HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

An infinitary logic is a
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premises ...
that allows infinitely long
statements Statement or statements may refer to: Common uses *Statement (computer science), the smallest standalone element of an imperative programming language *Statement (logic), declarative sentence that is either true or false *Statement, a declarative ...
and/or infinitely long
proofs Proof most often refers to: * Proof (truth), argument or sufficient evidence for the truth of a proposition * Alcohol proof, a measure of an alcoholic drink's strength Proof may also refer to: Mathematics and formal logic * Formal proof, a co ...
. Some infinitary logics may have different properties from those of standard
first-order logic First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantifie ...
. In particular, infinitary logics may fail to be
compact Compact as used in politics may refer broadly to a pact or treaty; in more specific cases it may refer to: * Interstate compact * Blood compact, an ancient ritual of the Philippines * Compact government, a type of colonial rule utilized in British ...
or
complete Complete may refer to: Logic * Completeness (logic) * Completeness of a theory, the property of a theory that every formula in the theory's language or its negation is provable Mathematics * The completeness of the real numbers, which implies t ...
. Notions of compactness and completeness that are equivalent in finitary logic sometimes are not so in infinitary logics. Therefore for infinitary logics, notions of strong compactness and strong completeness are defined. This article addresses Hilbert-type infinitary logics, as these have been extensively studied and constitute the most straightforward extensions of finitary logic. These are not, however, the only infinitary logics that have been formulated or studied. Considering whether a certain infinitary logic named
Ω-logic In set theory, Ω-logic is an infinitary logic and deductive system proposed by as part of an attempt to generalize the theory of determinacy of pointclasses to cover the structure H_. Just as the axiom of projective determinacy yields a canonic ...
is complete promises to throw light on the
continuum hypothesis In mathematics, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states that or equivalently, that In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this is equivalent to ...
.


A word on notation and the axiom of choice

As a language with infinitely long formulae is being presented, it is not possible to write such formulae down explicitly. To get around this problem a number of notational conveniences, which, strictly speaking, are not part of the formal language, are used. \cdots is used to point out an expression that is infinitely long. Where it is unclear, the length of the sequence is noted afterwards. Where this notation becomes ambiguous or confusing, suffixes such as \bigvee_ are used to indicate an infinite
disjunction In logic, disjunction is a logical connective typically notated as \lor and read aloud as "or". For instance, the English language sentence "it is raining or it is snowing" can be represented in logic using the disjunctive formula R \lor S ...
over a set of formulae of
cardinality In mathematics, the cardinality of a set is a measure of the number of elements of the set. For example, the set A = \ contains 3 elements, and therefore A has a cardinality of 3. Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept was generalized ...
\delta. The same notation may be applied to quantifiers, for example \forall_. This is meant to represent an infinite sequence of quantifiers: a quantifier for each V_ where \gamma < \delta. All usage of suffixes and \cdots are not part of formal infinitary languages. The
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collectio ...
is assumed (as is often done when discussing infinitary logic) as this is necessary to have sensible distributivity laws.


Definition of Hilbert-type infinitary logics

A first-order infinitary language ''L''''α'',''β'', ''α'' regular, ''β'' = 0 or ω ≤ ''β'' ≤ ''α'', has the same set of symbols as a finitary logic and may use all the rules for formation of formulae of a finitary logic together with some additional ones: *Given a set of formulae A=\ then (A_0 \lor A_1 \lor \cdots) and (A_0 \land A_1 \land \cdots) are formulae. (In each case the sequence has length \delta.) *Given a set of variables V=\ and a formula A_0 then \forall V_0 :\forall V_1 \cdots (A_0) and \exists V_0 :\exists V_1 \cdots (A_0) are formulae. (In each case the sequence of quantifiers has length \delta.) The concepts of free and bound variables apply in the same manner to infinite formulae. Just as in finitary logic, a formula all of whose variables are bound is referred to as a '' sentence''. A
theory A theory is a rational type of abstract thinking about a phenomenon, or the results of such thinking. The process of contemplative and rational thinking is often associated with such processes as observational study or research. Theories may be s ...
''T'' in infinitary language L_ is a set of sentences in the logic. A proof in infinitary logic from a theory ''T'' is a (possibly infinite)
sequence In mathematics, a sequence is an enumerated collection of objects in which repetitions are allowed and order matters. Like a set, it contains members (also called ''elements'', or ''terms''). The number of elements (possibly infinite) is calle ...
of statements that obeys the following conditions: Each statement is either a logical axiom, an element of ''T'', or is deduced from previous statements using a rule of inference. As before, all rules of inference in finitary logic can be used, together with an additional one: *Given a set of statements A=\ that have occurred previously in the proof then the statement \land_ can be inferred. The logical axiom schemata specific to infinitary logic are presented below. Global schemata variables: \delta and \gamma such that 0 < \delta < \alpha . *((\land_) \implies (A_ \implies \land_)) *For each \gamma < \delta, ((\land_) \implies A_) * Chang's distributivity laws (for each \gamma): (\lor_), where \forall \mu \forall \delta \exists \epsilon < \gamma: A_ = A_ or A_ = \neg A_, and \forall g \in \gamma^ \exists \epsilon < \gamma: \ \subseteq \ *For \gamma < \alpha, ((\land_) \implies (\lor_)), where \ is a well ordering of \gamma^ The last two axiom schemata require the axiom of choice because certain sets must be
well order In mathematics, a well-order (or well-ordering or well-order relation) on a Set (mathematics), set ''S'' is a total order on ''S'' with the property that every non-empty subset of ''S'' has a least element in this ordering. The set ''S'' together ...
able. The last axiom schema is strictly speaking unnecessary, as Chang's distributivity laws imply it, however it is included as a natural way to allow natural weakenings to the logic.


Completeness, compactness, and strong completeness

A theory is any set of sentences. The truth of statements in models are defined by recursion and will agree with the definition for finitary logic where both are defined. Given a theory ''T'' a sentence is said to be valid for the theory ''T'' if it is true in all models of ''T''. A logic in the language L_ is complete if for every sentence ''S'' valid in every model there exists a proof of ''S''. It is strongly complete if for any theory ''T'' for every sentence ''S'' valid in ''T'' there is a proof of ''S'' from ''T''. An infinitary logic can be complete without being strongly complete. A cardinal \kappa \neq \omega is weakly compact when for every theory ''T'' in L_ containing at most \kappa many formulas, if every ''S'' \subseteq ''T'' of cardinality less than \kappa has a model, then ''T'' has a model. A cardinal \kappa \neq \omega is strongly compact when for every theory ''T'' in L_, without restriction on size, if every ''S'' \subseteq ''T'' of cardinality less than \kappa has a model, then ''T'' has a model.


Concepts expressible in infinitary logic

In the language of
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly conce ...
the following statement expresses
foundation Foundation may refer to: * Foundation (nonprofit), a type of charitable organization ** Foundation (United States law), a type of charitable organization in the U.S. ** Private foundation, a charitable organization that, while serving a good cause ...
: :\forall_ \neg \land_.\, Unlike the axiom of foundation, this statement admits no non-standard interpretations. The concept of
well-foundedness In mathematics, a binary relation ''R'' is called well-founded (or wellfounded) on a class ''X'' if every non-empty subset ''S'' âŠ† ''X'' has a minimal element with respect to ''R'', that is, an element ''m'' not related by ''s  ...
can only be expressed in a logic that allows infinitely many quantifiers in an individual statement. As a consequence many theories, including
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly u ...
, which cannot be properly axiomatised in finitary logic, can be in a suitable infinitary logic. Other examples include the theories of
non-archimedean field In abstract algebra and analysis, the Archimedean property, named after the ancient Greek mathematician Archimedes of Syracuse, is a property held by some algebraic structures, such as ordered or normed groups, and fields. The property, typicall ...
s and
torsion-free group In mathematics, specifically in ring theory, a torsion element is an element of a module that yields zero when multiplied by some non-zero-divisor of the ring. The torsion submodule of a module is the submodule formed by the torsion elements. A to ...
s. These three theories can be defined without the use of infinite quantification; only infinite junctions are needed.


Complete infinitary logics

Two infinitary logics stand out in their completeness. These are the logics of L_ and L_. The former is standard finitary first-order logic and the latter is an infinitary logic that only allows statements of countable size. The logic of L_ is also strongly complete, compact and strongly compact. The logic of L_ fails to be compact, but it is complete (under the axioms given above). Moreover, it satisfies a variant of the
Craig interpolation In mathematical logic, Craig's interpolation theorem is a result about the relationship between different logical theories. Roughly stated, the theorem says that if a formula φ implies a formula ψ, and the two have at least one atomic variable sy ...
property. If the logic of L_ is strongly complete (under the axioms given above) then \alpha is strongly compact (because proofs in these logics cannot use \alpha or more of the given axioms).


References

* *{{citation , last=Barwise , first=Kenneth Jon , author-link=Jon Barwise , date=1969 , title=Infinitary logic and admissible sets , journal=
Journal of Symbolic Logic The '' Journal of Symbolic Logic'' is a peer-reviewed mathematics journal published quarterly by Association for Symbolic Logic. It was established in 1936 and covers mathematical logic. The journal is indexed by '' Mathematical Reviews'', Zentra ...
, doi=10.2307/2271099 , jstor=2271099 , mr=0406760 , volume=34 , issue=2 , pages=226–252, s2cid=38740720 Systems of formal logic Non-classical logic