Henkin quantifier
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premise ...
a branching quantifier, also called a Henkin quantifier, finite partially ordered quantifier or even nonlinear quantifier, is a partial ordering :\langle Qx_1\dots Qx_n\rangle of quantifiers for ''Q'' ∈ . It is a special case of
generalized quantifier In formal semantics, a generalized quantifier (GQ) is an expression that denotes a set of sets. This is the standard semantics assigned to quantified noun phrases. For example, the generalized quantifier ''every boy'' denotes the set of sets of ...
. In classical logic, quantifier prefixes are linearly ordered such that the value of a variable ''ym'' bound by a quantifier ''Qm'' depends on the value of the variables : ''y''1, ..., ''y''''m''−1 bound by quantifiers : ''Qy''1, ..., ''Qy''''m''−1 preceding ''Qm''. In a logic with (finite) partially ordered quantification this is not in general the case. Branching quantification first appeared in a 1959 conference paper of
Leon Henkin Leon Albert Henkin (April 19, 1921, Brooklyn, New York - November 1, 2006, Oakland, California) was an American logician, whose works played a strong role in the development of logic, particularly in the theory of types. He was an active scholar ...
. Systems of partially ordered quantification are intermediate in strength between
first-order logic First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantifie ...
and
second-order logic In logic and mathematics, second-order logic is an extension of first-order logic, which itself is an extension of propositional logic. Second-order logic is in turn extended by higher-order logic and type theory. First-order logic quantifies on ...
. They are being used as a basis for Hintikka's and Gabriel Sandu's independence-friendly logic.


Definition and properties

The simplest Henkin quantifier Q_H is :(Q_Hx_1,x_2,y_1,y_2)\varphi(x_1,x_2,y_1,y_2)\equiv\begin\forall x_1 \, \exists y_1\\ \forall x_2 \, \exists y_2\end\varphi(x_1,x_2,y_1,y_2). It (in fact every formula with a Henkin prefix, not just the simplest one) is equivalent to its second-order
Skolemization In mathematical logic, a formula of first-order logic is in Skolem normal form if it is in prenex normal form with only universal first-order quantifiers. Every first-order formula may be converted into Skolem normal form while not changing its ...
, i.e. : \exists f \, \exists g \, \forall x_1 \forall x_2 \, \varphi (x_1, x_2, f(x_1), g(x_2)). It is also powerful enough to define the quantifier Q_ (i.e. "there are infinitely many") defined as :(Q_x)\varphi (x)\equiv(\exists a)(Q_Hx_1,x_2,y_1,y_2) varphi(a)\land (x_1=x_2 \leftrightarrow y_1=y_2) \land (\varphi (x_1)\rightarrow (\varphi (y_1)\land y_1\neq a)) Several things follow from this, including the nonaxiomatizability of first-order logic with Q_H (first observed by Ehrenfeucht), and its equivalence to the \Sigma_1^1-fragment of
second-order logic In logic and mathematics, second-order logic is an extension of first-order logic, which itself is an extension of propositional logic. Second-order logic is in turn extended by higher-order logic and type theory. First-order logic quantifies on ...
( existential second-order logic)—the latter result published independently in 1970 by
Herbert Enderton Herbert Bruce Enderton (April 15, 1936 – October 20, 2010) was an American mathematician. He was a Professor Emeritus of Mathematics at UCLA and a former member of the faculties of Mathematics and of Logic and the Methodology of Science at the ...
and W. Walkoe. The following quantifiers are also definable by Q_H. * Rescher: "The number of ''φ''s is less than or equal to the number of ''ψ''s" ::(Q_Lx)(\varphi x,\psi x)\equiv \operatorname(\ )\leq \operatorname(\ ) \equiv (Q_Hx_1x_2y_1y_2) x_1=x_2 \leftrightarrow y_1=y_2) \land (\varphi x_1 \rightarrow \psi y_1)/math> * Härtig: "The ''φ''s are equinumerous with the ''ψ''s" ::(Q_Ix)(\varphi x,\psi x)\equiv (Q_Lx)(\varphi x,\psi x) \land (Q_Lx)(\psi x,\varphi x) * Chang: "The number of ''φ''s is equinumerous with the domain of the model" ::(Q_Cx)(\varphi x)\equiv (Q_Lx)(x=x,\varphi x) The Henkin quantifier Q_H can itself be expressed as a type (4) Lindström quantifier.


Relation to natural languages

Hintikka in a 1973 paper advanced the hypothesis that some sentences in natural languages are best understood in terms of branching quantifiers, for example: "some relative of each villager and some relative of each townsman hate each other" is supposed to be interpreted, according to Hintikka, as: : \begin\forall x_1 \, \exists y_1\\ \forall x_2 \, \exists y_2\end V(x_1) \wedge T(x_2)) \rightarrow (R(x_1,y_1) \wedge R(x_2,y_2) \wedge H(y_1, y_2) \wedge H(y_2, y_1)) which is known to have no first-order logic equivalent. The idea of branching is not necessarily restricted to using the classical quantifiers as leaves. In a 1979 paper,
Jon Barwise Kenneth Jon Barwise (; June 29, 1942 – March 5, 2000) was an American mathematician, philosopher and logician who proposed some fundamental revisions to the way that logic is understood and used. Education and career Born in Independence, ...
proposed variations of Hintikka sentences (as the above is sometimes called) in which the inner quantifiers are themselves generalized quantifiers, for example: "Most villagers and most townsmen hate each other." Observing that \Sigma_1^1 is not closed under negation, Barwise also proposed a practical test to determine whether natural language sentences really involve branching quantifiers, namely to test whether their natural-language negation involves universal quantification over a set variable (a \Pi_1^1 sentence). Hintikka's proposal was met with skepticism by a number of logicians because some first-order sentences like the one below appear to capture well enough the natural language Hintikka sentence. : forall x_1 \, \exists y_1 \, \forall x_2 \, \exists y_2\, \varphi (x_1, x_2, y_1, y_2)\wedge forall x_2 \, \exists y_2 \, \forall x_1 \, \exists y_1\, \varphi (x_1, x_2, y_1, y_2)/math> where : \varphi (x_1, x_2, y_1, y_2) denotes : (V(x_1) \wedge T(x_2)) \rightarrow (R(x_1,y_1) \wedge R(x_2,y_2) \wedge H(y_1, y_2) \wedge H(y_2, y_1)) Although much purely theoretical debate followed, it wasn't until 2009 that some empirical tests with students trained in logic found that they are more likely to assign models matching the "bidirectional" first-order sentence rather than branching-quantifier sentence to several natural-language constructs derived from the Hintikka sentence. For instance students were shown undirected bipartite graphs—with squares and circles as vertices—and asked to say whether sentences like "more than 3 circles and more than 3 squares are connected by lines" were correctly describing the diagrams.


See also

*
Game semantics Game semantics (german: dialogische Logik, translated as ''dialogical logic'') is an approach to Formal semantics (logic), formal semantics that grounds the concepts of truth or Validity (logic), validity on game theory, game-theoretic concepts, su ...
* Dependence logic * Independence-friendly logic (IF logic) * Mostowski quantifier * Lindström quantifier *
Nonfirstorderizability In formal logic, nonfirstorderizability is the inability of a natural-language statement to be adequately captured by a formula of first-order logic. Specifically, a statement is nonfirstorderizable if there is no formula of first-order logic whic ...


References

{{reflist


External links


Game-theoretical quantifier
at PlanetMath. Quantifier (logic)