emerges then is that info-gap theory is yet to explain in what way, if any, it actually attempts to deal with the severity of the uncertainty under consideration. Subsequent sections of this article will address this severity issue and its methodological and practical implications. A more detailed analysis of an illustrative numerical investment problem of this type can be found in Sniedovich (2007).


Uncertainty models

Info-gaps are quantified by info-gap models of uncertainty. An info-gap model is an unbounded family of nested sets. For example, a frequently encountered example is a family of nested
ellipsoid An ellipsoid is a surface that may be obtained from a sphere by deforming it by means of directional scalings, or more generally, of an affine transformation. An ellipsoid is a quadric surface;  that is, a surface that may be defined as the ...
s all having the same shape. The structure of the sets in an info-gap model derives from the information about the uncertainty. In general terms, the structure of an info-gap model of uncertainty is chosen to define the smallest or strictest family of sets whose elements are consistent with the prior information. Since there is, usually, no known worst case, the family of sets may be unbounded. A common example of an info-gap model is the fractional error model. The best estimate of an uncertain function u(x)\!\, is (x), but the fractional error of this estimate is unknown. The following unbounded family of nested sets of functions is a fractional-error info-gap model: : \mathcal(\alpha, ) = \left \ , \ \ \ \alpha \ge 0 At any horizon of uncertainty \alpha, the set \mathcal(\alpha, ) contains all functions u(x)\!\, whose fractional deviation from (x) is no greater than \alpha. However, the horizon of uncertainty is unknown, so the info-gap model is an unbounded family of sets, and there is no worst case or greatest deviation. There are many other types of info-gap models of uncertainty. All info-gap models obey two basic
axiom An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or f ...
s: *Nesting. The info-gap model \mathcal(\alpha, ) is nested if \alpha < \alpha^\prime implies that: :: \mathcal(\alpha, ) \ \subseteq \ \mathcal(\alpha^\prime, ) *Contraction. The info-gap model \mathcal(0,) is a singleton set containing its center point: :: \mathcal(0,) = \ The nesting axiom imposes the property of "clustering" which is characteristic of info-gap uncertainty. Furthermore, the nesting axiom implies that the uncertainty sets \mathcal(\alpha, u) become more inclusive as \alpha grows, thus endowing \alpha with its meaning as a horizon of uncertainty. The contraction axiom implies that, at horizon of uncertainty zero, the estimate is correct. Recall that the uncertain element u may be a parameter, vector, function or set. The info-gap model is then an unbounded family of nested sets of parameters, vectors, functions or sets.


Sublevel sets

For a fixed point estimate \tilde, an info-gap model is often equivalent to a function \phi\colon \mathfrak \to [0,+\infty) defined as: :\phi(u) := \min \ meaning "the uncertainty of a point ''u'' is the minimum uncertainty such that ''u'' is in the set with that uncertainty". In this case, the family of sets \mathcal(\alpha, \tilde) can be recovered as the sublevel sets of \phi: :\mathcal(\alpha, \tilde) := \phi^([0,\alpha]) meaning: "the nested subset with horizon of uncertainty \alpha consists of all points with uncertainty less than or equal to \alpha". Conversely, given a function \phi\colon \mathfrak \to [0,+\infty), satisfying the axiom \phi^(0) = \ (equivalently, \phi(u) = 0 if and only if u = \tilde), it defines an info-gap model via the sublevel sets. For instance, if the region of uncertainty is a metric space, then the uncertainty function can simply be the distance, \phi(u) := d(\tilde,u), so the nested subsets are simply :\mathcal(\alpha, \tilde) = \. This always defines an info-gap model, as distances are always non-negative (axiom of non-negativity), and satisfies \phi^(0) = \ (info-gap axiom of contraction) because the distance between two points is zero if and only if they are equal (the identity of indiscernibles); nesting follows by construction of sublevel set. Not all info-gap models arise as sublevel sets: for instance, if u_1 \in \mathcal(\alpha, \tilde) for all \alpha > 1, but not for \alpha = 1 (it has uncertainty "just more" than 1), then the minimum above is not defined; one can replace it by an
infimum In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; plural infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is a greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. Consequently, the term ''greatest low ...
, but then the resulting sublevel sets will not agree with the infogap model: u_1 \in \phi^( ,1, but u_1 \not\in \mathcal(1, \tilde). The effect of this distinction is very minor, however, as it modifies sets by less than changing the horizon of uncertainty by any positive number \epsilon, however small.


Robustness and opportuneness

Uncertainty may be either
pernicious ''Pernicious'' is a Thai-American supernatural horror film directed by James Cullen Bressack, who also wrote the story along with co-writer Taryn Hillin. The film stars Ciara Hanna, Emily O'Brien, and Jackie Moore. Cast * Ciara Hanna as ...
or propitious. That is, uncertain variations may be either adverse or favorable. Adversity entails the possibility of failure, while favorability is the opportunity for sweeping success. Info-gap decision theory is based on quantifying these two aspects of uncertainty, and choosing an action which addresses one or the other or both of them simultaneously. The pernicious and propitious aspects of uncertainty are quantified by two "immunity functions": the robustness function expresses the immunity to failure, while the opportuneness function expresses the immunity to windfall gain.


Robustness and opportuneness functions

The robustness function expresses the greatest level of uncertainty at which failure cannot occur; the opportuneness function is the least level of uncertainty which entails the possibility of sweeping success. The robustness and opportuneness functions address, respectively, the pernicious and propitious facets of uncertainty. Let q be a decision vector of parameters such as design variables, time of initiation, model parameters or operational options. We can verbally express the robustness and opportuneness functions as the maximum or minimum of a set of values of the uncertainty parameter \alpha of an info-gap model: : Formally, : We can "read" eq. (1) as follows. The robustness (q) of decision vector q is the greatest value of the horizon of uncertainty \alpha for which specified minimal requirements are ''always'' satisfied. (q) expresses robustness — the degree of resistance to uncertainty and immunity against failure — so a large value of (q) is desirable. Robustness is defined as a ''worst-case'' scenario up to the horizon of uncertainty: how large can the horizon of uncertainty be and still, even in the worst case, achieve the critical level of outcome? Eq. (2) states that the opportuneness (q) is the least level of uncertainty \alpha which must be tolerated in order to enable the ''possibility'' of sweeping success as a result of decisions q. (q) is the immunity against windfall reward, so a small value of (q) is desirable. A small value of (q) reflects the opportune situation that great reward is possible even in the presence of little ambient uncertainty. Opportuneness is defined as a ''best-case'' scenario up to the horizon of uncertainty: how small can the horizon of uncertainty be and still, in the best case, achieve the windfall reward? The immunity functions (q) and (q) are complementary and are defined in an anti-symmetric sense. Thus "bigger is better" for (q) while "big is bad" for (q). The immunity functions — robustness and opportuneness — are the basic decision functions in info-gap decision theory.


Optimization

The robustness function involves a maximization, but not of the performance or outcome of the decision: in general the outcome could be arbitrarily bad. Rather, it maximizes the level of uncertainty that would be required for the outcome to fail. The greatest tolerable uncertainty is found at which decision q satisfices the performance at a critical survival-level. One may establish one's preferences among the available actions q, \, q^\prime,\, \ldots according to their robustnesses (q),\, (q^\prime), \, \ldots , whereby larger robustness engenders higher preference. In this way the robustness function underlies a satisficing decision algorithm which maximizes the immunity to pernicious uncertainty. The opportuneness function in eq. (2) involves a minimization, however not, as might be expected, of the damage which can accrue from unknown adverse events. The least horizon of uncertainty is sought at which decision q enables (but does not necessarily guarantee) large windfall gain. Unlike the robustness function, the opportuneness function does not satisfice, it "windfalls". Windfalling preferences are those which prefer actions for which the opportuneness function takes a small value. When (q) is used to choose an action q, one is "windfalling" by optimizing the opportuneness from propitious uncertainty in an attempt to enable highly ambitious goals or rewards. Given a scalar reward function R(q,u), depending on the decision vector q and the info-gap-uncertain function u, the minimal requirement in eq. (1) is that the reward R(q,u) be no less than a critical value . Likewise, the sweeping success in eq. (2) is attainment of a "wildest dream" level of reward which is much greater than . Usually neither of these threshold values, and , is chosen irrevocably before performing the decision analysis. Rather, these parameters enable the decision maker to explore a range of options. In any case the windfall reward is greater, usually much greater, than the critical reward : : > The robustness and opportuneness functions of eqs. (1) and (2) can now be expressed more explicitly: : (q, ) is the greatest level of uncertainty consistent with guaranteed reward no less than the critical reward , while (q, ) is the least level of uncertainty which must be accepted in order to facilitate (but not guarantee) windfall as great as . The complementary or anti-symmetric structure of the immunity functions is evident from eqs. (3) and (4). These definitions can be modified to handle multi-criterion reward functions. Likewise, analogous definitions apply when R(q,u) is a loss rather than a reward.


Decision rules

Based on these function, one can then decided on a course of action by optimizing for uncertainty: choose the decision which is most robust (can withstand the greatest uncertainty; "satisficing"), or choose the decision which requires the least uncertainty to achieve a windfall. Formally, optimizing for robustness or optimizing for opportuneness yields a
preference relation The term preference relation is used to refer to orderings that describe human preferences for one thing over an other. * In mathematics, preferences may be modeled as a weak ordering or a semiorder, two different types of binary relation. One speci ...
on the set of decisions, and the
decision rule In decision theory, a decision rule is a function which maps an observation to an appropriate action. Decision rules play an important role in the theory of statistics and economics, and are closely related to the concept of a strategy (game theory ...
is the "optimize with respect to this preference". In the below, let \mathcal be the set of all available or feasible decision vectors q.


Robust-satisficing

The robustness function generates robust-satisficing preferences on the options: decisions are ranked in increasing order of robustness, for a given critical reward, i.e., by (q, ) value, meaning q \succ _ q^\prime if (q, ) > (q^\prime, ). A robust-satisficing decision is one which ''maximizes'' the robustness and satisfices the performance at the critical level . Denote the maximum robustness by \hat, (formally \hat(), for the maximum robustness for a given critical reward), and the corresponding decision (or decisions) by \hat_ (formally, (), the critical optimizing action for a given level of critical reward): :\begin \hat() &= \max_ (q, )\\ () &= \arg \max_ (q, ) \end Usually, though not invariably, the robust-satisficing action () depends on the critical reward .


Opportune-windfalling

Conversely, one may optimize opportuneness: the opportuneness function generates opportune-windfalling preferences on the options: decisions are ranked in ''decreasing'' order of opportuneness, for a given windfall reward, i.e., by (q, ) value, meaning q \succ _ q^\prime if (q, ) < (q^\prime, ). The opportune-windfalling decision, (), ''minimizes'' the opportuneness function on the set of available decisions. Denote the minimum opportuneness by \hat, (formally \hat(), for the minimum opportuneness for a given windfall reward), and the corresponding decision (or decisions) by \hat_ (formally, (), the windfall optimizing action for a given level of windfall reward): :\begin \hat () &= \min_ (q, )\\ () &= \arg \min_ (q, ) \end The two preference rankings, as well as the corresponding the optimal decisions () and (), may be different, and may vary depending on the values of and .


Applications

Info-gap theory has generated a lot of literature. Info-gap theory has been studied or applied in a range of applications including engineering, Yakov Ben-Haim, 2005, Info-gap Decision Theory For Engineering Design. Or: Why `Good' is Preferable to `Best', appearing as chapter 11 in ''Engineering Design Reliability Handbook'', Edited by Efstratios Nikolaidis, Dan M.Ghiocel and Surendra Singhal, CRC Press, Boca Raton. Kaihong Wang, 2005, Vibration Analysis of Cracked Composite Bending-torsion Beams for Damage Diagnosis, PhD thesis, Virginia Politechnic Institute, Blacksburg, Virginia. biological conservation, Burgman, Mark, 2005, ''Risks and Decisions for Conservation and Environmental Management'', Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. theoretical biology, homeland security, economics, project management and statistics. Foundational issues related to info-gap theory have also been studied. The remainder of this section describes in a little more detail the kind of uncertainties addressed by info-gap theory. Although many published works are mentioned below, no attempt is made here to present insights from these papers. The emphasis is not upon elucidation of the concepts of info-gap theory, but upon the context where it is used and the goals.


Engineering

A typical engineering application is the vibration analysis of a cracked beam, where the location, size, shape and orientation of the crack is unknown and greatly influence the vibration dynamics. Very little is usually known about these spatial and geometrical uncertainties. The info-gap analysis allows one to model these uncertainties, and to determine the degree of robustness - to these uncertainties - of properties such as vibration amplitude, natural frequencies, and natural modes of vibration. Another example is the structural design of a building subject to uncertain loads such as from wind or earthquakes. The response of the structure depends strongly on the spatial and temporal distribution of the loads. However, storms and earthquakes are highly idiosyncratic events, and the interaction between the event and the structure involves very site-specific mechanical properties which are rarely known. The info-gap analysis enables the design of the structure to enhance structural immunity against uncertain deviations from design-base or estimated worst-case loads. Another engineering application involves the design of a neural net for detecting faults in a mechanical system, based on real-time measurements. A major difficulty is that faults are highly idiosyncratic, so that training data for the neural net will tend to differ substantially from data obtained from real-time faults after the net has been trained. The info-gap robustness strategy enables one to design the neural net to be robust to the disparity between training data and future real events.


Biology

The conservation biologist faces info-gaps in using biological models. They use info-gap robustness curves to select among management options for spruce-budworm populations in Eastern Canada. Burgman uses the fact that the robustness curves of different alternatives can intersect.


Project management

Project management is another area where info-gap uncertainty is common. The project manager often has very limited information about the duration and cost of some of the tasks in the project, and info-gap robustness can assist in project planning and integration. Financial economics is another area where the future is fraught with surprises, which may be either pernicious or propitious. Info-gap robustness and opportuneness analyses can assist in portfolio design,
credit rationing Credit rationing is the limiting by lenders of the supply of additional credit to borrowers who demand funds at a set quoted rate by the financial institution. It is an example of market failure, as the price mechanism fails to bring about equil ...
, and other applications.


Limitations

In applying info-gap theory, one must remain aware of certain limitations. Firstly, info-gap makes assumptions, namely on universe in question, and the degree of uncertainty – the info-gap model is a model of degrees of uncertainty or similarity of various assumptions, within a given universe. Info-gap does not make probability assumptions within this universe – it is non-probabilistic – but does quantify a notion of "distance from the estimate". In brief, info-gap makes ''fewer'' assumptions than a probabilistic method, but does make some assumptions. For instance, a simple model of daily stock market returns – which by definition fall in the range 100\%,+\infty\%) – may include extreme moves such as Black Monday (1987) but might not model the market breakdowns following the September 11 attacks: it considers the "known unknowns", not the "unknown unknowns". This is a general criticism of much
decision theory Decision theory (or the theory of choice; not to be confused with choice theory) is a branch of applied probability theory concerned with the theory of making decisions based on assigning probabilities to various factors and assigning numerical ...
, and is by no means specific to info-gap, but info-gap is not immune to it. Secondly, there is no natural scale: is uncertainty of \alpha = 1 small or large? Different models of uncertainty give different scales, and require judgment and understanding of the domain and the model of uncertainty. Similarly, measuring differences between outcomes requires judgment and understanding of the domain. Thirdly, if the universe under consideration is larger than a significant horizon of uncertainty, and outcomes for these distant points are significantly different from points near the estimate, then conclusions of robustness or opportuneness analyses will generally be: "one must be very confident of one's assumptions, else outcomes may be expected to vary significantly from projections" – a cautionary conclusion.


Disclaimer and summary

The robustness and opportuneness functions can inform decision. For example, a change in decision increasing robustness may increase or decrease opportuneness. From a subjective stance, robustness and opportuneness both trade-off against aspiration for outcome: robustness and opportuneness deteriorate as the decision maker's aspirations increase. Robustness is zero for model-best anticipated outcomes. Robustness curves for alternative decisions may cross as a function of aspiration, implying reversal of preference. Various theorems identify conditions where larger info-gap robustness implies larger probability of success, regardless of the underlying probability distribution. However, these conditions are technical, and do not translate into any common-sense, verbal recommendations, limiting such applications of info-gap theory by non-experts.


Criticism

A general criticism of non-probabilistic decision rules, discussed in detail at decision theory: alternatives to probability theory, is that optimal decision rules (formally,
admissible decision rule In statistical decision theory, an admissible decision rule is a rule for making a decision such that there is no other rule that is always "better" than it (or at least sometimes better and never worse), in the precise sense of "better" defined ...
s) can ''always'' be derived by probabilistic methods, with a suitable
utility function As a topic of economics, utility is used to model worth or value. Its usage has evolved significantly over time. The term was introduced initially as a measure of pleasure or happiness as part of the theory of utilitarianism by moral philosoph ...
and
prior distribution In Bayesian statistical inference, a prior probability distribution, often simply called the prior, of an uncertain quantity is the probability distribution that would express one's beliefs about this quantity before some evidence is taken int ...
(this is the statement of the complete class theorems), and thus that non-probabilistic methods such as info-gap are unnecessary and do not yield new or better decision rules. A more general criticism of decision making under uncertainty is the impact of outsized, unexpected events, ones that are not captured by the model. This is discussed particularly in
black swan theory The black swan theory or theory of black swan events is a metaphor that describes an event that comes as a surprise, has a major effect, and is often inappropriately rationalized after the fact with the benefit of hindsight. The term is based o ...
, and info-gap, used in isolation, is vulnerable to this, as are a fortiori all decision theories that use a fixed universe of possibilities, notably probabilistic ones. Sniedovich raises two points to info-gap decision theory, one substantive, one scholarly: ;1. the info-gap uncertainty model is flawed and oversold: One should consider the range of possibilities, not its subsets. Sniedovich argues that info-gap decision theory is therefore a "voodoo decision theory." ;2. info-gap is maximin: Ben-Haim states (Ben-Haim 1999, pp. 271–2) that "robust reliability is emphatically not a in-maxworst-case analysis". Note that Ben-Haim compares info-gap to ''minimax,'' while Sniedovich considers it a case of ''maximin.'' Sniedovich has challenged the validity of info-gap theory for making decisions under severe uncertainty. Sniedovich notes that the info-gap robustness function is "local" to the region around \displaystyle \tilde, where \displaystyle \tilde is likely to be substantially in error.


Maximin

Symbolically, max \alpha assuming min (worst-case) outcome, or maximin. In other words, while it is not a maximin analysis of outcome over the universe of uncertainty, it is a maximin analysis over a properly construed decision space. Ben-Haim argues that info-gap's robustness model is not min-max/maximin analysis because it is not worst-case analysis of ''outcomes;'' it is a
satisficing Satisficing is a decision-making strategy or cognitive heuristic that entails searching through the available alternatives until an acceptability threshold is met. The term ''satisficing'', a portmanteau of ''satisfy'' and ''suffice'', was introduc ...
model, not an optimization model – a (straightforward) maximin analysis would consider worst-case outcomes over the entire space which, since uncertainty is often potentially unbounded, would yield an unbounded bad worst case.


Stability radius

Sniedovich has shown that info-gap's robustness model is a simple
stability radius In mathematics, the stability radius of an object (system, function, matrix, parameter) at a given nominal point is the radius of the largest ball, centered at the nominal point, all of whose elements satisfy pre-determined stability condition ...
model, namely a local stability model of the generic form :\hat(\tilde):= \max \ \ where B(\rho,\tilde) denotes a
ball A ball is a round object (usually spherical, but can sometimes be ovoid) with several uses. It is used in ball games, where the play of the game follows the state of the ball as it is hit, kicked or thrown by players. Balls can also be used f ...
of radius \rho centered at \tilde and P(s) denotes the set of values of p that satisfy pre-determined stability conditions. In other words, info-gap's robustness model is a stability radius model characterized by a stability requirement of the form r_\le R(q,p). Since stability radius models are designed for the analysis of small perturbations in a given nominal value of a parameter, Sniedovich argues that info-gap's robustness model is unsuitable for the treatment of severe uncertainty characterized by a poor estimate and a vast uncertainty space.


Discussion


Satisficing and bounded rationality

It is correct that the info-gap robustness function is local, and has restricted quantitative value in some cases. However, a major purpose of decision analysis is to provide focus for subjective judgments. That is, regardless of the formal analysis, a framework for discussion is provided. Without entering into any particular framework, or characteristics of frameworks in general, discussion follows about proposals for such frameworks. Simon introduced the idea of
bounded rationality Bounded rationality is the idea that rationality is limited when individuals make decisions, and under these limitations, rational individuals will select a decision that is satisfactory rather than optimal. Limitations include the difficulty of ...
. Limitations on knowledge, understanding, and computational capability constrain the ability of decision makers to identify optimal choices. Simon advocated
satisficing Satisficing is a decision-making strategy or cognitive heuristic that entails searching through the available alternatives until an acceptability threshold is met. The term ''satisficing'', a portmanteau of ''satisfy'' and ''suffice'', was introduc ...
rather than optimizing: seeking adequate (rather than optimal) outcomes given available resources. Schwartz, Conlisk and others discuss extensive evidence for the phenomenon of bounded rationality among human decision makers, as well as for the advantages of satisficing when knowledge and understanding are deficient. The info-gap robustness function provides a means of implementing a satisficing strategy under bounded rationality. For instance, in discussing bounded rationality and satisficing in conservation and environmental management, Burgman notes that "Info-gap theory ... can function sensibly when there are 'severe' knowledge gaps." The info-gap robustness and opportuneness functions provide "a formal framework to explore the kinds of speculations that occur intuitively when examining decision options." Burgman then proceeds to develop an info-gap robust-satisficing strategy for protecting the endangered orange-bellied parrot. Similarly, Vinot, Cogan and Cipolla discuss engineering design and note that "the downside of a model-based analysis lies in the knowledge that the model behavior is only an approximation to the real system behavior. Hence the question of the honest designer: how sensitive is my measure of design success to uncertainties in my system representation? ... It is evident that if model-based analysis is to be used with any level of confidence then ...
ne must NE, Ne or ne may refer to: Arts and entertainment * Neutral Evil, an alignment in the American role-playing game ''Dungeons & Dragons'' * New Edition, an American vocal group * Nicomachean Ethics, a collection of ten books by Greek philosopher A ...
attempt to satisfy an acceptable sub-optimal level of performance while remaining maximally robust to the system uncertainties." They proceed to develop an info-gap robust-satisficing design procedure for an aerospace application.


Alternatives

Of course, decision in the face of uncertainty is nothing new, and attempts to deal with it have a long history. A number of authors have noted and discussed similarities and differences between info-gap robustness and
minimax Minimax (sometimes MinMax, MM or saddle point) is a decision rule used in artificial intelligence, decision theory, game theory, statistics, and philosophy for ''mini''mizing the possible loss for a worst case (''max''imum loss) scenario. When de ...
or worst-case methods Z. Ben-Haim and Y. C. Eldar, Maximum set estimators with bounded estimation error, ''IEEE Trans. Signal Process.'', vol. 53, no. 8, August 2005, pp. 3172-3182. . Sniedovich has demonstrated formally that the info-gap robustness function can be represented as a maximin optimization, and is thus related to Wald's minimax theory. Sniedovich has claimed that info-gap's robustness analysis is conducted in the neighborhood of an estimate that is likely to be substantially wrong, concluding that the resulting robustness function is equally likely to be substantially wrong. On the other hand, the estimate is the best one has, so it is useful to know if it can err greatly and still yield an acceptable outcome. This critical question clearly raises the issue of whether robustness (as defined by info-gap theory) is qualified to judge whether confidence is warranted,Yakov Ben-Haim, ''Robust Reliability in the Mechanical Science,'' Springer, Berlin ,1996. and how it compares to methods used to inform decisions under uncertainty using considerations not limited to the neighborhood of a bad initial guess. Answers to these questions vary with the particular problem at hand. Some general comments follow.


Sensitivity analysis

Sensitivity analysis Sensitivity analysis is the study of how the uncertainty in the output of a mathematical model or system (numerical or otherwise) can be divided and allocated to different sources of uncertainty in its inputs. A related practice is uncertainty anal ...
– how sensitive conclusions are to input assumptions – can be performed independently of a model of uncertainty: most simply, one may take two different assumed values for an input and compares the conclusions. From this perspective, info-gap can be seen as a technique of sensitivity analysis, though by no means the only.


Robust optimization

The robust optimization literature P. Kouvelis and G. Yu, 1997, Robust Discrete Optimization and Its Applications, Kluwer.B. Rustem and M. Howe, 2002, Algorithms for Worst-case Design and Applications to Risk Management, Princeton University Press.R.J. Lempert, S.W. Popper, and S.C. Bankes, 2003, Shaping the Next One Hundred Years: New Methods for Quantitative, Long-Term Policy Analysis, The Rand Corporation.A. Ben-Tal, L. El Ghaoui, and A. Nemirovski, 2006, Mathematical Programming, Special issue on Robust Optimization, Volume 107(1-2). provides methods and techniques that take a global approach to robustness analysis. These methods directly address decision under severe uncertainty, and have been used for this purpose for more than thirty years now.
Wald WALD (1080 kHz) is an AM radio station licensed to Johnsonville, South Carolina. The station is part of the Worship and Word Network and is owned by Glory Communications, Inc., based in St. Stephen, South Carolina. It carries an Urban Gosp ...
's Maximin model is the main instrument used by these methods. The principal difference between the Maximin model employed by info-gap and the various Maximin models employed by robust optimization methods is in the manner in which the total region of uncertainty is incorporated in the robustness model. Info-gap takes a local approach that concentrates on the immediate neighborhood of the estimate. In sharp contrast, robust optimization methods set out to incorporate in the analysis the entire region of uncertainty, or at least an adequate representation thereof. In fact, some of these methods do not even use an estimate.


Comparative analysis

Classical decision theory,Resnik, M.D., ''Choices: an Introduction to Decision Theory,'' University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, MN, 1987.French, S.D., ''Decision Theory,'' Ellis Horwood, 1988. offers two approaches to decision-making under severe uncertainty, namely maximin and Laplaces'
principle of insufficient reason The principle of indifference (also called principle of insufficient reason) is a rule for assigning epistemic probabilities. The principle of indifference states that in the absence of any relevant evidence, agents should distribute their cre ...
(assume all outcomes equally likely); these may be considered alternative solutions to the problem info-gap addresses. Further, as discussed at decision theory: alternatives to probability theory, probabilists, particularly Bayesians probabilists, argue that optimal decision rules (formally,
admissible decision rule In statistical decision theory, an admissible decision rule is a rule for making a decision such that there is no other rule that is always "better" than it (or at least sometimes better and never worse), in the precise sense of "better" defined ...
s) can ''always'' be derived by probabilistic methods (this is the statement of the
complete class theorems In statistics, completeness is a property of a statistic in relation to a model for a set of observed data. In essence, it ensures that the distributions corresponding to different values of the parameters are distinct. It is closely related t ...
), and thus that non-probabilistic methods such as info-gap are unnecessary and do not yield new or better decision rules.


Maximin

As attested by the rich literature on
robust optimization Robust optimization is a field of mathematical optimization theory that deals with optimization problems in which a certain measure of robustness is sought against uncertainty that can be represented as deterministic variability in the value of the ...
, maximin provides a wide range of methods for decision making in the face of severe uncertainty. Indeed, as discussed in criticism of info-gap decision theory, info-gap's robustness model can be interpreted as an instance of the general maximin model.


Bayesian analysis

As for Laplaces'
principle of insufficient reason The principle of indifference (also called principle of insufficient reason) is a rule for assigning epistemic probabilities. The principle of indifference states that in the absence of any relevant evidence, agents should distribute their cre ...
, in this context it is convenient to view it as an instance of
Bayesian analysis Bayesian inference is a method of statistical inference in which Bayes' theorem is used to update the probability for a hypothesis as more evidence or information becomes available. Bayesian inference is an important technique in statistics, and e ...
. The essence of the
Bayesian analysis Bayesian inference is a method of statistical inference in which Bayes' theorem is used to update the probability for a hypothesis as more evidence or information becomes available. Bayesian inference is an important technique in statistics, and e ...
is applying probabilities for different possible realizations of the uncertain parameters. In the case of Knightian (non-probabilistic) uncertainty, these probabilities represent the decision maker's "degree of belief" in a specific realization. In our example, suppose there are only five possible realizations of the uncertain revenue to allocation function. The decision maker believes that the estimated function is the most likely, and that the likelihood decreases as the difference from the estimate increases. Figure 11 exemplifies such a probability distribution. Now, for any allocation, one can construct a probability distribution of the revenue, based on his prior beliefs. The decision maker can then choose the allocation with the highest expected revenue, with the lowest probability for an unacceptable revenue, etc. The most problematic step of this analysis is the choice of the realizations probabilities. When there is an extensive and relevant past experience, an expert may use this experience to construct a probability distribution. But even with extensive past experience, when some parameters change, the expert may only be able to estimate that A is more likely than B, but will not be able to reliably quantify this difference. Furthermore, when conditions change drastically, or when there is no past experience at all, it may prove to be difficult even estimating whether A is more likely than B. Nevertheless, methodologically speaking, this difficulty is not as problematic as basing the analysis of a problem subject to severe uncertainty on a single point estimate and its immediate neighborhood, as done by info-gap. And what is more, contrary to info-gap, this approach is global, rather than local. Still, it must be stressed that Bayesian analysis does not expressly concern itself with the question of robustness. Bayesian analysis raises the issue of ''learning from experience'' and adjusting probabilities accordingly. In other words, decision is not a one-stop process, but profits from a sequence of decisions and observations.


Classical decision theory perspective

Sniedovich raises two points to info-gap, from the point of view of classical decision theory, one substantive, one scholarly: ;the info-gap uncertainty model is flawed and oversold: Under severe uncertainty, one should use ''global'' decision theory , not ''local'' decision theory. ;info-gap is maximin: Ben-Haim (2006, p.xii) claims that info-gap is "radically different from all current theories of decision under uncertainty,". Ben-Haim states (Ben-Haim 1999, pp. 271–2) that "robust reliability is emphatically not a in-maxworst-case analysis". Sniedovich has challenged the validity of info-gap theory for making decisions under severe uncertainty. In the framework of classical
decision theory Decision theory (or the theory of choice; not to be confused with choice theory) is a branch of applied probability theory concerned with the theory of making decisions based on assigning probabilities to various factors and assigning numerical ...
, info-gap's robustness model can be construed as an instance of
Wald WALD (1080 kHz) is an AM radio station licensed to Johnsonville, South Carolina. The station is part of the Worship and Word Network and is owned by Glory Communications, Inc., based in St. Stephen, South Carolina. It carries an Urban Gosp ...
's Maximin model and its opportuneness model is an instance of the classical Minimin model. Both operate in the neighborhood of an estimate of the parameter of interest whose true value is subject to ''severe'' uncertainty and therefore is likely to be ''substantially wrong''. Moreover, the considerations brought to bear upon the decision process itself also originate in the locality of this unreliable estimate, and so may or may not be reflective of the entire range of decisions and uncertainties.


Background, working assumptions, and a look ahead

Now, as portrayed in the info-gap literature, Info-Gap was designed expressly as a methodology for solving decision problems that are subject to severe uncertainty. And what is more, its aim is to seek solutions that are robust. Thus, to have a clear picture of info-gap's modus operandi and its role and place in decision theory and robust optimization, it is imperative to examine it within this context. In other words, it is necessary to establish info-gap's relation to classical decision theory and robust optimization. To this end, the following questions must be addressed: * What are the characteristics of decision problems that are subject to severe uncertainty? * What difficulties arise in the modelling and solution of such problems? * What type of robustness is sought? * How does info-gap theory address these issues? * In what way is info-gap decision theory similar to and/or different from other theories for decision under uncertainty? Two important points need to be elucidated in this regard at the outset: * Considering the severity of the uncertainty that info-gap was designed to tackle, it is essential to clarify the difficulties posed by severe uncertainty. * Since info-gap is a non-probabilistic method that seeks to maximize robustness to uncertainty, it is imperative to compare it to the single most important "non-probabilistic" model in classical decision theory, namely Wald's Maximin paradigm (Wald 1945, 1950). After all, this paradigm has dominated the scene in classical decision theory for well over sixty years now. So, first let us clarify the assumptions that are implied by severe uncertainty.


Working assumptions

Info-gap decision theory employs three simple constructs to capture the uncertainty associated with decision problems: # A parameter \displaystyle u whose true value is subject to severe uncertainty. # A region of uncertainty \displaystyle \mathfrak\ where the true value of \displaystyle u \ lies. # An estimate \ \displaystyle \tilde\ of the true value of \displaystyle u \ . It should be pointed out, though, that as such these constructs are generic, meaning that they can be employed to model situations where the uncertainty is not severe but mild, indeed very mild. So it is vital to be clear that to give apt expression to the severity of the uncertainty, in the Info-Gap framework these three constructs are given specific meaning.
# The region of uncertainty \displaystyle \mathfrak\ is relatively large.
In fact, Ben-Haim (2006, p. 210) indicates that in the context of info-gap decision theory most of the commonly encountered regions of uncertainty are unbounded. # The estimate \displaystyle \tilde\ is a poor approximation of the true value of \displaystyle \ u\ .
That is, the estimate is a poor indication of the true value of \displaystyle \ u\ (Ben-Haim, 2006, p. 280) and is likely to be substantially wrong (Ben-Haim, 2006, p. 281). In the picture \displaystyle u^\ represents the true (unknown) value of \ \displaystyle u\ . The point to note here is that conditions of severe uncertainty entail that the estimate \displaystyle \tilde\ can—relatively speaking—be very distant from the true value \displaystyle u^\ . This is particularly pertinent for methodologies, like info-gap, that seek robustness to uncertainty. Indeed, assuming otherwise would—methodologically speaking—be tantamount to engaging in wishful thinking.


Wald's Maximin paradigm

The basic idea behind this famous paradigm can be expressed in plain language as follows:
We are to adopt the alternative the worst outcome of which is superior to the worst outcome of the others.
RawlsRawls, J. Theory of Justice, 1971, Belknap Press, Cambridge, MA.(1971, p. 152)
Thus, according to this paradigm, in the framework of decision-making under severe uncertainty, the robustness of an alternative is a measure of how well this alternative can cope with the worst uncertain outcome that it can generate. Needless to say, this attitude towards severe uncertainty often leads to the selection of highly conservative alternatives. This is precisely the reason that this paradigm is not always a satisfactory methodology for decision-making under severe uncertainty (Tintner 1952). As indicated in the overview, info-gap's robustness model is a Maximin model in disguise. More specifically, it is a simple instance of Wald's Maximin model where: # The region of uncertainty associated with an alternative decision is an immediate neighborhood of the estimate \displaystyle \tilde\ . # The uncertain outcomes of an alternative are determined by a characteristic function of the performance requirement under consideration. Thus, aside from the conservatism issue, a far more serious issue must be addressed. This is the validity issue arising from the local nature of info-gap's robustness analysis.


Local vs global robustness

The validity of the results generated by info-gap's robustness analysis are contingent on the quality of the estimate \displaystyle \tilde\ . According to info-gap's own working assumptions, this estimate is poor and likely to be substantially wrong (Ben-Haim, 2006, p. 280-281). The trouble with this feature of info-gap's robustness model is brought out more forcefully by the picture. The white circle represents the immediate neighborhood of the estimate \ \displaystyle \tilde\ on which the Maximin analysis is conducted. Since the region of uncertainty is large and the quality of the estimate is poor, it is very likely that the true value of \ \displaystyle u\ is distant from the point at which the Maximin analysis is conducted. So given the severity of the uncertainty under consideration, how valid/useful can this type of Maximin analysis really be? What extent a local robustness analysis a la Maximin in the immediate neighborhood of a poor estimate can aptly represent a large region of uncertainty. Robust optimization methods invariably take a far more global view of robustness. So much so that scenario planning and scenario generation are central issues in this area. This reflects a strong commitment to an adequate representation of the entire region of uncertainty in the definition of robustness and in the robustness analysis itself. This has to do with the portrayal of info-gap's contribution to the state of the art in decision theory, and its role and place vis-a-vis other methodologies.


Role and place in decision theory

Info-gap is emphatic about its advancement of the state of the art in decision theory (color is used here for emphasis):
Info-gap decision theory is radically different from all current theories of decision under uncertainty. The difference originates in the modelling of uncertainty as an information gap rather than as a probability.
Ben-Haim (2006, p.xii)
In this book we concentrate on the fairly new concept of information-gap uncertainty, whose differences from more classical approaches to uncertainty are real and deep. Despite the power of classical decision theories, in many areas such as engineering, economics, management, medicine and public policy, a need has arisen for a different format for decisions based on severely uncertain evidence.
Ben-Haim (2006, p. 11)
These strong claims must be substantiated. In particular, a clear-cut, unequivocal answer must be given to the following question: in what way is info-gap's generic robustness model different, indeed radically different, from worst-case analysis a la Maximin? Subsequent sections of this article describe various aspects of info-gap decision theory and its applications, how it proposes to cope with the working assumptions outlined above, the local nature of info-gap's robustness analysis and its intimate relationship with Wald's classical Maximin paradigm and worst-case analysis.


Invariance property

The main point to keep in mind here is that info-gap's raison d'être is to provide a methodology for decision under severe uncertainty. This means that its primary test would be in the efficacy of its handling of and coping with severe uncertainty. To this end it must be established first how Info-Gap's robustness/opportuneness models behave/fare, as the severity of the uncertainty is increased/decreased. Second, it must be established whether info-gap's robustness/opportuneness models give adequate expression to the potential variability of the performance function over the entire region of uncertainty. This is particularly important because Info—Gap is usually concerned with relatively large, indeed unbounded, regions of uncertainty. So, let \ \displaystyle \mathfrak \ denote the total region of uncertainty and consider these key questions:
* How does the robustness/opportuneness analysis respond to an increase/decrease in the size of \ \displaystyle \mathfrak \ ? * How does an increase/decrease in the size of \ \displaystyle \mathfrak \ affect the robustness or opportuneness of a decision? * How representative are the results generated by info-gap's robustness/opportuneness analysis of what occurs in the relatively large total region of uncertainty \ \displaystyle \mathfrak \ ?
Suppose then that the robustness \ \displaystyle \hat(q,r_) \ has been computed for a decision \ \displaystyle q\in \mathcal\ and it is observed that \ \displaystyle \ \mathcal(\alpha^,\tilde) \subseteq \mathfrak\ where \ \displaystyle \alpha^=\hat(q,r_) + \varepsilon \   for some \ \displaystyle \varepsilon > 0\ . The question is then: how would the robustness of \ \displaystyle q \ , namely \ \displaystyle \hat(q,r_) \ , be affected if the region of uncertainty would be say, twice as large as \ \displaystyle \mathfrak \ , or perhaps even 10 times as large as \ \displaystyle \mathfrak \ ? Consider then the following result which is a direct consequence of the local nature of info-gap's robustness/opportuneness analysis and the nesting property of info-gaps' regions of uncertainty (Sniedovich 2007):


Invariance theorem

The robustness of decision \ \displaystyle q \ is invariant with the size of the total region of uncertainty \ \displaystyle \mathfrak \ for all \ \displaystyle \mathfrak \ such that : In other words, for any given decision, info-gap's analysis yields the same results for all total regions of uncertainty that contain \ \displaystyle \ \mathcal(\alpha^,\tilde) \ . This applies to both the robustness and opportuneness models. This is illustrated in the picture: the robustness of a given decision does not change notwithstanding an increase in the region of uncertainty from \ \displaystyle \mathfrak \ to \ \displaystyle \mathfrak \ . In short, by dint of focusing exclusively on the immediate neighborhood of the estimate \ \displaystyle \tilde \ info-gap's robustness/opportuneness models are inherently local. For this reason they are -- in principle -- incapable of incorporating in the analysis of \ \displaystyle \hat(q,r_) \ and \ \displaystyle \hat(q,r_) \ regions of uncertainty that lie outside the neighborhoods \mathcal(\hat(q,r_),\tilde)\ and \mathcal(\hat(q,r_),\tilde)\ of the estimate \ \displaystyle \tilde \ , respectively. To illustrate, consider a simple numerical example where the total region of uncertainty is \mathfrak=(-\infty,\infty),\ the estimate is \ \displaystyle \tilde=0 \ and for some decision \ \displaystyle \hat \ we obtain \mathcal(\hat(\hat,r_),\tilde)=(-2,2). The picture is this: where the term '' "No man's land" ''  refers to the part of the total region of uncertainty that is outside the region \ \displaystyle \mathcal(\hat(q,r_)+\varepsilon,\tilde) \ . Note that in this case the robustness of decision \ \displaystyle \hat \ is based on its (worst-case) performance over no more than a minuscule part of the total region of uncertainty that is an immediate neighborhood of the estimate \ \displaystyle \tilde \ . Since usually info-gap's total region of uncertainty is unbounded, this illustration represents a ''usual''   case rather than an exception. Info-gap's robustness/opportuneness are by definition local properties. As such they cannot assess the performance of decisions over the total region of uncertainty. For this reason it is not clear how Info-Gap's Robustness/Opportuneness models can provide a meaningful/sound/useful basis for decision under severe uncertainty where the estimate is poor and is likely to be substantially wrong. This crucial issue is addressed in subsequent sections of this article.


Maximin/Minimin: playing robustness/opportuneness games with Nature

For well over sixty years now
Wald WALD (1080 kHz) is an AM radio station licensed to Johnsonville, South Carolina. The station is part of the Worship and Word Network and is owned by Glory Communications, Inc., based in St. Stephen, South Carolina. It carries an Urban Gosp ...
's Maximin model has figured in classical
decision theory Decision theory (or the theory of choice; not to be confused with choice theory) is a branch of applied probability theory concerned with the theory of making decisions based on assigning probabilities to various factors and assigning numerical ...
and related areas – such as
robust optimization Robust optimization is a field of mathematical optimization theory that deals with optimization problems in which a certain measure of robustness is sought against uncertainty that can be represented as deterministic variability in the value of the ...
- as the foremost non-probabilistic paradigm for modeling and treatment of severe uncertainty. Info-gap is propounded (e.g. Ben-Haim 2001, 2006) as a new non-probabilistic theory that is radically different from all current decision theories for decision under uncertainty. So, it is imperative to examine in this discussion in what way, if any, is info-gap's robustness model radically different from Maximin. For one thing, there is a well-established assessment of the utility of Maximin. For example, Berger (Chapter 5) suggests that even in situations where no prior information is available (a best case for Maximin), Maximin can lead to bad decision rules and be hard to implement. He recommends Bayesian methodology. And as indicated above,
It should also be remarked that the minimax principle even if it is applicable leads to an extremely conservative policy.
Tintner (1952, p. 25)
However, quite apart from the ramifications that establishing this point might have for the utility of info-gaps' robustness model, the reason that it behooves us to clarify the relationship between info-gap and Maximin is the centrality of the latter in decision theory. After all, this is a major classical decision methodology. So, any theory claiming to furnish a new non-probabilistic methodology for decision under severe uncertainty would be expected to be compared to this stalwart of decision theory. And yet, not only is a comparison of info-gap's robustness model to Maximin absent from the three books expounding info-gap (Ben-Haim 1996, 2001, 2006), Maximin is not even mentioned in them as the major decision theoretic methodology for severe uncertainty that it is. Elsewhere in the info-gap literature, one can find discussions dealing with similarities and differences between these two paradigms, as well as discussions on the relationship between info-gap and worst-case analysis, However, the general impression is that the intimate connection between these two paradigms has not been identified. Indeed, the opposite is argued. For instance, Ben-Haim (2005) argues that info-gap's robustness model is similar to Maximin but, is not a Maximin model. The following quote eloquently expresses Ben-Haim's assessment of info-gap's relationship to Maximin and it provides ample motivation for the analysis that follows.
We note that robust reliability is emphatically '' not '' a worst-case analysis. In classical worst-case min-max analysis the designer minimizes the impact of the maximally damaging case. But an info-gap model of uncertainty is an unbounded family of nested sets: \ \displaystyle \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde) \ , for all \ \displaystyle \alpha\ge 0 \ . Consequently, there is no worst case: any adverse occurrence is less damaging than some other more extreme event occurring at a larger value of \ \displaystyle \alpha \ . What Eq. (1) expresses is the greatest level of uncertainty consistent with no-failure. When the designer chooses q to maximize \ \displaystyle \hat(q, r_) \ he is maximizing his immunity to an unbounded ambient uncertainty. The closest this comes to "min-maxing" is that the design is chosen so that "bad" events (causing reward \ \displaystyle R\ less than \ \displaystyle r_\ ) occur as "far away" as possible (beyond a maximized value of \ \displaystyle \hat \ ).
Ben-Haim, 1999, pp. 271–2
The point to note here is that this statement misses the fact that the horizon of uncertainty \ \displaystyle \alpha \ is bounded above (implicitly) by the performance requirement
r_ \le R(q,u),\forall u\in \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde)
and that info-gap conducts its worst-case analysis—one analysis at a time for a given \ \displaystyle \alpha \ge 0 \   -- within each of the regions of uncertainty \displaystyle \ \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde), \alpha\ge 0 \ . In short, given the discussions in the info-gap literature on this issue, it is obvious that the kinship between info-gap's robustness model and Wald's Maximin model, as well as info-gap's kinship with other models of classical decision theory must be brought to light. So, the objective in this section is to place info-gap's robustness and opportuneness models in their proper context, namely within the wider frameworks of classical
decision theory Decision theory (or the theory of choice; not to be confused with choice theory) is a branch of applied probability theory concerned with the theory of making decisions based on assigning probabilities to various factors and assigning numerical ...
and
robust optimization Robust optimization is a field of mathematical optimization theory that deals with optimization problems in which a certain measure of robustness is sought against uncertainty that can be represented as deterministic variability in the value of the ...
. The discussion is based on the classical decision theoretic perspective outlined by Sniedovich (2007) and on standard texts in this area (e.g. Resnik 1987, French 1988).
Certain parts of the exposition that follows have a mathematical slant.
This is unavoidable because info-gap's models are mathematical.


Generic models

The basic conceptual framework that classical decision theory provides for dealing with uncertainty is that of a two-player game. The two players are the decision maker (DM) and Nature, where Nature represents uncertainty. More specifically, Nature represents the DM's attitude towards uncertainty and risk. Note that a clear distinction is made in this regard between a pessimistic decision maker and an optimistic decision maker, namely between a worst-case attitude and a best-case attitude. A pessimistic decision maker assumes that Nature plays against him whereas an optimistic decision maker assumes that Nature plays with him. To express these intuitive notions mathematically, classical
decision theory Decision theory (or the theory of choice; not to be confused with choice theory) is a branch of applied probability theory concerned with the theory of making decisions based on assigning probabilities to various factors and assigning numerical ...
uses a simple model consisting of the following three constructs:
* A set \ \displaystyle D representing the ''decision space'' available to the DM. * A set of sets \ \displaystyle \\ representing ''state spaces'' associated with the decisions in \ \displaystyle D . * A function \ \displaystyle g=g(d,s) stipulating the ''outcomes'' generated by the decision-state pairs \ \displaystyle (d,s)\ .
The function \ \displaystyle g \ is called ''objective function, payoff function, return function, cost function'' etc. The decision-making process (game) defined by these objects consists of three steps:
* Step 1: The DM selects a decision d\in D . * Step 2: In response, given d, Nature selects a state \ \displaystyle s\in S(d)\ . * Step 3: The outcome g(d,s) is allotted to DM.
Note that in contrast to games considered in classical
game theory Game theory is the study of mathematical models of strategic interactions among rational agents. Myerson, Roger B. (1991). ''Game Theory: Analysis of Conflict,'' Harvard University Press, p.&nbs1 Chapter-preview links, ppvii–xi It has appli ...
, here the first player (DM) moves first so that the second player (Nature) knows what decision was selected by the first player prior to selecting her decision. Thus, the conceptual and technical complications regarding the existence of Nash equilibrium point are not pertinent here. Nature is not an independent player, it is a conceptual device describing the DM's attitude towards uncertainty and risk. At first sight, the simplicity of this framework may strike one as naive. Yet, as attested by the variety of specific instances that it encompasses it is rich in possibilities, flexible, and versatile. For the purposes of this discussion it suffices to consider the following classical generic setup: : z^ = \underset \ \underset g(d,s) where \ \displaystyle \mathop \ and \displaystyle \mathop\ represent the DM's and Nature's optimality criteria, respectively, that is, each is equal to either \ \displaystyle \max\ or \ \displaystyle \min\ . If \ \displaystyle \mathop = \mathop\ then the game is cooperative, and if \ \displaystyle \mathop \neq \mathop\ then the game is non-cooperative. Thus, this format represents four cases: two non-cooperative games (Maximin and Minimax) and two cooperative games (Minimin, and Maximax). The respective formulations are as follows: : \begin \text & & \text\\ \hline \text & \text & \text & \text \\ \displaystyle \max_\,\min_\,g(d,s) & \displaystyle \min_\,\max_\,g(d,s) & \displaystyle \min_\,\min_\,g(d,s) & \displaystyle \max_\,\max_\,g(d,s) \end Each case is specified by a pair of optimality criteria employed by DM and Nature. For example, Maximin depicts a situation where DM strives to maximize the outcome and Nature strives to minimize it. Similarly, the Minimin paradigm represents situations where both DM and Nature are striving to in minimize the outcome. Of particular interest to this discussion are the Maximin and Minimin paradigms because they subsume info-gap's robustness and opportuneness models, respectively. So, here they are:
* Step 1: The DM selects a decision \ \displaystyle d\in D \ with a view to maximize the outcome \ \displaystyle g(d,s) \ . * Step 2: In response, given \ \displaystyle d\ , Nature selects a state in \ \displaystyle S(d)\ that minimizes \ \displaystyle g(d,s) \ over \ \displaystyle S(d) \ . * Step 3: The outcome \ \displaystyle g(d,s) is allotted to DM.
* Step 1: The DM selects a decision \ \displaystyle d\in D \ with a view to minimizes the outcome \ \displaystyle g(d,s) \ . * Step 2: In response, given \ \displaystyle d\ , Nature selects a state in \ \displaystyle S(d)\ that minimizes \ \displaystyle g(d,s) \ over \ \displaystyle S(d) \ . * Step 3: The outcome \ \displaystyle g(d,s) is allotted to DM.
With this in mind, consider now info-gap's robustness and opportuneness models.


Info-gap's robustness model

From a classical decision theoretic point of view info-gap's robustness model is a game between the DM and Nature, where the DM selects the value of \ \displaystyle \alpha \ (aiming for the largest possible) whereas Nature selects the worst value of \ \displaystyle u \ in \ \displaystyle \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde) \ . In this context the worst value of \ \displaystyle u \ pertaining to a given \ \displaystyle (q,\alpha) \ pair is a \ \displaystyle u\in \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde) \ that violates the performance requirement \ \displaystyle r_ \le R(q,u) \ . This is achieved by minimizing \ \displaystyle R(q,u)\ over \ \displaystyle \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde)\ . There are various ways to incorporate the DM's objective and Nature's antagonistic response in a single outcome. For instance, one can use the following characteristic function for this purpose:
\varphi(q,\alpha,u):=\begin \quad \alpha &, \ \ r_ \le R(q,u) \\ -\infty &, \ \ r_ > R(q,u) \end \ , \ q\in \mathcal, \alpha\ge 0, u\in \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde)
Note that, as desired, for any triplet \ \ (q,\alpha,u)\ of interest we have
r_ \le R(q,u) \ \ \ \longleftrightarrow \ \ \ \alpha \le \varphi(q,\alpha,u)
hence from the DM's point of view satisficing the performance constraint is equivalent to maximizing   \ \displaystyle \varphi(q,\alpha,u)\ . In short,
* Step 1: The DM selects a horizon of uncertainty \ \displaystyle \alpha\ge 0 \ with a view to maximize the outcome \ \displaystyle \varphi(q,\alpha,u) \ . * Step 2: In response, given \ \displaystyle \alpha \ , Nature selects a \ \displaystyle u \in \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde)\ that minimizes \ \displaystyle \varphi(q,\alpha,u) \ over \ \displaystyle \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde) \ . * Step 3: The outcome \ \displaystyle \varphi(q,\alpha,u) is allotted to DM.
Clearly, the DM's optimal alternative is to select the largest value of \ \displaystyle \alpha \ such that the worst \ \displaystyle u\in \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde)\ satisfies the performance requirement.


Maximin Theorem

As shown in Sniedovich (2007), Info-gap's robustness model is a simple instance of
Wald's maximin model In decision theory and game theory, Wald's maximin model is a non-probabilistic decision-making model according to which decisions are ranked on the basis of their worst-case outcomes – the optimal decision is one with the least bad worst outco ...
. Specifically,
(q, ) = \max \left \ = \max_ \min_ \varphi(q,\alpha,u) \quad \quad \Box


Info-gap's opportuneness model

By the same token, info-gap's opportuneness model is a simple instance of the generic Minimin model. That is,
(q, ) = \min \left \ = \min_ \min_ \psi(q,\alpha,u)
where
\psi(q,\alpha,u) = \left\
Note that although the model on the left does not include an explicit "min", it is nevertheless a typical Maximin model. The feature rendering it a Maximin model is the \ \displaystyle \forall \ requirement which lends itself to an intuitive worst-case formulation and interpretation. In fact, the presence of a double "max" in an info-gap robustness model does not necessarily alter the fact that this model is a Maximin model. For instance, consider the robustness model
\max\
This is an instance of the following Maximin model
\max_ \min_ \vartheta(q,\alpha,u)
where
\vartheta(q,\alpha,u):= \begin \quad \alpha &, \ \ r_ \ge R(q,\alpha)\\ -\infty &,\ \ r_ < R(q,\alpha) \end
The "inner min" indicates that Nature plays against the DM—the "max" player—hence the model is a robustness model.


The nature of the info-gap/maximin/minimin connection

This modeling issue is discussed here because claims have been made that although there is a close relationship between info-gap's robustness and opportuneness models and the generic maximin and Minimin models, respectively, the description of info-gap as an '' instance of ''  these models is too strong. The argument put forward is that although it is true that info-gap's robustness model can be expressed as a maximin model, the former is not an instance of the latter. This objection apparently stems from the fact that any optimization problem can be formulated as a maximin model by a simple employment of ''dummy''  variables. That is, clearly : \min_ f(x) = \max_\min_ g(y,x) where : g(y,x) = f(x) \ , \ \forall x\in X, y\in Y for any arbitrary non-empty set Y. The point of this objection seems to be that we are running the risk of watering down the meaning of the term ''instance''  if we thus contend that any minimization problem is an instance of the maximin model. It must therefore be pointed out that this concern is utterly unwarranted in the case of the info-gap/maximin/minimin relation. The correspondence between info-gap's robustness model and the generic maximin model is neither contrived nor is it formulated with the aid of dummy objects. The correspondence is immediate, intuitive, and compelling hence, aptly described by the term '' instance of ''. Specifically, as shown above, info-gap's robustness model is an instance of the generic maximin model specified by the following constructs: : \begin \text & & D & = (0,\infty)\\ \text & & S(d) & = \mathcal(d,\tilde)\\ \text & & g(d,s) & = \varphi(q,d,s) \end Furthermore, those objecting to the use of the term '' instance of ''  should note that the Maximin model formulated above has an equivalent so called '' Mathematical Programming ''  (MP) formulation deriving from the fact that : \begin \text&& \text\\ \displaystyle \max_ \ \min_\ g(d,s) &=& \displaystyle \max_\ \end where \ \mathbb \ denotes the real line. So here are side by side info-gap's robustness model and the two equivalent formulations of the generic maximin paradigm: : \begin\text \\ \begin \text& \text&\text\\ \hline \\ 0.18in\displaystyle \max\&\displaystyle \max\&\displaystyle \max_ \ \min_ \varphi(q,\alpha,u) \end \end Note that the equivalence between these three representations of the same decision-making situation makes no use of dummy variables. It is based on the equivalence : r_c \le R(q,u) \longleftrightarrow \alpha \le \varphi(q,\alpha,u) deriving directly from the definition of the characteristic function \varphi. Clearly then, info-gap's robustness model is an instance of the generic maximin model. Similarly, for info-gap's opportuneness model we have : \begin\text \\ \begin \text& \text&\text\\ \hline \\ 0.18in\displaystyle \min\ & \displaystyle \min\ & \displaystyle \min_ \ \min_ \psi(q,\alpha,u) \end \end Again, it should be stressed that the equivalence between these three representations of the same decision-making situation makes no use of dummy variables. It is based on the equivalence : r_c \le R(q,u) \longleftrightarrow \alpha \ge \psi(q,\alpha,u) deriving directly from the definition of the characteristic function \psi. Thus, to "help" the DM minimize \alpha, a sympathetic Nature will select a u \in \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde)\ that minimizes \ \psi(q,\alpha,u) \ over \ \displaystyle \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde)\ . Clearly, info-gap's opportuneness model is an instance of the generic minimin model.


Other formulations

There are of course other valid representations of the robustness/opportuneness models. For instance, in the case of the robustness model, the outcomes can be defined as follows (Sniedovich 2007) :
g(\alpha,u):= \alpha \cdot \left(r_ \preceq R(q,u)\right)
where the binary operation \ \ \preceq \ \ is defined as follows:
a \preceq b := \begin 1 &, \ \ a\le b \\ 0 &,\ \ a>b \end
The corresponding MP format of the Maximin model would then be as follows:
\max\ = \max\
In words, to maximize the robustness, the DM selects the largest value of \ \alpha \ such that the performance constraint \ r_ \le R(q,u) \ is satisfied by all \ u\in \mathcal(\alpha,\tilde)\ . In plain language: the DM selects the largest value of \ \displaystyle \alpha \ whose worst outcome in the region of uncertainty of size \ \displaystyle \alpha \ satisfies the performance requirement.


Simplifications

As a rule the classical Maximin formulations are not particularly useful when it comes to solving the problems they represent, as no "general purpose" Maximin solver is available (Rustem and Howe 2002). It is common practice therefore to simplify the classical formulation with a view to derive a formulation that would be readily amenable to solution. This is a problem-specific task which involves exploiting a problem's specific features. The mathematical programming format of Maximin is often more user-friendly in this regard. The best example is of course the classical Maximin model of 2-person zero-sum games which after streamlining is reduced to a standard
linear programming Linear programming (LP), also called linear optimization, is a method to achieve the best outcome (such as maximum profit or lowest cost) in a mathematical model whose requirements are represented by linear function#As a polynomial function, li ...
model (Thie 1988, pp. 314–317) that is readily solved by
linear programming Linear programming (LP), also called linear optimization, is a method to achieve the best outcome (such as maximum profit or lowest cost) in a mathematical model whose requirements are represented by linear function#As a polynomial function, li ...
algorithms In mathematics and computer science, an algorithm () is a finite sequence of rigorous instructions, typically used to solve a class of specific problems or to perform a computation. Algorithms are used as specifications for performing c ...
. To reiterate, this
linear programming Linear programming (LP), also called linear optimization, is a method to achieve the best outcome (such as maximum profit or lowest cost) in a mathematical model whose requirements are represented by linear function#As a polynomial function, li ...
model is an instance of the generic Maximin model obtained via simplification of the classical Maximin formulation of the 2-person zero-sum game. Another example is
dynamic programming Dynamic programming is both a mathematical optimization method and a computer programming method. The method was developed by Richard Bellman in the 1950s and has found applications in numerous fields, from aerospace engineering to economics. I ...
where the Maximin paradigm is incorporated in the dynamic programming functional equation representing sequential decision processes that are subject to severe uncertainty (e.g. Sniedovich 2003).


Summary

Recall that in plain language the Maximin paradigm maintains the following:
The maximin rule tells us to rank alternatives by their worst possible outcomes: we are to adopt the alternative the worst outcome of which is superior to the worst outcome of the others.
Rawls (1971, p. 152)
Info-gap's robustness model is a simple instance of this paradigm that is characterized by a specific decision space, state spaces and objective function, as discussed above. Much can be gained by viewing info-gap's theory in this light.


See also

*
Bayesian estimation In estimation theory and decision theory, a Bayes estimator or a Bayes action is an estimator or decision rule that minimizes the posterior expected value of a loss function (i.e., the posterior expected loss). Equivalently, it maximizes the pos ...
*
Bayesian inference Bayesian inference is a method of statistical inference in which Bayes' theorem is used to update the probability for a hypothesis as more evidence or information becomes available. Bayesian inference is an important technique in statistics, a ...
*
Bayesian probability Bayesian probability is an Probability interpretations, interpretation of the concept of probability, in which, instead of frequentist probability, frequency or propensity probability, propensity of some phenomenon, probability is interpreted as re ...
*
Decision analysis Decision analysis (DA) is the discipline comprising the philosophy, methodology, and professional practice necessary to address important decisions in a formal manner. Decision analysis includes many procedures, methods, and tools for identifying, ...
*
Decision theory Decision theory (or the theory of choice; not to be confused with choice theory) is a branch of applied probability theory concerned with the theory of making decisions based on assigning probabilities to various factors and assigning numerical ...
*
Hierarchical Bayes model Multilevel models (also known as hierarchical linear models, linear mixed-effect model, mixed models, nested data models, random coefficient, random-effects models, random parameter models, or split-plot designs) are statistical models of parame ...
*
List of publications in statistics This is a list of important publications in statistics, organized by field. Some reasons why a particular publication might be regarded as important: *Topic creator – A publication that created a new topic *Breakthrough – A publicatio ...
*
Markov chain Monte Carlo In statistics, Markov chain Monte Carlo (MCMC) methods comprise a class of algorithms for sampling from a probability distribution. By constructing a Markov chain that has the desired distribution as its equilibrium distribution, one can obtain ...
*
Robust decision making Robust decision-making (RDM) is an iterative decision analytics framework that aims to help identify potential robust strategies, characterize the vulnerabilities of such strategies, and evaluate the tradeoffs among them. RDM focuses on informing ...
*
Robust optimization Robust optimization is a field of mathematical optimization theory that deals with optimization problems in which a certain measure of robustness is sought against uncertainty that can be represented as deterministic variability in the value of the ...
*
Robust statistics Robust statistics are statistics with good performance for data drawn from a wide range of probability distributions, especially for distributions that are not normal. Robust statistical methods have been developed for many common problems, suc ...
*
Sensitivity analysis Sensitivity analysis is the study of how the uncertainty in the output of a mathematical model or system (numerical or otherwise) can be divided and allocated to different sources of uncertainty in its inputs. A related practice is uncertainty anal ...
*
Stability radius In mathematics, the stability radius of an object (system, function, matrix, parameter) at a given nominal point is the radius of the largest ball, centered at the nominal point, all of whose elements satisfy pre-determined stability condition ...


Notes


References


External links


Info-Gap Theory and Its Applications
further information on info-gap theory

informal introduction
Making Responsible Decisions (When it Seems that You Can't): Engineering Design and Strategic Planning Under Severe Uncertainty



Frequently Asked Questions about info-gap theory

Info-Gap Campaign
further analysis and critique of info-gap
PDF
{{DEFAULTSORT:Info-Gap Decision Theory Decision theory Robust statistics