How to Do Things With Words
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

John Langshaw Austin (26 March 1911 – 8 February 1960) was an English philosopher of language and leading proponent of
ordinary language philosophy Ordinary language philosophy (OLP) is a philosophical methodology that sees traditional philosophical problems as rooted in misunderstandings philosophers develop by distorting or forgetting how words are ordinarily used to convey meaning in ...
, best known for developing the theory of
speech acts Speech is the use of the human voice as a medium for language. Spoken language combines vowel and consonant sounds to form units of meaning like words, which belong to a language's lexicon. There are many different intentional speech acts, suc ...
. Austin pointed out that we use language to ''do'' things as well as to ''assert'' things, and that the utterance of a statement like "I promise to do so-and-so" is best understood as ''doing'' something—here, ''making a promise''—rather than making an assertion about anything; hence the title of one of his best-known works, ''How to Do Things with Words'' (1955). Austin, in formulating this theory of speech acts, mounts a significant challenge to the philosophy of language, far beyond merely elucidating a class of morphological sentence forms that function to do what they name. Austin's work ultimately suggests that all speech and all utterance is the doing of something with words and signs, challenging a
metaphysics Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that examines the basic structure of reality. It is traditionally seen as the study of mind-independent features of the world, but some theorists view it as an inquiry into the conceptual framework of ...
of language that would posit denotative, propositional assertion as the essence of language and meaning.


Life

Austin was born in Lancaster, Lancashire, England, the second son of Geoffrey Langshaw Austin (1884–1971), an
architect An architect is a person who plans, designs, and oversees the construction of buildings. To practice architecture means to provide services in connection with the design of buildings and the space within the site surrounding the buildings that h ...
, and Mary Hutton Bowes-Wilson (1883–1948; ''née'' Wilson). In 1921 the family moved to
Scotland Scotland is a Countries of the United Kingdom, country that is part of the United Kingdom. It contains nearly one-third of the United Kingdom's land area, consisting of the northern part of the island of Great Britain and more than 790 adjac ...
, where Austin's father became the secretary of
St Leonards School St Leonards School is a co-educational private boarding and day school for pupils aged 4–19 in St Andrews, Fife, Scotland. Founded in 1877 as St Andrews School for Girls Company, it adopted the St Leonards name upon moving to its current pre ...
,
St Andrews St Andrews (; ; , pronounced ʰʲɪʎˈrˠiː.ɪɲ is a town on the east coast of Fife in Scotland, southeast of Dundee and northeast of Edinburgh. St Andrews had a recorded population of 16,800 , making it Fife's fourth-largest settleme ...
. Austin was educated at
Shrewsbury School Shrewsbury School is a Public school (United Kingdom), public school in Shrewsbury. Founded in 1552 by Edward VI by royal charter, to replace the town's Saxon collegiate foundations which were disestablished in the sixteenth century, Shrewsb ...
in 1924, earning a scholarship in
Classics Classics, also classical studies or Ancient Greek and Roman studies, is the study of classical antiquity. In the Western world, ''classics'' traditionally refers to the study of Ancient Greek literature, Ancient Greek and Roman literature and ...
, and went on to study classics at
Balliol College, Oxford Balliol College () is a constituent college of the University of Oxford. Founded in 1263 by nobleman John I de Balliol, it has a claim to be the oldest college in Oxford and the English-speaking world. With a governing body of a master and aro ...
, in 1929. In 1930 Austin received a First in Classical Moderations (Greek and Latin) and in the following year won the Gaisford Prize for Greek prose. In finals in 1933 he received a first in Literae Humaniores (Philosophy and Ancient History). Literae Humaniores introduced Austin to serious philosophy and gave him a lifelong interest in
Aristotle Aristotle (; 384–322 BC) was an Ancient Greek philosophy, Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath. His writings cover a broad range of subjects spanning the natural sciences, philosophy, linguistics, economics, politics, psychology, a ...
.Hacker, P. M. S. 'Austin, John Langshaw (1911–1960)'
in
Oxford Dictionary of National Biography The ''Dictionary of National Biography'' (''DNB'') is a standard work of reference on notable figures from History of the British Isles, British history, published since 1885. The updated ''Oxford Dictionary of National Biography'' (''ODNB'') ...
, Oxford University Press, 200
online
(Archived 7 June 2021)
Austin won a prize fellowship at
All Souls College, Oxford All Souls College (official name: The College of All Souls of the Faithful Departed, of Oxford) is a constituent college of the University of Oxford in England. Unique to All Souls, all of its members automatically become fellows (i.e., full me ...
, that year, but aside from being friends with
Isaiah Berlin Sir Isaiah Berlin (6 June 1909 – 5 November 1997) was a Russian-British social and political theorist, philosopher, and historian of ideas. Although he became increasingly averse to writing for publication, his improvised lectures and talks ...
, he did not like its lack of structure, and undertook his first teaching position in 1935, as fellow and tutor at
Magdalen College, Oxford Magdalen College ( ) is a Colleges of the University of Oxford, constituent college of the University of Oxford. It was founded in 1458 by Bishop of Winchester William of Waynflete. It is one of the wealthiest Oxford colleges, as of 2022, and ...
. Austin's early interests included
Aristotle Aristotle (; 384–322 BC) was an Ancient Greek philosophy, Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath. His writings cover a broad range of subjects spanning the natural sciences, philosophy, linguistics, economics, politics, psychology, a ...
,
Kant Immanuel Kant (born Emanuel Kant; 22 April 1724 – 12 February 1804) was a German philosopher and one of the central Enlightenment thinkers. Born in Königsberg, Kant's comprehensive and systematic works in epistemology, metaphysics, et ...
,
Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (or Leibnitz; – 14 November 1716) was a German polymath active as a mathematician, philosopher, scientist and diplomat who is credited, alongside Sir Isaac Newton, with the creation of calculus in addition to many ...
, and
Plato Plato ( ; Greek language, Greek: , ; born  BC, died 348/347 BC) was an ancient Greek philosopher of the Classical Greece, Classical period who is considered a foundational thinker in Western philosophy and an innovator of the writte ...
(particularly the '' Theaetetus''). His contemporary influences included
G. E. Moore George Edward Moore (4 November 1873 – 24 October 1958) was an English philosopher, who with Bertrand Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein and earlier Gottlob Frege was among the initiators of analytic philosophy. He and Russell began de-emphasizing ...
, John Cook Wilson and H. A. Prichard. These contemporary philosophers shaped their views about general philosophical questions on the basis of careful attention to the more specific judgements we make, as they took our specific judgements to be relatively more secure than our general judgements. According to Guy Longworth, writing in ''
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (''SEP'') is a freely available online philosophy resource published and maintained by Stanford University, encompassing both an online encyclopedia of philosophy and peer-reviewed original publication ...
'': "It's plausible that some aspects of Austin's distinctive approach to philosophical questions derived from his engagement with oore, Wilson, and Prichard" During
World War II World War II or the Second World War (1 September 1939 – 2 September 1945) was a World war, global conflict between two coalitions: the Allies of World War II, Allies and the Axis powers. World War II by country, Nearly all of the wo ...
, Austin joined the military—in July 1940—and married his student Jean Coutts (in the spring of 1941). Austin served in the
British Intelligence Corps The Intelligence Corps (Int Corps) is a corps of the British Army. It is responsible for gathering, analysing and disseminating military intelligence and also for counter-intelligence and security. The Director of the Intelligence Corps is a b ...
, and was responsible for as many as 500 analysts. Known as "the Martians", the group's preparation for
D-Day The Normandy landings were the landing operations and associated airborne operations on 6 June 1944 of the Allied invasion of Normandy in Operation Overlord during the Second World War. Codenamed Operation Neptune and often referred to as ...
helped keep Allied casualties much lower than expected. Austin left the army with the rank of lieutenant colonel and was honoured for his intelligence work with an OBE (Officer of the
Order of the British Empire The Most Excellent Order of the British Empire is a British order of chivalry, rewarding valuable service in a wide range of useful activities. It comprises five classes of awards across both civil and military divisions, the most senior two o ...
), the French
Croix de Guerre The (, ''Cross of War'') is a military decoration of France. It was first created in 1915 and consists of a square-cross medal on two crossed swords, hanging from a ribbon with various degree pins. The decoration was first awarded during World ...
, and the U.S. Officer of the
Legion of Merit The Legion of Merit (LOM) is a Awards and decorations of the United States military, military award of the United States Armed Forces that is given for exceptionally meritorious conduct in the performance of outstanding services and achievemen ...
. After the war Austin became White's Professor of Moral Philosophy at
Oxford Oxford () is a City status in the United Kingdom, cathedral city and non-metropolitan district in Oxfordshire, England, of which it is the county town. The city is home to the University of Oxford, the List of oldest universities in continuou ...
, as a Professorial Fellow of Corpus Christi College. Publishing little, his influence would largely make itself felt through his teaching in lectures and tutorials and, especially, his famous 'Saturday morning meetings'. Austin visited
Harvard Harvard University is a private Ivy League research university in Cambridge, Massachusetts, United States. Founded in 1636 and named for its first benefactor, the Puritan clergyman John Harvard, it is the oldest institution of higher lear ...
and Berkeley in the mid-fifties, in 1955 delivering the William James Lectures at Harvard that would become ''How to Do Things With Words'', and offering a seminar on excuses whose material would find its way into "A Plea for Excuses". It was at this time that he met and befriended
Noam Chomsky Avram Noam Chomsky (born December 7, 1928) is an American professor and public intellectual known for his work in linguistics, political activism, and social criticism. Sometimes called "the father of modern linguistics", Chomsky is also a ...
. He was president of the Aristotelian Society from 1956 to 1957. Before he could decide whether to accept an offer to move to Berkeley, Austin died on 8 February 1960 at the age of 48, shortly after being diagnosed with
lung cancer Lung cancer, also known as lung carcinoma, is a malignant tumor that begins in the lung. Lung cancer is caused by genetic damage to the DNA of cells in the airways, often caused by cigarette smoking or inhaling damaging chemicals. Damaged ...
. His wealth, after
probate In common law jurisdictions, probate is the judicial process whereby a will is "proved" in a court of law and accepted as a valid public document that is the true last testament of the deceased; or whereby, in the absence of a legal will, the e ...
, was £15,049 0s. 5d. (equivalent to £ in ). At the time of his death, he was developing a semantic theory based on sound symbolism, using the English gl-words as data.


Work


''How to Do Things with Words''

''How to Do Things with Words'' (1955/1962) is perhaps Austin's most influential work. This work is based on a series of lectures that Austin delivered at Oxford University (1951-1954) and then at Harvard University (1955). A version of these lectures was published as a book. In contrast to the positivist view, he argues, sentences with
truth-value In logic and mathematics, a truth value, sometimes called a logical value, is a value indicating the relation of a proposition to truth, which in classical logic has only two possible values ('' true'' or '' false''). Truth values are used in c ...
s form only a small part of the range of utterances. After introducing several kinds of sentences which he asserts are neither true nor false, he turns in particular to one of these kinds of sentences, which he calls ''
performative utterance In the philosophy of language and speech acts theory, performative utterances are sentences which not only describe a given reality, but also change the social reality they are describing. In a 1955 lecture series, later published as ''How to D ...
s'' or just "performatives". These he characterises by two features: * First, performative sentences—though they may take the form of a typical indicative sentence—are not used to describe (or "constate"), and are thus neither true nor false; i.e., they have no truth-value. * Second, to utter one of these sentences in appropriate circumstances is not just to ''say'' something, but rather to ''thereby perform'' a certain kind of action (i.e., beyond and in addition to that of speaking alone). When something goes wrong in connection with a performative utterance it is—in Austin's words—''infelicitous'' or ''unhappy'', rather than ''false''. The action that is performed when a "performative utterance" is issued belongs to what Austin later calls a '' speech-act''. More particularly, the kind of action Austin has in mind is what he subsequently terms the ''
illocutionary act The concept of illocutionary acts was introduced into linguistics by the philosopher J. L. Austin in his investigation of the various aspects of speech acts. In his framework, ''locution'' is what was said and meant, ''illocution'' is what was do ...
''. For example, if you say "I name this ship the ''Queen Elizabeth''", and the circumstances are appropriate in certain ways, then you will have done something special: namely, you will have thus christened the ship. Other examples include "I take this man as my lawfully wedded husband" (used in the course of a marriage ceremony), or "I bequeath this watch to my brother" (as occurring in a will). In all three cases the sentence is not being used to ''describe'' or ''state'' what one is doing, but being used to ''actually do'' it. After numerous attempts to find more characteristics of performatives, and after having met with many difficulties, Austin makes what he calls a "fresh start", in which he considers "more generally the senses in which to say something may be to do something, or in saying something we do something". For example: John Smith turns to Sue Snub and asks "Is Jeff's shirt red?", to which Sue replies "Yes". John has undertaken a series of bodily movements which result in the production of a certain sound; Austin calls such a performance a ''phonetic act'', and the resulting "certain sound" a ''phone''. John's utterance also conforms to the lexical and grammatical conventions of English—that is, John has produced an English sentence; Austin calls this a '' phatic act'', and labels such utterances ''phemes''. John also referred to Jeff's shirt, and to the colour red. To use a pheme with a more or less definite sense and reference is to utter a '' rheme'', and to perform a ''rhetic act''. Note that rhemes are a sub-class of phemes, which in turn are a sub-class of phones. One cannot perform a rheme without also performing a pheme and a phone. The performance of these three acts is the performance of a ''locution''—it is the act of saying something. John has therefore performed a locutionary act. He has also done at least two other things: he has asked a question of, and elicited an answer from, Sue; in so doing, he has performed two further speech-acts, as Austin would have it: # Asking a question is an example of the ''
illocutionary act The concept of illocutionary acts was introduced into linguistics by the philosopher J. L. Austin in his investigation of the various aspects of speech acts. In his framework, ''locution'' is what was said and meant, ''illocution'' is what was do ...
.'' To perform an illocutionary act is to use a locution with a certain force; that is, in contrast to a locution—the act ''of'' saying something—an illocutionary act is an act performed ''in'' saying something. Other examples would be making an assertion, giving an order, and promising to do something. # Eliciting an answer is an example of what Austin calls a ''
perlocutionary act A perlocutionary act (or perlocutionary effect) is the effect of an utterance on an interlocutor. Examples of perlocutionary acts include persuading, convincing, scaring, enlightening, inspiring, or otherwise affecting the interlocutor. The perloc ...
:'' an act performed ''by'' the saying of something. Whereas illocutions and locutions are alternative descriptions of the utterance itself, perlocutions are classifiable by the further effects of an utterance. Other examples would be a heeded warning, or a successful attempt at persuasion. Notice that if one successfully performs a perlocution, one also succeeds in performing both an illocution and a locution. In the theory of speech acts, attention has especially focused on the illocutionary act; much less on the locutionary and perlocutionary act; and only rarely on the subdivision of the locution into phone, pheme and rheme.


Performative utterance

According to Austin, a "
performative utterance In the philosophy of language and speech acts theory, performative utterances are sentences which not only describe a given reality, but also change the social reality they are describing. In a 1955 lecture series, later published as ''How to D ...
" refers to the action of "performing" or "doing" a certain action; for example, when people say "I promise to do so and so", they are generating the action of making a promise ''by'' so speaking. If this is accomplished without any flaw (in this case: if the promise is fulfilled), the performative utterance is "happy" or "felicitous"; if, on the other hand, one fails to do as promised, it is "unhappy", or "infelicitous". Notice that performative utterance is not truth-valuable; i.e., the judgements "true" and "false" do not apply. Austin variously opposes different categories of utterance in order to analyze the differences, or lack thereof, between them: ''explicit'' vs. ''implicit'' or ''inexplicit'' performatives; ''explicit'' performatives vs. ''primitive'' or ''primary'' utterances or performatives; and ''pure'' performatives vs. ''half-descriptive'' vs. ''descriptive'' utterances. In ''How to Do Things With Words'' (edited by J. O. Urmson & Marina Sbisà), which records Austin's lectures on this topic, examples are offered for each of these distinctions: * For ''explicit'' or ''pure'' performatives, Austin gives the example of "I apologize"—the saying of which ''explicitly performs'' the speech-act, such that it would be nonsensical for someone to ask: "Does he or she ''really?''" * As an example of a ''half-descriptive'' utterance, Austin gives the phrase "I am sorry": there is some uncertainty as to whether the speaker is thereby ''offering'' an apology, or merely ''stating'' a fact; it could be either, absent clarifying context. * A entirely ''descriptive'' utterance might be a statement such as "I repent": here we have speech merely reporting upon our interlocutor's feeling (rather than itself enacting repentance ''by'' so being spoken). * ''Implicit'' performatives are those wherein the performance of an action is implied, but not expressly established; an example Austin uses is the phrase "I shall be there": one may ask, in this case, if the speaker is ''promising'' to be there, stating an ''intention,'' or reporting a ''prediction.'' * A ''primary'' performative admits of some ambiguity in interpretation: these may be taken to be either ''implicit'' performatives, or else entirely non-performative (sometimes ''constative,'' in Austin's parlance) utterances. A similar situation obtains with a statement such as "there is a bull in that field", which Austin gives as an illustration of a ''primitive'' utterance—does the speaker mean to warn us of the bull and thereby keep us out of the field, or is it merely an observation? Most examples given in the book are of explicit performatives, because they are easy to identify and observe; identifying other performatives requires comparison and contrast with explicit performatives.


''Sense and Sensibilia''

In the posthumously published ''Sense and Sensibilia'' (the title is Austin's own, and wittily echoes the title of ''
Sense and Sensibility ''Sense and Sensibility'' ( working title; ''Elinor and Marianne'') is the first novel by the English author Jane Austen, published in 1811. It was published anonymously: ''By A Lady'' appears on the title page where the author's name might h ...
'',
Jane Austen Jane Austen ( ; 16 December 1775 – 18 July 1817) was an English novelist known primarily for #List of works, her six novels, which implicitly interpret, critique, and comment on the English landed gentry at the end of the 18th century ...
's first book, just as his name echoes hers), Austin criticizes the claims put forward by A. J. Ayer's ''The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge'' (1940), and to a lesser extent,
H. H. Price Henry Habberley Price (17 May 1899 – 26 November 1984), usually cited as H. H. Price, was a Welsh philosopher, known for his work on the philosophy of perception. He also wrote on parapsychology. Biography Born in Neath, Glamorganshire, Wa ...
's ''Perception'' (1932) and G. J. Warnock's ''Berkeley'' (1953), concerning the sense-data theory. He states that perceptual variation, which can be attributed to physical causes, does not involve a figurative disconnection between sense and reference, due to an unreasonable separation of parts from the perceived object. Central to his argument, he shows that "there is no one kind of thing that we 'perceive' but many different kinds, the number being reducible if at all by scientific investigation and not by philosophy" (Austin 1962a, 4). Austin argues that Ayer fails to understand the proper function of such words as "illusion", "delusion", "hallucination", "looks", "appears" and "seems", and uses them instead in a "special way...invented by philosophers." According to Austin, normally these words allow us to express reservations about our commitment to the truth of what we are saying, and that the introduction of sense-data adds nothing to our understanding of or ability to talk about what we see. As an example, Austin examines the word 'real' and contrasts the ordinary meanings of that word based on everyday language and the ways it is used by sense-data theorists. In order to determine the meaning of 'real' we have to consider, case by case, the ways and contexts in which it is used. By observing that it is (i) a substantive-hungry word that is sometimes (ii) an adjuster-word, as well as (iii) a dimension-word and (iv) a word whose negative use "wears the trousers," Austin highlights its complexities. Only by doing so, according to Austin, can we avoid introducing false dichotomies.


''Philosophical Papers''

Austin's papers were collected and published posthumously as ''Philosophical Papers'' by J. O. Urmson and Geoffrey Warnock. The book originally contained ten papers, two more being added in the second edition and one in the third. His paper "Excuses" has had a massive impact on criminal law theory. Chapters 1 and 3 study how a word may have different, but related, senses. Chapters 2 and 4 discuss the nature of knowledge, focusing on
performative utterance In the philosophy of language and speech acts theory, performative utterances are sentences which not only describe a given reality, but also change the social reality they are describing. In a 1955 lecture series, later published as ''How to D ...
. Chapters 5 and 6 study the correspondence theory, where a statement is true when it corresponds to a fact. Chapters 6 and 10 concern the doctrine of
speech acts Speech is the use of the human voice as a medium for language. Spoken language combines vowel and consonant sounds to form units of meaning like words, which belong to a language's lexicon. There are many different intentional speech acts, suc ...
. Chapters 8, 9, and 12 reflect on the problems that language encounters in discussing actions and considering the cases of excuses, accusations, and freedom.


"Are There ''A Priori'' Concepts?"

This early paper contains a broad criticism of
idealism Idealism in philosophy, also known as philosophical realism or metaphysical idealism, is the set of metaphysics, metaphysical perspectives asserting that, most fundamentally, reality is equivalent to mind, Spirit (vital essence), spirit, or ...
. The question set dealing with the existence of ''
a priori ('from the earlier') and ('from the later') are Latin phrases used in philosophy to distinguish types of knowledge, Justification (epistemology), justification, or argument by their reliance on experience. knowledge is independent from any ...
'' concepts is treated only indirectly, by dismissing the concept of ''concept'' that underpins it. The first part of this paper takes the form of a reply to an argument for the existence of universals: from observing that we do use words such as "grey" or "circular", and that we use a single term in each case, it follows that there must be a ''something'' that is named by such terms—a universal. Furthermore, since each case of "grey" or "circular" is different, it follows that universals ''themselves'' cannot be sensed. Austin carefully dismantles this argument, and in the process other
transcendental arguments A transcendental argument is a kind of deductive argument that appeals to the necessary conditions that make experience and knowledge possible.Transcendental-arguments and Scepticism; Answering the Question of Justification (Clarendon Press: Oxfo ...
. He points out first that universals are not "something we stumble across", and that they are ''defined'' by their relation to particulars. He continues by pointing out that, from the observation that we use "grey" and "circular" ''as if'' they were the names of things, it does not necessarily follow that these ''are actually'' things that exist, in any sense but the nominal. In the process he dismisses the notion that "words are essentially proper names", asking: "...why, if 'one identical' word is used, ''must'' there be 'one identical object' present which it denotes?" In the second part of the article, he generalizes this argument against universals to address
concept A concept is an abstract idea that serves as a foundation for more concrete principles, thoughts, and beliefs. Concepts play an important role in all aspects of cognition. As such, concepts are studied within such disciplines as linguistics, ...
s as a whole. He points out that it is "facile" to treat concepts as if they were "an article of property". Such questions as "do we possess such-and-such a concept?" and "how do we come to possess such-and-such a concept?" are meaningless, because concepts are not the sort of thing that one possesses. In the final part of the paper, Austin further extends the discussion to relations, presenting a series of arguments to reject the idea that there is some ''thing'' that is a relation. His argument likely follows from the conjecture of his colleague S. V. Tezlaf, who questioned what makes "this" "that".


"The Meaning of a Word"

''The Meaning of a Word'' is a polemic against doing
philosophy Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
by attempting to pin down the ''meaning'' of the words used, arguing that 'there is ''no'' simple and handy appendage of a word called "the meaning of the word (x)"'. Austin warns us to take care when removing words from their ordinary usage, giving numerous examples of how this can lead to error.


"Other Minds"

In ''Other Minds'', one of his most highly acclaimed pieces, Austin criticizes the method that philosophers have used since Descartes to analyze and verify statements of the form "That person S feels X." This method works from the following three assumptions: *(1) We can know only if we intuit and directly feel what he feels. *(2) It is impossible to do so. *(3) It may be possible to find strong evidence for belief in our impressions. Although Austin agrees with (2), quipping that "we should be in a pretty predicament if I did", he found (1) to be false and (3) to be therefore unnecessary. The background assumption to (1), Austin claims, is that if I say that I know X and later find out that X is false, I did not know it. Austin believes that this is not consistent with the way we actually use language. He claims that if I was in a position where I would normally say that I know X, if X should turn out to be false, I would be speechless rather than self-corrective. He gives an argument that this is so by suggesting that believing is to knowing as intending is to promising— knowing and promising are the speech-act versions of believing and intending respectively.


"A Plea for Excuses"

''A Plea for Excuses'' is both a demonstration by example, and a defense of the methods of
ordinary language philosophy Ordinary language philosophy (OLP) is a philosophical methodology that sees traditional philosophical problems as rooted in misunderstandings philosophers develop by distorting or forgetting how words are ordinarily used to convey meaning in ...
, which proceeds on the conviction that: "...our common stock of words embodies all the distinctions men have found worth drawing, and the connections they have found worth marking, in the lifetime of many generations: these surely are likely to be more numerous, more sound, since they have stood up to the long test of survival of the fittest, and more subtle, at least in all ordinary and reasonable practical matters, than any that you or I are likely to think up in our armchair of an afternoon—the most favourite alternative method." An example of such a distinction Austin describes in a footnote is that between the phrases "by mistake" and "by accident". Although their uses are similar, Austin argues that with the right examples we can see that a distinction exists in when one or the other phrase is appropriate. Austin proposes some curious philosophical tools. For instance, he uses a sort of word game for developing an understanding of a key concept. This involves taking up a dictionary and finding a selection of terms relating to the key concept, then looking up each of the words in the explanation of their meaning. This process is iterated until the list of words begins to repeat, closing a "family circle" of words relating to the key concept.


Quotes

* "The theory of truth is a series of truisms." —'' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', vol. xxiv (1950). ''Philosophical Papers'', p. 121. Oxford University Press, second edition (1970). * "Sentences are not ''as such'' either true or false." —'' Sense and Sensibilia'' (1962), p. 111. * "It is, of course, not really correct that a sentence ever ''is'' a statement: rather, it is ''used'' in ''making a statement'', and the statement itself is a 'logical construction' out of the makings of statements." —''How to Do Things with Words'', Lecture 1, page 1 footnote 1. Oxford at the Clarendon press (1955). * "Going back into the history of a word, very often into Latin, we come back pretty commonly to pictures or models of how things happen or are done. These models may be fairly sophisticated and recent, as is perhaps the case with 'motive' or 'impulse', but one of the commonest and most primitive types of model is one which is apt to baffle us through its very naturalness and simplicity."
A Plea for Excuses
(1956). Published in ''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1956-7.'' Transcribed into hypertext by Andrew Chrucky, 23 August 2004. *"A sentence is ''made up'' of words, a statement is made ''in'' words ... Statements are made, words or sentences are used." —''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', vol. xxiv (1950); published in ''Philosophical Papers'', p. 120. Oxford University Press, second edition (1970). * "We walk along the cliff, and I feel a sudden impulse to push you over, which I promptly do: I acted on impulse, yet I certainly intended to push you over, and may even have devised a little ruse to achieve it; yet even then I did not act deliberately, for I did not (stop to) ask myself whether to do it or not." —''Philosophical Papers'', "The Meaning of a Word," p. 195. Oxford University Press, second edition (1970). * "You are more than entitled not to know what the word 'performative' means. It is a new word and an ugly word, and perhaps it does not mean anything very much. But at any rate there is one thing in its favor, it is not a profound word." —''Philosophical Papers'', "Performative Utterances", p. 233. Oxford University Press, second edition (1970). * "Let us distinguish between acting intentionally and acting deliberately or on purpose, as far as this can be done by attending to what language can teach us." —''Philosophical Papers'', "Three Ways of Spilling Ink," p. 273. Oxford University Press, second edition (1970). * "Usually it is ''uses'' of words, not words in themselves, that are properly called 'vague.'" —''Sense and Sensibilia'', p. 126. Oxford University Press (1962). * "But then we have to ask, of course, what this class comprises. We are given, as examples, 'familiar objects'—chairs, tables, pictures, books, flowers, pens, cigarettes; the expression 'material thing' is not here (or anywhere else in Ayer's text) further defined. But does the ordinary man believe that what he perceives is (always) something like furniture, or like these other 'familiar objects'—moderate-sized specimens of dry goods?" —''Sense and Sensibilia'', p. 8. Oxford University Press (1962). * During a lecture at
Columbia University Columbia University in the City of New York, commonly referred to as Columbia University, is a Private university, private Ivy League research university in New York City. Established in 1754 as King's College on the grounds of Trinity Churc ...
attended by American philosopher Sidney Morgenbesser, Austin made the claim that although a
double negative A double negative is a construction occurring when two forms of grammatical negation are used in the same sentence. This is typically used to convey a different shade of meaning from a strictly positive sentence ("You're not unattractive" vs "You ...
in English implies a positive meaning, there is no language in which a double positive implies a negative. To which Morgenbesser responded in a dismissive tone, "Yeah, yeah." (Some have quoted it as "Yeah, right.")


Publications


Books


Authored

* '' Philosophical Papers'' 1961, 1970, 1979, (eds. J. O. Urmson and G. J. Warnock), Oxford:
Oxford University Press Oxford University Press (OUP) is the publishing house of the University of Oxford. It is the largest university press in the world. Its first book was printed in Oxford in 1478, with the Press officially granted the legal right to print books ...
. * ''How to Do Things with Words: The William James Lectures delivered at Harvard University in 1955'', 1962 (ed. J. O. Urmson), 2nd edition, 1975 (with Marina Sbisà), Oxford: Clarendon Press. * '' Sense and Sensibilia'', 1962 (ed. G. J. Warnock), Oxford:
Clarendon Press Oxford University Press (OUP) is the publishing house of the University of Oxford. It is the largest university press in the world. Its first book was printed in Oxford in 1478, with the Press officially granted the legal right to print books ...
.


Translated

* (Translation of '' Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik''.)


Papers and articles

* 1930s–1940s, "The Line and the Cave in Plato's Republic," reconstructed from notes by J. O. Urmson, in ''Philosophical Papers'' 1979 * 1938ms, extracts in: Price, A. (2018
"J. L. Austin's Lecture Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics: Making Sense of Aristotle on Akrasia."
In '' Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy'', V. 55. * 1939ms/1967, "Agathon and Eudaimonia in the Ethics of Aristotle," in J. M. E. Moravcsik (ed.), '' Aristotle: a collection of critical essays'', New York: Doubleday. Reprinted in ''Philosophical Papers'' 1970 * 1939
"Are There A Priori Concepts?"
'' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', Supplementary Volume 18: 83–105. Reprinted in '' Philosophical Papers'' 1961 * 1940ms, "The Meaning of a Word," in '' Philosophical Papers'' 1961, Reprinted in C. E. Caton ed., '' Philosophy and Ordinary Language'', University of Illinois Press 1963. * 1946, "Other Minds," ''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', Supplementary Volume 20: 148–187. Reprinted in '' Philosophical Papers'' 1961 * 1950, "Truth," ''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', Supplementary Volume 24: 111–128. Reprinted in '' Philosophical Papers'' 1961, and i
''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'' ''Virtual Issue No. I: Truth''
(2013) * 1953
"How to Talk—some simple ways"
''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', 53: 227–246. Reprinted in '' Philosophical Papers'' 1961 * 1954ms, "Unfair to Facts," in '' Philosophical Papers'' 1961 * 1956a, "Ifs and Cans," ''
Proceedings of the British Academy The ''Proceedings of the British Academy'' is a series of academic volumes on subjects in the humanities and social sciences. The first volume was published in 1905. Up to 1991, the volumes (appearing annually from 1927) mostly consisted of the te ...
''. Reprinted in '' Philosophical Papers'' 1961 * 1956b
"Performative Utterances,"
corrected transcript of an unscripted radio talk delivered in the Third Programme of the
BBC The British Broadcasting Corporation (BBC) is a British public service broadcaster headquartered at Broadcasting House in London, England. Originally established in 1922 as the British Broadcasting Company, it evolved into its current sta ...
. In '' Philosophical Papers'' 1961 * 1957
"A Plea for Excuses: The Presidential Address"
''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', 57: 1–30. Reprinted in '' Philosophical Papers'' 1961 * 1958
"Pretending"
''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', Supplementary Volume 32: 261–278. Reprinted in '' Philosophical Papers'' 1961 * 1962, "Performatif-Constatif," in ''Cahiers de Royaumont, Philosophie No. IV, La Philosophie Analytique'', Les Editions de Minuit. ** Translated in 1963 as "Performative-Constative" by G. J. Warnock, in C. E. Caton ed., '' Philosophy and Ordinary Language'', University of Illinois Press.reprinted in '' Philosophy of Language: The Central Topics'' 2008, Nuccetelli, Susana (ed.), Seay, Gary (Series ed.) * 1966, "Three Ways of Spilling Ink", L. W. Forguson (ed.), ''The Philosophical Review'', 75 (4): 427–440. Reprinted in '' Approaches to Ethics'', 2d ed., ed. W. T. Jones, F. Sontag, M. O. Beckner, and R. J. Fogelin (New York: McGraw Hill Book Co., 1969), and ''Philosophical Papers'' 1970,


See also

* * * *


Notes


References


Further reading

* Berlin, I. et al., (ed.) (1973) '' Essays on J.L. Austin'', Oxford: The Clarendon Press. * Cavell, S. (1990), '' The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy'', New York:
Oxford University Press Oxford University Press (OUP) is the publishing house of the University of Oxford. It is the largest university press in the world. Its first book was printed in Oxford in 1478, with the Press officially granted the legal right to print books ...
. (The major work by one of Austin's most prominent heirs. Takes ordinary language approaches to issues of skepticism, but also makes those approaches a subject of scrutiny.) * Fann, K.T., ed. (1969), ''Symposium on J.L. Austin'', New York: Humanities Press. * Felman, Shoshana (2002), ''The Scandal of the Speaking Body: Don Juan with J. L. Austin, or Seduction in Two Languages'', Stanford: Stanford UP. * Friggieri, Joe (1993), " Linguaggio e azione. Saggio su J. L. Austin", Milano: Vita e Pensiero * Friggieri, Joe (1991), "Actions and Speech Actions: In the Philosophy of J. L. Austin", Msida: Mireva Publications * Garvey, Brian, ed. (2004), ''J. L. Austin on Language'', Palgrave, Houndmills (UK). (Includes ''Remembering J. L. Austin'' by Austin's younger sister, Ann Lendrum, and ''Recollections of J. L. Austin'' by
John Searle John Rogers Searle (; born July 31, 1932) is an American philosopher widely noted for contributions to the philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, and social philosophy. He began teaching at UC Berkeley in 1959 and was Willis S. and Mario ...
.) * Gustafsson, M. and Sørli, R. (2011), ''The Philosophy of J. L. Austin''. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Anthology of philosophical essays on Austin's work.) * Kirkham, R. (1992, reprinted 1995), '' Theories of Truth: A Critical Introduction''. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. . (Chapter 4 contains a detailed discussion of Austin's theory of truth.) * Nagel, Thomas
"Leader of the Martians"
(review of M.W. Rowe, ''J.L. Austin: Philosopher and D-Day Intelligence Officer'', Oxford, May 2023, , 660 pp.), ''
London Review of Books The ''London Review of Books'' (''LRB'') is a British literary magazine published bimonthly that features articles and essays on fiction and non-fiction subjects, which are usually structured as book reviews. History The ''London Review of Book ...
'', vol. 45, no. 17 (7 September 2023), pp. 9–10. "I he reviewer, Thomas Nagelwas one of Austin's last students..." (p. 10.) A quotation from Austin: "Is it not possible that the next century may see the birth... of a true and comprehensive ''
science Science is a systematic discipline that builds and organises knowledge in the form of testable hypotheses and predictions about the universe. Modern science is typically divided into twoor threemajor branches: the natural sciences, which stu ...
'' of ''
language Language is a structured system of communication that consists of grammar and vocabulary. It is the primary means by which humans convey meaning, both in spoken and signed language, signed forms, and may also be conveyed through writing syste ...
''? Then we shall have rid ourselves of one more part of
philosophy Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
... in the only way we ever can get rid of philosophy, by kicking it upstairs." (p. 10.) * Passmore, J. (1966), '' A Hundred Years of Philosophy'', rev. ed. New York: Basic Books. (Chapter 18 includes a perceptive exposition of Austin's philosophical project.) * Pitcher, G. (1973), "Austin: a personal memoir" in '' Essays on J.L. Austin'', ed. Berlin, I. et al. Oxford: The Clarendon Press. * Putnam, H. (1999), "The Importance of Being Austin: The Need of a 'Second Näivetē'" Lecture Two in '' The Threefold Cord: Mind, Body, and World'' New York: Columbia University Press. (In arguing for "naive realism", Putnam invokes Austin's handling of sense-data theories and their reliance on arguments from perceptual illusion in ''Sense and Sensibilia'', which Putnam calls "one of the most unjustly neglected classics of analytics philosophy".) * Rowe, M. W. (2023), ''J.L. Austin: Philosopher and D-Day Intelligence Officer''. Oxford: Oxford University Press. * Searle, J. (1969), ''Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language'', Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Searle's has been the most notable of attempts to extend and adjust Austin's conception of speech acts.) * Searle, J. (1979), '' Expression and Meaning: Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts'', Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979. * Searle, J.. (2001
"J. L. Austin (1911–1960)"
in Martinich, A. P.; Sosa, David (eds.) ''A Companion to Analytic Philosophy'', Blackwell, 2001'')'' * Soames, S. (2005), ''Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century: Volume II: The Age of Meaning''. Princeton: Princeton UP. (Contains a large section on ordinary language philosophy, and a chapter on Austin's treatment of skepticism and perception in ''Sense and Sensibilia''.) * Warnock, G. J. (1964
"Austin, John Langshaw, 1911-1960"
''Proceedings of the British Academy'' 49. * Warnock, G. J. (1969) "John Langshaw Austin, a biographical sketch", in ''Symposium on J. L. Austin'', K.T. Fann (ed), New York: Humanities Press. * Warnock, G. J. (1979), ''Philosophical Papers'', Oxford: OUP (Clarendon Paperbacks), * Warnock, G. J. (1973), "Saturday Mornings" in '' Essays on J.L. Austin'' I. Berlin et al. (ed) Oxford: The Clarendon Press. * Warnock, G. J. (1992), ''J. L. Austin'', London: Routledge.


External links


J. L. Austin
''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' *
"J. L. Austin: A return to common sense"
'' TLS Online 'Footnotes to Plato article by Guy Longworth (on 'Austin's view that philosophers fail to understand everyday speech').
"Guy Longworth on J.L. Austin and Ordinary Language"
'' Philosophy Bites'' (audio) interview.
Lecture and Q&A session by J. L. Austin
in Sweden (October 1959), uploaded by Harvard Philosophy Department to
YouTube YouTube is an American social media and online video sharing platform owned by Google. YouTube was founded on February 14, 2005, by Steve Chen, Chad Hurley, and Jawed Karim who were three former employees of PayPal. Headquartered in ...
{{DEFAULTSORT:Austin, John Langshaw People from Lancaster, Lancashire 1911 births 1960 deaths Deaths from lung cancer Deaths from cancer in England People educated at Shrewsbury School Alumni of Balliol College, Oxford 20th-century British philosophers Analytic philosophers Intelligence Corps officers British Army personnel of World War II British philosophers Philosophers of language Action theorists White's Professors of Moral Philosophy Ordinary language philosophy Presidents of the Aristotelian Society Officers of the Order of the British Empire