In
theoretical computer science, in particular in
formal language theory, Greibach's theorem states that certain properties of
formal language classes are
undecidable. It is named after the computer scientist
Sheila Greibach
Sheila Adele Greibach (born 6 October 1939 in New York City) is a researcher in formal languages in computing, automata, compiler theory and computer science. She is an Emeritus Professor of Computer Science at the University of California, Los ...
, who first proved it in 1963.
Definitions
Given a set Σ, often called "alphabet", the (infinite) set of all
strings
String or strings may refer to:
*String (structure), a long flexible structure made from threads twisted together, which is used to tie, bind, or hang other objects
Arts, entertainment, and media Films
* ''Strings'' (1991 film), a Canadian anim ...
built from members of Σ is denoted by Σ
*.
A
formal language is a subset of Σ
*.
If ''L''
1 and ''L''
2 are formal languages, their
product ''L''
1''L''
2 is defined as the set of all
concatenations of a string ''w''
1 from ''L''
1 with a string ''w''
2 from ''L''
2.
If ''L'' is a formal language and ''a'' is a symbol from Σ, their quotient ''L''/''a'' is defined as the set of all strings that can be made members of ''L'' by appending an ''a''.
Various approaches are known from formal language theory to denote a formal language by a finite description, such as a
formal grammar or a
finite-state machine.
For example, using an alphabet Σ = , the set Σ
* consists of all (decimal representations of) natural numbers, with leading zeroes allowed, and the empty string, denoted as ε.
The set ''L''
div3 of all naturals divisible by 3 is an infinite formal language over Σ; it can be finitely described by the following
regular grammar with
start symbol ''S''
0:
:
Examples for finite languages are and ; their product yields the even numbers up to 28. The quotient of the set of prime numbers up to 100 by the symbol 7, 4, and 2 yields the language , , and , respectively.
Formal statement of the theorem
Greibach's theorem is independent of a particular approach to describe a formal language.
It just considers a set ''C'' of formal languages over an alphabet Σ∪ such that
* each language in ''C'' has a finite description,
* each regular language over Σ∪ is in ''C'',
[This is left implicit in Hopcroft, Ullman, 1979: ''P'' ⊆ ''C'' needs to contain all these regular languages.]
* given descriptions of languages ''L''
1, ''L''
2 ∈ ''C'' and of a regular language ''R'' ∈ ''C'', a description of the products ''L''
1''R'' and ''RL''
1, and of the union ''L''
1∪''L''
2 can be effectively computed, and
* it is undecidable for any member language ''L'' ∈ ''C'' with ''L'' ⊆ Σ
* whether ''L'' = Σ
*.
Let ''P'' be any nontrivial subset of ''C'' that contains all regular sets over Σ∪ and is closed under
quotient by each single symbol in Σ∪.
[That is, if ''L'' ∈ ''P'', then ''L''/''a'' ∈ ''P'' for each ''a'' ∈ Σ∪.]
Then the question whether ''L'' ∈ ''P'' for a given description of a language ''L'' ∈ ''C'' is undecidable.
Proof
Let ''M'' ⊆ Σ
*, such that ''M'' ∈ ''C'', but ''M'' ∉ ''P''.
[The existence of such an ''M'' is required by the above somewhat vague requirement of ''P'' being "nontrivial".]
For any ''L'' ∈ ''C'' with ''L'' ⊆ Σ
*, define φ(''L'') = (''M''#Σ
*) ∪ (Σ
*#''L'').
From a description of ''L'', a description of φ(''L'') can be effectively computed.
Then ''L'' = Σ
* if and only if φ(''L'') ∈ ''P'':
*If ''L'' = Σ
*, then φ(''L'') = Σ
*#Σ
* is a regular language, and hence in ''P''.
*Else, some ''w'' ∈ Σ
* \ ''L'' exists, and the quotient φ(''L'')/(#''w'') equals ''M''. Therefore, by repeated application of the quotient-closure property, φ(''L'') ∈ ''P'' would imply ''M'' = φ(''L'')/(#''w'') ∈ ''P'', contradicting the definition of ''M''.
Hence, if membership in ''P'' would be decidable for φ(''L'') from its description, so would be ''L''’s equality to Σ
* from its description, which contradicts the definition of ''C''.
Applications
Using Greibach's theorem, it can be shown that the following problems are undecidable:
* Given a
context-free grammar
In formal language theory, a context-free grammar (CFG) is a formal grammar whose production rules are of the form
:A\ \to\ \alpha
with A a ''single'' nonterminal symbol, and \alpha a string of terminals and/or nonterminals (\alpha can be empt ...
, does it describe a
regular language?
: Proof: The class of context-free languages, and the set of regular languages, satisfies the above properties of ''C'', and ''P'', respectively.
[Regular languages are context-free: Context-free grammar#Subclasses; context-free languages are closed with respect to union and (even general) concatenation: Context-free grammar#Closure properties; equality to Σ* is undecidable for context-free languages: Context-free grammar#Universality; regular languages are closed under (even general) quotients: Regular language#Closure properties.]
* Given a
context-free language, is it
inherently ambiguous?
: Proof: The class of context-free languages, and the set of context-free languages that aren't inherently ambiguous, satisfies the above properties of ''C'', and ''P'', respectively.
[Hopcroft, Ullman, 1979, p.206, Theorem 8.16]
* Given a
context-sensitive grammar
A context-sensitive grammar (CSG) is a formal grammar in which the left-hand sides and right-hand sides of any production rules may be surrounded by a context of terminal and nonterminal symbols. Context-sensitive grammars are more general than co ...
, does it describe a
context-free language?
See also
Context-free grammar#Being in a lower or higher level of the Chomsky hierarchy.
Notes
References
{{reflist
Formal languages