HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The identity of indiscernibles is an ontological principle that states that there cannot be separate objects or
entities An entity is something that exists as itself, as a subject or as an object, actually or potentially, concretely or abstractly, physically or not. It need not be of material existence. In particular, abstractions and legal fictions are usually r ...
that have all their properties in common. That is, entities ''x'' and ''y'' are identical if every predicate possessed by ''x'' is also possessed by ''y'' and vice versa. It states that no two distinct things (such as
snowflake A snowflake is a single ice crystal that has achieved a sufficient size, and may have amalgamated with others, which falls through the Earth's atmosphere as snow.Knight, C.; Knight, N. (1973). Snow crystals. Scientific American, vol. 228, no. ...
s) can be exactly alike, but this is intended as a metaphysical principle rather than one of natural science. A related principle is the indiscernibility of identicals, discussed below. A form of the principle is attributed to the German philosopher
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm (von) Leibniz . ( – 14 November 1716) was a German polymath active as a mathematician, philosopher, scientist and diplomat. He is one of the most prominent figures in both the history of philosophy and the history of mat ...
. While some think that Leibniz's version of the principle is meant to be only the indiscernibility of identicals, others have interpreted it as the conjunction of the identity of indiscernibles and the indiscernibility of identicals (the converse principle). Because of its association with Leibniz, the indiscernibility of identicals is sometimes known as Leibniz's law. It is considered to be one of his great metaphysical principles, the other being the principle of noncontradiction and the principle of sufficient reason (famously been used in his disputes with Newton and Clarke in the Leibniz–Clarke correspondence). Some philosophers have decided, however, that it is important to exclude certain predicates (or purported predicates) from the principle in order to avoid either triviality or contradiction. An example (detailed below) is the predicate that denotes whether an object is equal to ''x'' (often considered a valid predicate). As a consequence, there are a few different versions of the principle in the philosophical literature, of varying logical strength—and some of them are termed "the strong principle" or "the weak principle" by particular authors, in order to distinguish between them.
Willard Van Orman Quine Willard Van Orman Quine (; known to his friends as "Van"; June 25, 1908 – December 25, 2000) was an American philosopher and logician in the analytic tradition, recognized as "one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century ...
thought that the failure of substitution in intensional contexts (e.g., "Sally believes that ''p''" or "It is necessarily the case that ''q''") shows that modal logic is an impossible project. Saul Kripke holds that this failure may be the result of the use of the disquotational principle implicit in these proofs, and not a failure of substitutivity as such.Kripke, Saul. "A Puzzle about Belief". First appeared in, ''Meaning and Use''. ed., A. Margalit. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1979. pp. 239–283 The identity of indiscernibles has been used to motivate notions of noncontextuality within quantum mechanics. Associated with this principle is also the question as to whether it is a logical principle, or merely an empirical principle.


Identity and indiscernibility

Both identity and indiscernibility are expressed by the word "same". ''Identity'' is about ''numerical sameness'', it is expressed by the equality sign ("="). It is the relation each object bears only to itself. ''Indiscernibility'', on the other hand, concerns ''qualitative sameness'': two objects are indiscernible if they have all their properties in common. Formally, this can be expressed as "\forall F(Fx \leftrightarrow Fy)". The two senses of ''sameness'' are linked by two principles: the principle of ''indiscernibility of identicals'' and the principle of ''identity of indiscernibles''. The principle of ''indiscernibility of identicals'' is uncontroversial and states that if two entities are identical with each other then they have the same properties. The principle of ''identity of indiscernibles'', on the other hand, is more controversial in making the converse claim that if two entities have the same properties then they must be identical. This entails that "no two distinct things exactly resemble each other". Note that these are all second-order expressions. Neither of these principles can be expressed in
first-order logic First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quanti ...
(are nonfirstorderizable). Taken together, they are sometimes referred to as ''Leibniz's law''. Formally, the two principles can be expressed in the following way: #The indiscernibility of identicals: \forall x \, \forall y \, =y \rightarrow \forall F(Fx \leftrightarrow Fy)/math> #:For any x and y, if x is identical to y, then x and y have all the same properties. #The identity of indiscernibles: \forall x \, \forall y \, forall F(Fx \leftrightarrow Fy) \rightarrow x=y/math> #:For any x and y, if x and y have all the same properties, then x is identical to y. Principle 1 is generally regarded as an a priori
logical truth Logical truth is one of the most fundamental concepts in logic. Broadly speaking, a logical truth is a statement which is true regardless of the truth or falsity of its constituent propositions. In other words, a logical truth is a statement whi ...
. Principle 2, on the other hand, is controversial; Max Black famously argued against it. In a universe of two distinct objects A and B, all predicates F are materially equivalent to one of the following properties: * IsA, the property that holds of A but not of B; * IsB, the property that holds of B but not of A; * IsAorB, the property that holds of both A and B; * IsNotAorB, the property that holds of neither A nor B. If ∀F applies to all such predicates, then the second principle as formulated above reduces trivially and uncontroversially to a logical tautology. In that case, the objects are distinguished by IsA, IsB, and all predicates that are materially equivalent to either of these. This argument can combinatorially be extended to universes containing any number of distinct objects. The equality relation expressed by the sign "=" is an
equivalence relation In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation. Each equivalence relatio ...
in being reflexive (everything is equal to itself),
symmetric Symmetry (from grc, συμμετρία "agreement in dimensions, due proportion, arrangement") in everyday language refers to a sense of harmonious and beautiful proportion and balance. In mathematics, "symmetry" has a more precise definit ...
(if ''x'' is equal to ''y'' then ''y'' is equal to ''x'') and transitive (if ''x'' is equal to ''y'' and ''y'' is equal to ''z'' then ''x'' is equal to ''z''). The ''indiscernibility of identicals'' and ''identity of indiscernables'' can jointly be used to define the equality relation. The ''symmetry'' and ''transitivity'' of equality follow from the first principle, whereas ''reflexivity'' follows from the second. Both principles can be combined into a single axiom by using a biconditional operator (''\leftrightarrow'') in place of material implication (''\rightarrow'').


Indiscernibility and conceptions of properties

Indiscernibility is usually defined in terms of shared properties: two objects are indiscernible if they have all their properties in common. The plausibility and strength of the principle of identity of indiscernibles depend on the conception of properties used to define indiscernibility. One important distinction in this regard is between ''pure'' and ''impure'' properties. ''Impure properties'' are properties that, unlike ''pure properties'', involve reference to a particular substance in their definition. So, for example, ''being a wife'' is a pure property while ''being the wife of Socrates'' is an impure property due to the reference to the particular "Socrates". Sometimes, the terms ''qualitative'' and ''non-qualitative'' are used instead of ''pure'' and ''impure''. Discernibility is usually defined in terms of pure properties only. The reason for this is that taking impure properties into consideration would result in the principle being trivially true since any entity has the impure property of being identical to itself, which it does not share with any other entity. Another important distinction concerns the difference between
intrinsic and extrinsic properties In science and engineering, an intrinsic property is a Property (philosophy), property of a specified subject that exists itself or within the subject. An extrinsic property is not essential or inherent to the subject that is being character ...
. A property is ''extrinsic'' to an object if having this property depends on other objects (with or without reference to particular objects), otherwise it is ''intrinsic''. For example, the property of ''being an aunt'' is extrinsic while the property of ''having a mass of 60 kg'' is intrinsic. If the identity of indiscernibles is defined only in terms of ''intrinsic pure'' properties, one cannot regard two books lying on a table as distinct when they are ''intrinsically identical''. But if ''extrinsic'' and ''impure'' properties are also taken into consideration, the same books become distinct so long as they are discernible through the latter properties.


Critique


Symmetric universe

Max Black has argued against the identity of indiscernibles by counterexample. Notice that to show that the identity of indiscernibles is false, it is sufficient that one provide a model in which there are two distinct (numerically nonidentical) things that have all the same properties. He claimed that in a symmetric universe wherein only two symmetrical spheres exist, the two spheres are two distinct objects even though they have all their properties in common. Black argues that even relational properties (properties specifying distances between objects in space-time) fail to distinguish two identical objects in a symmetrical universe. Per his argument, two objects are, and will remain, equidistant from the universe's plane of symmetry and each other. Even bringing in an external observer to label the two spheres distinctly does not solve the problem, because it violates the symmetry of the universe.


Indiscernibility of identicals

As stated above, the principle of indiscernibility of identicals—that if two objects are in fact one and the same, they have all the same properties—is mostly uncontroversial. However, one famous application of the indiscernibility of identicals was by
René Descartes René Descartes ( or ; ; Latinized: Renatus Cartesius; 31 March 1596 – 11 February 1650) was a French philosopher, scientist, and mathematician, widely considered a seminal figure in the emergence of modern philosophy and science. Mathe ...
in his '' Meditations on First Philosophy''. Descartes concluded that he could not doubt the existence of himself (the famous '' cogito'' argument), but that he ''could'' doubt the existence of his body. This argument is criticized by some modern philosophers on the grounds that it allegedly derives a conclusion about what is true from a premise about what people know. What people know or believe about an entity, they argue, is not really a characteristic of that entity. A response may be that the argument in the '' Meditations on First Philosophy'' is that the inability of Descartes to doubt the existence of his mind is part of his mind's
essence Essence ( la, essentia) is a polysemic term, used in philosophy and theology as a designation for the property or set of properties that make an entity or substance what it fundamentally is, and which it has by necessity, and without which it ...
. One may then argue that identical things should have identical essences. Numerous counterexamples are given to debunk Descartes' reasoning via '' reductio ad absurdum'', such as the following argument based on a
secret identity A secret identity is a person's alter ego which is not known to the general populace, most often used in fiction. Brought into popular culture by the Scarlet Pimpernel in 1903, the concept was widespread in pulp heroes and is particularly prevalen ...
: #Entities ''x'' and ''y'' are identical if and only if any predicate possessed by ''x'' is also possessed by ''y'' and vice versa. #Clark Kent is Superman's secret identity; that is, they're the same person (identical) but people don't know this fact. #
Lois Lane Lois Lane is a Character (arts), fictional character appearing in American comic books published by DC Comics. Created by writer Jerry Siegel and artist Joe Shuster, she first appeared in ''Action Comics'' Action Comics 1, #1 (June 1938). Lois ...
thinks that
Clark Kent Superman is a superhero who appears in American comic books published by DC Comics. The character was created by writer Jerry Siegel and artist Joe Shuster, and debuted in the comic book ''Action Comics'' #1 (cover-dated June 1938 and publi ...
cannot fly. #Lois Lane thinks that Superman can fly. #Therefore Superman has a property that Clark Kent does not have, namely that Lois Lane thinks that he can fly. #Therefore, Superman is not identical to Clark Kent. #Since in proposition 6 we come to a contradiction with proposition 2, we conclude that at least one of the premises is wrong. Either: #* Leibniz's law is wrong; or #* A person's knowledge about ''x'' is not a predicate of ''x''; or #* The application of Leibniz's law is erroneous; the law is only applicable in cases of monadic, not polyadic, properties; or #* What people think about are not the actual objects themselves; or #* A person is capable of holding conflicting beliefs. :::Any of which will undermine Descartes' argument.


See also

* 1st axiom of a metric * * *, a similar idea in quantum mechanics * * *, a fallacious use of this principle * *, a similar idea in computer science *


References


External links


Leibniz's Law

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry
{{DEFAULTSORT:Identity Of Indiscernibles
indiscernibles In mathematical logic, indiscernibles are objects that cannot be distinguished by any property or relation defined by a formula. Usually only first-order formulas are considered. Examples If ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'' are distinct and is a set of i ...
Concepts in logic Concepts in metaphysics Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Ontology Philosophical problems Philosophical theories Philosophical logic Philosophy of logic Principles Semantics