In
mathematical logic
Mathematical logic is the study of logic, formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of for ...
, the Hilbert–Bernays provability conditions, named after
David Hilbert
David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician, one of the most influential mathematicians of the 19th and early 20th centuries. Hilbert discovered and developed a broad range of fundamental ideas in many a ...
and
Paul Bernays
Paul Isaac Bernays (17 October 1888 – 18 September 1977) was a Swiss mathematician who made significant contributions to mathematical logic, axiomatic set theory, and the philosophy of mathematics. He was an assistant and close collaborator of ...
, are a set of requirements for formalized provability predicates in formal theories of arithmetic (Smith 2007:224).
These conditions are used in many proofs of
Kurt Gödel
Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( , ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel had an imme ...
's
second incompleteness theorem
The second (symbol: s) is the unit of time in the International System of Units (SI), historically defined as of a day – this factor derived from the division of the day first into 24 hours, then to 60 minutes and finally to 60 seconds e ...
. They are also closely related to axioms of
provability logic Provability logic is a modal logic, in which the box (or "necessity") operator is interpreted as 'it is provable that'. The point is to capture the notion of a proof predicate of a reasonably rich formal theory, such as Peano arithmetic.
Examples
...
.
The conditions
Let be a formal theory of arithmetic with a formalized provability predicate , which is expressed as a formula of with one free number variable. For each formula in the theory, let be the
Gödel number of . The Hilbert–Bernays provability conditions are:
# If proves a sentence then proves .
# For every sentence , proves
# proves that and imply
Note that is predicate of numbers, and it is a provability predicate in the sense that the intended interpretation of is that there exists a number that codes for a proof of . Formally what is required of is the above three conditions.
In the more concise notation of
provability logic Provability logic is a modal logic, in which the box (or "necessity") operator is interpreted as 'it is provable that'. The point is to capture the notion of a proof predicate of a reasonably rich formal theory, such as Peano arithmetic.
Examples
...
, letting
denote "
proves
" and
denote
:
#
#
#
Use in proving Gödel's incompleteness theorems
The Hilbert–Bernays provability conditions, combined with the
diagonal lemma
In mathematical logic, the diagonal lemma (also known as diagonalization lemma, self-reference lemma or fixed point theorem) establishes the existence of self-referential sentences in certain formal theories of the natural numbers—specificall ...
, allow proving both of Gödel's incompleteness theorems shortly. Indeed the main effort of Godel's proofs lied in showing that these conditions (or equivalent ones) and the diagonal lemma hold for Peano arithmetics; once these are established the proof can be easily formalized.
Using the diagonal lemma, there is a formula
such that
.
Proving Godel's first incompleteness theorem
For the first theorem only the first and third conditions are needed.
The condition that is
ω-consistent is generalized by the condition that if for every formula , if proves , then proves . Note that this indeed holds for an -consistent because means that there is a number coding for the proof of , and if is -consistent then going through all natural numbers one can actually find such a particular number , and then one can use to construct an actual proof of in .
Suppose T could have proven
. We then would have the following theorems in :
#
#
(by construction of
and theorem 1)
#
(by condition no. 1 and theorem 1)
Thus proves both
and
. But if is consistent, this is impossible, and we are forced to conclude that does not prove
.
Now let us suppose could have proven
. We then would have the following theorems in :
#
#
(by construction of
and theorem 1)
#
(by ω-consistency)
Thus proves both
and
. But if is consistent, this is impossible, and we are forced to conclude that does not prove
.
To conclude, can prove neither
nor
.
Using Rosser's trick
Using
Rosser's trick
In mathematical logic, Rosser's trick is a method for proving Gödel's incompleteness theorems without the assumption that the theory being considered is ω-consistent (Smorynski 1977, p. 840; Mendelson 1977, p. 160). This method ...
, one needs not assume that is -consistent. However, one would need to show that the first and third provability conditions holds for , Rosser's provability predicate, rather than for the naive provability predicate Prov. This follows from the fact that for every formula , holds if and only if holds.
An additional condition used is that proves that implies . This condition holds for every that includes logic and very basic arithmetics (as elaborated in
Rosser's trick#The Rosser sentence).
Using Rosser's trick, is defined using Rosser's provability predicate, instead of the naive provability predicate. The first part of the proof remains unchanged, except that the provability predicate is replaced with Rosser's provability predicate there, too.
The second part of the proof no longer uses ω-consistency, and is changed to the following:
Suppose could have proven
. We then would have the following theorems in :
#
#
(by construction of
and theorem 1)
#
(by theorem 2 and the additional condition following the definition of Rosser's provability predicate)
#
(by condition no. 1 and theorem 1)
Thus proves both
and
. But if is consistent, this is impossible, and we are forced to conclude that does not prove
.
The second theorem
We assume that proves its own consistency, i.e. that:
:
.
For every formula :
:
(by
negation elimination)
It is possible to show by using condition no. 1 on the latter theorem, followed by repeated use of condition no. 3, that:
:
And using proving its own consistency it follows that:
:
We now use this to show that is not consistent:
#
(following proving its own consistency, with
)
#
(by construction of
)
#
(by condition no. 1 and theorem 2)
#
(by condition no. 3 and theorem 3)
#
(by theorems 1 and 4)
#
(by condition no. 2)
#
(by theorems 5 and 6)
#
(by construction of
)
#
(by theorems 7 and 8)
#
(by condition 1 and theorem 9)
Thus proves both
and
, hence is inconsistent.
References
* Smith, Peter (2007). ''An introduction to Gödel's incompleteness theorems''. Cambridge University Press.
Mathematical logic
Provability logic
{{mathlogic-stub