Humeanism refers to the philosophy of
David Hume
David Hume (; born David Home; 7 May 1711 NS (26 April 1711 OS) – 25 August 1776) Cranston, Maurice, and Thomas Edmund Jessop. 2020 999br>David Hume" ''Encyclopædia Britannica''. Retrieved 18 May 2020. was a Scottish Enlightenment philo ...
and to the tradition of thought inspired by him. Hume was an influential Scottish philosopher well known for his empirical approach, which he applied to various fields in philosophy.
In the
philosophy of science
Philosophy of science is a branch of philosophy concerned with the foundations, methods, and implications of science. The central questions of this study concern what qualifies as science, the reliability of scientific theories, and the ultim ...
, he is notable for developing the ''regularity theory of causation'', which in its strongest form states that causation is nothing but constant conjunction of certain types of events without any underlying forces responsible for this regularity of conjunction. This is closely connected to his metaphysical thesis that there are ''no necessary connections between distinct entities''. The Humean theory of
action
Action may refer to:
* Action (narrative), a literary mode
* Action fiction, a type of genre fiction
* Action game, a genre of video game
Film
* Action film, a genre of film
* ''Action'' (1921 film), a film by John Ford
* ''Action'' (1980 fil ...
defines actions as ''bodily behavior caused by mental states and processes'' without the need to refer to an agent responsible for this. The slogan of Hume's theory of
practical reason
In philosophy, practical reason is the use of reason to decide how to act. It contrasts with theoretical reason, often called speculative reason, the use of reason to decide what to follow. For example, agents use practical reason to decide whethe ...
is that "reason is...the slave of the passions". It restricts the sphere of practical reason to ''instrumental rationality'' concerning which means to employ to achieve a given end. But it denies reason a direct role regarding which ends to follow. Central to Hume's position in
metaethics
In metaphilosophy and ethics, meta-ethics is the study of the nature, scope, and meaning of moral judgment. It is one of the three branches of ethics generally studied by philosophers, the others being normative ethics (questions of how one ought ...
is the
is-ought distinction. It states that ''is-statements'', which concern facts about the natural world, do not imply ''ought-statements'', which are moral or
evaluative claims about what should be done or what has value. In
philosophy of mind
Philosophy of mind is a branch of philosophy that studies the ontology and nature of the mind and its relationship with the body. The mind–body problem is a paradigmatic issue in philosophy of mind, although a number of other issues are addre ...
, Hume is well known for his development of the
bundle theory
Bundle theory, originated by the 18th century Scottish philosopher David Hume, is the ontological theory about objecthood in which an object consists only of a collection (''bundle'') of properties, relations or tropes.
According to bundle the ...
of the self. It states that the self is to be understood as a bundle of mental states and not as a substance acting as the bearer of these states, as is the traditional conception. Many of these positions were initially motivated by Hume's
empirical outlook. It emphasizes the need to ground one's theories in experience and faults opposing theories for failing to do so. But many philosophers within the Humean tradition have gone beyond these methodological restrictions and have drawn various
metaphysical
Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the fundamental nature of reality, the first principles of being, identity and change, space and time, causality, necessity, and possibility. It includes questions about the nature of conscio ...
conclusions from Hume's ideas.
Causality and necessity
''
Causality
Causality (also referred to as causation, or cause and effect) is influence by which one event, process, state, or object (''a'' ''cause'') contributes to the production of another event, process, state, or object (an ''effect'') where the cau ...
'' is usually understood as a relation between two
events
Event may refer to:
Gatherings of people
* Ceremony, an event of ritual significance, performed on a special occasion
* Convention (meeting), a gathering of individuals engaged in some common interest
* Event management, the organization of ev ...
where the earlier event is responsible for bringing about or ''necessitating'' the later event. Hume's account of causality has been influential. His first question is how to categorize causal relations. On his view, they belong either to ''relations of ideas'' or ''matters of fact''. This distinction is referred to as
Hume's fork. ''Relations of ideas'' involve necessary connections that are knowable
a priori
("from the earlier") and ("from the later") are Latin phrases used in philosophy to distinguish types of knowledge, justification, or argument by their reliance on empirical evidence or experience. knowledge is independent from current ex ...
independently of experience. ''Matters of fact'', on the other hand, concern
contingent propositions
In philosophy and logic, contingency is the status of propositions that are neither true under every possible valuation (i.e. tautologies) nor false under every possible valuation (i.e. contradictions). A contingent proposition is neither necess ...
about the world knowable only a posteriori through perception and memory.
Causal relations fall under the category of matters of facts, according to Hume, since it is conceivable that they do not obtain, which would not be the case if they were necessary. For Hume's
empiricist outlook, this means that causal relations should be studied by attending to sensory experience.
The problem with this is that the causal relation itself is never given directly in perception. Through visual perception, for example, we can know that a stone was first thrown in the direction of a window and that subsequently, the window broke, but we do not directly see that the throwing caused the breaking. This leads to Hume's
skeptical
Skepticism, also spelled scepticism, is a questioning attitude or doubt toward knowledge claims that are seen as mere belief or dogma. For example, if a person is skeptical about claims made by their government about an ongoing war then the p ...
conclusion: that, strictly speaking, we do not know that a causal relation was involved.
Instead, we just assume it based on earlier experiences that had very similar chains of events as their contents. This results in a habit of expecting the later event given the impression of the earlier one. On the metaphysical level, this conclusion has often been interpreted as the thesis that causation is nothing but constant conjunction of certain types of events. This is sometimes termed the "simple regularity theory of causation".
A closely related metaphysical thesis is known as
Hume's dictum: "
ere is no object, which implies the existence of any other if we consider these objects in themselves".
Jessica Wilson provides the following contemporary formulation: "
ere are no metaphysically necessary connections between wholly distinct, intrinsically typed, entities".
Hume's intuition motivating this thesis is that while experience presents us with certain ideas of various objects, it might as well have presented us with very different ideas. So when I perceive a bird on a tree, I might as well have perceived a bird without a tree or a tree without a bird. This is so because their
essence
Essence ( la, essentia) is a polysemic term, used in philosophy and theology as a designation for the property or set of properties that make an entity or substance what it fundamentally is, and which it has by necessity, and without which it ...
s do not depend upon one another.
Followers and interpreters of Hume have sometimes used ''Hume's dictum'' as the metaphysical foundation of ''Hume's theory of causation''. On this view, there cannot be any causal relation in a robust sense since this would involve one event necessitating another event, the possibility of which is denied by Hume's dictum.
Hume's dictum has been employed in various arguments in contemporary
metaphysics
Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the fundamental nature of reality, the first principles of being, identity and change, space and time, causality, necessity, and possibility. It includes questions about the nature of conscio ...
. It can be used, for example, as an argument against
nomological
In philosophy, nomology refers to a "science of laws" based on the theory that it is possible to elaborate descriptions dedicated not to particular aspects of reality but inspired by a scientific vision of universal validity expressed by scientific ...
necessitarianism
Necessitarianism is a metaphysical principle that denies all mere possibility; there is exactly one way for the world to be.
It is the strongest member of a family of principles, including hard determinism, each of which deny libertarian free wil ...
, the view that the
laws of nature are necessary, i.e. are the same in all
possible world
A possible world is a complete and consistent way the world is or could have been. Possible worlds are widely used as a formal device in logic, philosophy, and linguistics in order to provide a semantics for intensional logic, intensional and mod ...
s. To see how this might work, consider the case of salt being thrown into a cup of water and subsequently dissolving. This can be described as a series of two events, a throwing-event and a dissolving-event. Necessitarians hold that all possible worlds with the throwing-event also contain a subsequent dissolving-event. But the two events are distinct entities, so according to Hume's dictum, it is possible to have one event without the other.
David Lewis follows this line of thought in formulating his ''principle of recombination'': "anything can coexist with anything else, at least provided they occupy distinct spatiotemporal positions. Likewise, anything can fail to coexist with anything else".
Combined with the assumption that reality consists on the most fundamental level of nothing but a spatio-temporal distribution of local natural properties, this thesis is known as "
Humean supervenience
Humeanism refers to the philosophy of David Hume and to the tradition of thought inspired by him. Hume was an influential Scottish philosopher well known for his empirical approach, which he applied to various fields in philosophy. In the philosop ...
". It states that laws of nature and causal relations merely
supervene
In philosophy, supervenience refers to a relation between sets of properties or sets of facts. X is said to supervene on Y if and only if some difference in Y is necessary for any difference in X to be possible. Some examples include:
* Whether t ...
on this distribution of local natural properties. An even wider application is to use Hume's dictum as the foundational principle determining which propositions or worlds are possible and which are impossible based on the notion of recombination.
Not all interpreters agree that the ''reductive metaphysical outlook'' on causation of the Humean tradition presented in the last paragraphs actually reflects Hume's own position.
Some argue against the ''metaphysical aspect'', instead claiming that Hume's view concerning causality remained within the field of epistemology as a skeptical position on the possibility of knowing about causal relations. Others, sometimes referred to as the "New Hume tradition", reject the ''reductive aspect'' by holding that Hume was, despite his skeptical outlook, a robust
realist about causation.
Theory of action
''Theories of
action
Action may refer to:
* Action (narrative), a literary mode
* Action fiction, a type of genre fiction
* Action game, a genre of video game
Film
* Action film, a genre of film
* ''Action'' (1921 film), a film by John Ford
* ''Action'' (1980 fil ...
'' try to determine what actions are, specifically their essential features. One important feature of ''actions'', which sets them apart from ''mere behavior'', is that they are
intentional
Intentions are mental states in which the agent commits themselves to a course of action. Having the plan to visit the zoo tomorrow is an example of an intention. The action plan is the ''content'' of the intention while the commitment is the ''a ...
or guided "under an idea".
On this issue, Hume's analysis of action emphasizes the role of psychological faculties and states, like reasoning, sensation, memory, and passion. It is characteristic of his outlook that it manages to define action without reference to an ''agent''. ''Agency'' arises instead from psychological states and processes like beliefs, desires and deliberation.
Some actions are initiated upon concluding an explicit deliberation on which course of action to take. But for many other actions, this is not the case. Hume infers from this that "
acts of the will" are not a necessary requirement for actions.
The most prominent philosopher of action in the Humean tradition is
Donald Davidson. Following Hume in defining actions without reference to an agent, he holds that actions are bodily movements that are caused by intentions.
The intentions themselves are explained in terms of
beliefs
A belief is an attitude that something is the case, or that some proposition is true. In epistemology, philosophers use the term "belief" to refer to attitudes about the world which can be either true or false. To believe something is to take i ...
and
desires
Desires are states of mind that are expressed by terms like "wanting", "wishing", "longing" or "craving". A great variety of features is commonly associated with desires. They are seen as propositional attitudes towards conceivable states of affa ...
.
For example, the action of flipping a light switch rests, on the one hand, on the agent's belief that this bodily movement would turn on the light and, on the other hand, on the desire to have light. According to Davidson, it is not just the bodily behavior that counts as the action but also the consequences that follow from it. So the movement of the finger flipping the switch is part of the action as well as the electrons moving through the wire and the light bulb turning on. Some consequences are included in the action even though the agent did not intend them to happen.
It is sufficient that what the agent does "can be described under an aspect that makes it intentional".
So, for example, if flipping the light switch alerts the burglar then alerting the burglar is part of the agent's actions.
One important objection to Davidson's and similar Humean theories focuses on the central role assigned to ''causation'' in defining action as bodily behavior ''caused'' by intention. The problem has been referred to as ''wayward'' or ''deviant'' causal chains.
A causal chain is ''wayward'' if the intention caused its goal to realize but in a very unusual way that was not intended, e.g. because the skills of the agent are not exercised in the way planned.
For example, a rock climber forms the intention to kill the climber below him by letting go of the rope. A wayward causal chain would be that, instead of opening the holding hand intentionally, the intention makes the first climber so nervous that the rope slips through his hand and thus leads to the other climber's death. Davidson addresses this issue by excluding cases of wayward causation from his account since they are not examples of intentional behavior in the strict sense. So bodily behavior only constitutes an action if it was caused by intentions ''in the right way''. But this response has been criticized because of its vagueness since spelling out what "right way" means has proved rather difficult.
Practical reason
The slogan of Hume's theory of
practical reason
In philosophy, practical reason is the use of reason to decide how to act. It contrasts with theoretical reason, often called speculative reason, the use of reason to decide what to follow. For example, agents use practical reason to decide whethe ...
is that "reason is...the slave of the passions".
It expresses the idea that it is the function of practical reason to find the ''means'' for realizing pre-given ''ends''. Important for this issue is the distinction between ''means'' and ''ends''. ''Ends'' are based on ''
intrinsic desires'', which are about things that are wanted for their own sake or are
valuable in themselves. ''Means'', on the other hand, are based on ''instrumental desires'' which want something for the sake of something else and thereby depend on other desires. So on this view, practical reason is about how to achieve something but it does not concern itself with what should be achieved.
What should be achieved is determined by the agent's intrinsic desires. This may vary a lot from person to person since different people want very different things.
In contemporary philosophy, Hume's theory of practical reason is often understood in terms of norms of
rationality
Rationality is the quality of being guided by or based on reasons. In this regard, a person acts rationally if they have a good reason for what they do or a belief is rational if it is based on strong evidence. This quality can apply to an abil ...
.
On the one hand, it is the thesis that we should be motivated to employ the means necessary for the ends we have. Failing to do so would be irrational.
Expressed in terms of practical reasons, it states that if an agent has a reason to realize an end, this reason is transmitted from the end to the means, i.e. the agent also has a derivative reason to employ the means.
This thesis is seldom contested since it seems quite intuitive. Failing to follow this requirement is a form of error, not only when judged from an external perspective, but even from the agent's own perspective: the agent cannot plead that he does not care since he already has a desire for the corresponding end.
On the other hand, contemporary Humeanism about practical reason includes the assertion that only our desires determine which initial reasons we have.
So having a desire to swim at the beach provides the agent with a reason to do so, which in turn provides him with a reason to travel to the beach. On this view, whether the agent has this desire is not a matter of being rational or not. Rationality just requires that an agent who wants to swim at the beach should be motivated to travel there. This thesis has proved most controversial.
Some have argued that desires do not provide reasons at all, or only in special cases. This position is often combined with an ''externalist'' view of rationality: that reasons are given not from the agent's psychological states but from objective facts about the world, for example, from what would be objectively best. This is reflected, for example, in the view that some desires are bad or irrational and can be criticized on these grounds.
On this position, psychological states like desires may be ''
motivational reasons'', which move the agent, but not ''normative reasons'', which determine what should be done. Others allow that desires provide reasons in the relevant sense but deny that this role is played only by desires. So there may be
other psychological states or processes, like evaluative beliefs or deliberation, that also determine what we should do. This can be combined with the thesis that practical reason has something to say about which ends we should follow, for example, by having an impact either on these other states or on desires directly.
A common dispute between Humeans and Anti-Humeans in the field of practical reason concerns the status of
morality
Morality () is the differentiation of intentions, decisions and actions between those that are distinguished as proper (right) and those that are improper (wrong). Morality can be a body of standards or principles derived from a code of cond ...
. Anti-Humeans often assert that everyone has a reason to be moral.
But this seems to be incompatible with the Humean position, according to which reasons depend on desires and not everyone has a desire to be moral. This poses the following threat: it may lead to cases where an agent simply justifies his immoral actions by pointing out that he had no desire to be moral.
One way to respond to this problem is to draw a clear distinction between rationality and morality. If rationality is concerned with what should be done according to the agent's own perspective then it may well be rational to act immorally in cases when the agent lacks moral desires. Such actions are then rationally justified but immoral nonetheless.
But it is a contested issue whether there really is such a gap between rationality and morality.
Metaethics
Central to Hume's position in
metaethics
In metaphilosophy and ethics, meta-ethics is the study of the nature, scope, and meaning of moral judgment. It is one of the three branches of ethics generally studied by philosophers, the others being normative ethics (questions of how one ought ...
is the
is-ought distinction. It is guided by the idea that there is an important difference between ''is-statements'', which concern facts about the natural world, and ''ought-statements'', which are moral or
evaluative claims about what should be done or what has value. The key aspect of this difference is that ''is-statements'' do not imply ''ought-statements''.
This is important, according to Hume, because this type of
mistaken inference has been a frequent source of error in the history of philosophy. Based on this distinction, interpreters have often attributed various related philosophical theses to Hume in relation to contemporary debates in metaethics.
One of these theses concerns the dispute between
cognitivism and
non-cognitivism
Non-cognitivism is the meta-ethical view that ethical sentences do not express propositions (i.e., statements) and thus cannot be true or false (they are not truth-apt). A noncognitivist denies the cognitivist claim that "moral judgments are c ...
. Cognitivists assert that ''ought-statements'' are ''truth-apt'', i.e. are either true or false. They resemble ''is-statements'' in this sense, which is rejected by non-cognitivists.
Some non-cognitivists deny that ''ought-statements'' have meaning at all, although the more common approach is to account for their meaning in other ways.
Prescriptivists treat ''ought-statements'' as prescriptions or commands, which are meaningful without having a truth-value.
Emotivists, on the other hand, hold that ''ought-statements'' merely express the speaker's emotional attitudes in the form of approval or disapproval. The debate between cognitivism and non-cognitivism concerns the semantic level about the meaning and truth-value of statements. It is reflected on the metaphysical level as the dispute about whether normative facts about what should be the case are part of reality, as
realists claim, or not, as
anti-realists contend. Based on Hume's denial that ''ought-statements'' are about facts, he is usually interpreted as an anti-realist.
But interpreters of Hume have raised various doubts both for labeling him as an anti-realist and as a non-cognitivist.
Bundle theory of the self
In philosophy of mind, Hume is well known for his development of the
bundle theory
Bundle theory, originated by the 18th century Scottish philosopher David Hume, is the ontological theory about objecthood in which an object consists only of a collection (''bundle'') of properties, relations or tropes.
According to bundle the ...
of the self.
In his analyses, he uses the terms "self", "mind" and "person" interchangeably.
He denies the traditional conception, usually associated with
René Descartes
René Descartes ( or ; ; Latinized: Renatus Cartesius; 31 March 1596 – 11 February 1650) was a French philosopher, scientist, and mathematician, widely considered a seminal figure in the emergence of modern philosophy and science. Mathem ...
, that the mind is constituted by a substance or an immaterial soul that acts as the bearer of all its mental states.
The key to Hume's critique of this conception comes from his
empirical outlook: that such a substance is never given as part of our experience. Instead, introspection only shows a manifold of mental states, referred to by Hume as "perceptions".
For Hume, this
epistemic
Epistemology (; ), or the theory of knowledge, is the branch of philosophy concerned with knowledge. Epistemology is considered a major subfield of philosophy, along with other major subfields such as ethics, logic, and metaphysics.
Episte ...
finding implies a
semantic
Semantics (from grc, σημαντικός ''sēmantikós'', "significant") is the study of reference, meaning, or truth. The term can be used to refer to subfields of several distinct disciplines, including philosophy, linguistics and comput ...
conclusion: that the words "mind" or "self" cannot mean ''substance of mental states'' but must mean ''bundle of perceptions''. This is the case because, according to Hume, words are associated with ideas and ideas are based on impressions. So without impressions of a mental substance, we lack the corresponding idea.
Hume's theory is often interpreted as involving an
ontological
In metaphysics, ontology is the philosophical study of being, as well as related concepts such as existence, becoming, and reality.
Ontology addresses questions like how entities are grouped into categories and which of these entities exis ...
claim about what selves actually are, which goes beyond the semantic claim about what the word "self" means. But others contend that this constitutes a misinterpretation of Hume since he restricts his claims to the epistemic and semantic level.
One problem for the bundle theory of the self is how to account for the ''unity'' of the self. This is usually understood in terms of
diachronic unity, i.e. how the mind is unified with itself at different times or how it persists through time. But it can also be understood in terms of synchronic unity, i.e. how at one specific time, there is unity among the different mental states had by the same subject.
A substance, unlike a simple collection, can explain either type of unity. This is why ''bundles'' are not equated with mere collections, the difference being that the bundled elements are linked to each other by a relation often referred to as "compresence", "co-personality" or "co-consciousness". Hume tried to understand this relation in terms of
resemblance
Resemblance may refer to:
*Similarity (philosophy)
*Resemblance nominalism
*Family Resemblance (anthropology)
*Ludwig Wittgenstein's family resemblances
*In text mining, the degree to which two documents resemble each other, calculated using shingl ...
and
causality
Causality (also referred to as causation, or cause and effect) is influence by which one event, process, state, or object (''a'' ''cause'') contributes to the production of another event, process, state, or object (an ''effect'') where the cau ...
.
On this account, two perceptions belong to the same mind if they resemble each other and/or stand in the right causal relations to each other. Hume's particular version of this approach is usually rejected, but there are various other proposals on how to solve this problem compatible with the bundle theory. They include accounting for the unity in terms of ''
psychological continuity'' or seeing it as a primitive aspect of the ''compresence-relation''.
References
{{reflist
Action (philosophy)
Empiricism
History of philosophy
Meta-ethics
Philosophy of mind
Philosophy of science
Reasoning