HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In algebraic geometry, a morphism of schemes generalizes a morphism of algebraic varieties just as a scheme generalizes an
algebraic variety Algebraic varieties are the central objects of study in algebraic geometry, a sub-field of mathematics. Classically, an algebraic variety is defined as the set of solutions of a system of polynomial equations over the real or complex numbers ...
. It is, by definition, a morphism in the category of schemes. A morphism of algebraic stacks generalizes a morphism of schemes.


Definition

By definition, a morphism of schemes is just a morphism of locally ringed spaces. A scheme, by definition, has open affine charts and thus a morphism of schemes can also be described in terms of such charts (compare the definition of morphism of varieties). Let ƒ:''X''→''Y'' be a morphism of schemes. If ''x'' is a point of ''X'', since ƒ is continuous, there are open affine subsets ''U'' = Spec ''A'' of ''X'' containing ''x'' and ''V'' = Spec ''B'' of ''Y'' such that ƒ(''U'') ⊆ ''V''. Then ƒ: ''U'' → ''V'' is a morphism of
affine scheme In commutative algebra, the prime spectrum (or simply the spectrum) of a ring ''R'' is the set of all prime ideals of ''R'', and is usually denoted by \operatorname; in algebraic geometry it is simultaneously a topological space equipped with t ...
s and thus is induced by some ring homomorphism ''B'' → ''A'' (cf. #Affine case.) In fact, one can use this description to "define" a morphism of schemes; one says that ƒ:''X''→''Y'' is a morphism of schemes if it is locally induced by ring homomorphisms between coordinate rings of affine charts. *Note: It would not be desirable to define a morphism of schemes as a morphism of ringed spaces. One trivial reason is that there is an example of a ringed-space morphism between affine schemes that is not induced by a ring homomorphism (for example, a morphism of ringed spaces: *:\operatorname k(x) \to \operatorname k = \ :that sends the unique point to ''s'' and that comes with k \to k(x), \, y \mapsto x.) More conceptually, the definition of a morphism of schemes needs to capture "Zariski-local nature" or localization of rings; this point of view (i.e., a local-ringed space) is essential for a generalization (topos). Let be a morphism of schemes with \phi: \mathcal_Y \to f_*\mathcal_X. Then, for each point ''x'' of ''X'', the homomorphisms on the stalks: :\phi: \mathcal_ \to \mathcal_ is a local ring homomorphism: i.e., \phi(\mathfrak_) \subseteq \mathfrak_x and so induces an injective homomorphism of
residue field In mathematics, the residue field is a basic construction in commutative algebra. If ''R'' is a commutative ring and ''m'' is a maximal ideal, then the residue field is the quotient ring ''k'' = ''R''/''m'', which is a field. Frequently, ''R'' is ...
s :\phi: k(f(x)) \hookrightarrow k(x). (In fact, φ maps th ''n''-th power of a maximal ideal to the ''n''-th power of the maximal ideal and thus induces the map between the (Zariski) cotangent spaces.) For each scheme ''X'', there is a natural morphism :\theta: X \to \operatorname \Gamma(X, \mathcal_X), which is an isomorphism if and only if ''X'' is affine; θ is obtained by gluing ''U'' → target which come from restrictions to open affine subsets ''U'' of ''X''. This fact can also be stated as follows: for any scheme ''X'' and a ring ''A'', there is a natural bijection: :\operatorname(X, \operatorname(A)) \cong \operatorname(A, \Gamma(X, \mathcal O_X)). (Proof: The map \phi \mapsto \operatorname(\phi) \circ \theta from the right to the left is the required bijection. In short, θ is an adjunction.) Moreover, this fact (adjoint relation) can be used to characterize an
affine scheme In commutative algebra, the prime spectrum (or simply the spectrum) of a ring ''R'' is the set of all prime ideals of ''R'', and is usually denoted by \operatorname; in algebraic geometry it is simultaneously a topological space equipped with t ...
: a scheme ''X'' is affine if and only if for each scheme ''S'', the natural map :\operatorname(S, X) \to \operatorname(\Gamma(X, \mathcal_X), \Gamma(S, \mathcal_S)) is bijective. (Proof: if the maps are bijective, then \operatorname(-, X) \simeq \operatorname(-, \operatorname \Gamma(X, \mathcal_X)) and ''X'' is isomorphic to \operatorname \Gamma(X, \mathcal_X) by Yoneda's lemma; the converse is clear.)


A morphism as a relative scheme

Fix a scheme ''S'', called a base scheme. Then a morphism p: X \to S is called a scheme over ''S'' or an ''S''-scheme; the idea of the terminology is that it is a scheme ''X'' together with a map to the base scheme ''S''. For example, a vector bundle ''E'' → ''S'' over a scheme ''S'' is an ''S''-scheme. An ''S''-morphism from ''p'':''X'' →''S'' to ''q'':''Y'' →''S'' is a morphism ƒ:''X'' →''Y'' of schemes such that ''p'' = ''q'' ∘ ƒ. Given an ''S''-scheme X \to S, viewing ''S'' as an ''S''-scheme over itself via the identity map, an ''S''-morphism S \to X is called a ''S''-section or just a section. All the ''S''-schemes form a category: an object in the category is an ''S''-scheme and a morphism in the category an ''S''-morphism. (Succinctly, this category is the
slice category In mathematics, specifically category theory, an overcategory (and undercategory) is a distinguished class of categories used in multiple contexts, such as with covering spaces (espace etale). They were introduced as a mechanism for keeping trac ...
of the category of schemes with the base object ''S''.)


Affine case

Let \varphi: B \to A be a ring homomorphism and let :\begin \varphi^a: \operatorname A \to \operatorname B, \\ \mathfrak \mapsto \varphi^(\mathfrak)\end be the induced map. Then *\varphi^a is continuous. *If \varphi is surjective, then \varphi^a is a homeomorphism onto its image. *For every ideal ''I'' of ''A'', \overline = V(\varphi^(I)). *\varphi^a has dense image if and only if the kernel of \varphi consists of nilpotent elements. (Proof: the preceding formula with ''I'' = 0.) In particular, when ''B'' is reduced, \varphi^a has dense image if and only if \varphi is injective. Let ''f'': Spec ''A'' → Spec ''B'' be a morphism of schemes between affine schemes with the pullback map \varphi: ''B'' → ''A''. That it is a morphism of locally ringed spaces translates to the following statement: if x = \mathfrak_x is a point of Spec ''A'', :\mathfrak_ = \varphi^(\mathfrak_x). (Proof: In general, \mathfrak_x consists of ''g'' in ''A'' that has zero image in the
residue field In mathematics, the residue field is a basic construction in commutative algebra. If ''R'' is a commutative ring and ''m'' is a maximal ideal, then the residue field is the quotient ring ''k'' = ''R''/''m'', which is a field. Frequently, ''R'' is ...
''k''(''x''); that is, it has the image in the maximal ideal \mathfrak_x. Thus, working in the local rings, g(f(x)) = 0 \Rightarrow \varphi(g) \in \varphi(\mathfrak_) \subseteq \mathfrak_x \Rightarrow g \in \varphi^(\mathfrak_x). If g(f(x)) \ne 0, then g is a unit element and so \varphi(g) is a unit element.) Hence, each ring homomorphism ''B'' → ''A'' defines a morphism of schemes Spec ''A'' → Spec ''B'' and, conversely, all morphisms between them arise this fashion.


Examples


Basic ones

*Let ''R'' be a field or \Z. For each ''R''-algebra ''A'', to specify an element of ''A'', say ''f'' in ''A'', is to give a ''R''-algebra homomorphism R \to A such that t \mapsto f. Thus, A = \operatorname_(R A). If ''X'' is a scheme over ''S'' = Spec ''R'', then taking A = \Gamma(X, \mathcal_X) and using the fact Spec is a right adjoint to the global section functor, we get \Gamma(X, \mathcal_X) = \operatorname_S(X, \mathbb^1_S) where \mathbb^1_S = \operatorname(R . Note the equality is that of rings. *Similarly, for any ''S''-scheme ''X'', there is the identification of the multiplicative groups: \Gamma(X, \mathcal_X^*) = \operatorname_S(X, \mathbb_m) where \mathbb_m = \operatorname(R , t^ is the multiplicative group scheme. *Many examples of morphisms come from families parameterized by some base space. For example, \text\left(\frac\right) \to \text(\Complex ,b,c = \mathbb^2_ is a projective morphism of projective varieties where the base space parameterizes quadrics in \mathbb^1.


Graph morphism

Given a morphism of schemes f: X \to Y over a scheme ''S'', the morphism X \to X \times_S Y induced by the identity 1_X : X \to X and ''f'' is called the graph morphism of ''f''. The graph morphism of the identity is called the diagonal morphism.


Types of morphisms


Finite Type

Morphisms of finite type are one of the basic tools for constructing families of varieties. A morphism f:X\to S is of finite type if there exists a cover \operatorname(A_i) \to S such that the fibers X \times_S \operatorname(A_i) can be covered by finitely many affine schemes \operatorname(B_) making the induced ring morphisms A_i \to B_ into finite-type morphisms. A typical example of a finite-type morphism is a family of schemes. For example, :\operatorname\left(\frac \right) \to \operatorname\left(\frac \right) is a morphism of finite type. A simple non-example of a morphism of finite-type is \operatorname(k _1,x_2,x_3,\ldots) \to \operatorname(k) where k is a field. Another is an infinite disjoint union :\coprod^\infty X \to X


Closed Immersion

A morphism of schemes i:Z \to X is a closed immersion if the following conditions hold: # i defines a homeomorphism of Z onto its image # i^\#: \mathcal_X \to i_*\mathcal_Z is surjective This condition is equivalent to the following: given an affine open \operatorname(R) = U \subseteq X there exists an ideal I \subseteq R such that i^(U) = \operatorname(R/I)


Examples

Of course, any (graded) quotient R/I defines a subscheme of \operatorname(R) (\operatorname(R)). Consider the quasi-affine scheme \mathbb^2 - \ and the subset of the x-axis contained in X. Then if we take the open subset \operatorname(k ,y,y^ the ideal sheaf is (x) while on the affine open \operatorname(k ,y,x^ there is no ideal since the subset does not intersect this chart.


Separated

Separated morphisms define families of schemes which are "Hausdorff". For example, given a separated morphism X \to S in \text/\Complex the associated analytic spaces X(\Complex)^ \to S(\Complex)^ are both Hausdorff. We say a morphism of scheme f:X \to S is separated if the diagonal morphism \Delta_:X \to X\times_SX is a closed immersion. In topology, an analogous condition for a space X to be Hausdorff is if the diagonal set :\Delta = \ is a closed subset of X\times X. Nevertheless, most schemes are not Hausdorff as topological spaces, as the Zariski topology is in general highly non-Hausdorff.


Examples

Most morphisms encountered in scheme theory will be separated. For example, consider the affine scheme :X = \operatorname\left( \frac \right) over \operatorname(\Complex). Since the product scheme is :X \times_\Complex X = \operatorname\left(\frac\otimes_\Complex \frac \right) the ideal defining the diagonal is generated by :x\otimes 1 - 1 \otimes x, y \otimes 1 - 1 \otimes y showing the diagonal scheme is affine and closed. This same computation can be used to show that projective schemes are separated as well.


Non-Examples

The only time care must be taken is when you are gluing together a family of schemes. For example, if we take the diagram of inclusions :\begin \operatorname(R ,x^ & &\\ &\searrow & \\ & & \operatorname(R \\ &\nearrow & \\ \operatorname(R ,x^ & & \end then we get the scheme-theoretic analogue of the classical line with two-origins.


Proper

A morphism f:X\to S is called proper if # it is separated # of finite-type # universally closed The last condition means that given a morphism S' \to S the base change morphism S'\times_SX is a closed immersion. Most known examples of proper morphisms are in fact projective; but, examples of proper varieties which are not projective can be found using toric geometry.


Projective

Projective morphisms define families of projective varieties over a fixed base scheme. Note that there are two definitions: Hartshornes which states that a morphism f:X\to S is called projective if there exists a closed immersion X \to \mathbb^n_S = \mathbb^n\times S and the EGA definition which states that a scheme X \in \text/S is projective if there is a quasi-coherent \mathcal_S-module of finite type such that there is a closed immersion X \to \mathbb_S(\mathcal). The second definition is useful because an exact sequence of \mathcal_S modules can be used to define projective morphisms.


Projective Morphism Over a Point

A projective morphism f:X \to \ defines a projective scheme. For example, :\text\left( \frac \right) \to \operatorname(\Complex ) defines a projective curve of genus (n-1)(n-1)/2 over \Complex .


Family of Projective Hypersurfaces

If we let S = \mathbb^1_t then the projective morphism :\underline_S\left( \frac \right) \to S defines a family of Calabi-Yau manifolds which degenerate.


Lefschetz Pencil

Another useful class of examples of projective morphisms are Lefschetz Pencils: they are projective morphisms \pi:X \to \mathbb^1_k = \operatorname(k ,t over some field k. For example, given smooth hypersurfaces X_1, X_2 \subseteq \mathbb^n_k defined by the homogeneous polynomials f_1,f_2 there is a projective morphism :\underline_\left( \frac \right)\to \mathbb^1 giving the pencil.


EGA Projective

A nice classical example of a projective scheme is by constructing projective morphisms which factor through rational scrolls. For example, take S = \mathbb^1 and the vector bundle \mathcal = \mathcal_S \oplus \mathcal_S \oplus \mathcal_S(3). This can be used to construct a \mathbb^2-bundle \mathbb_S(\mathcal) over S. If we want to construct a projective morphism using this sheaf we can take an exact sequence, such as :\mathcal_S(-d)\oplus\mathcal_S(-e) \to \mathcal \to \mathcal_X \to 0 which defines the structure sheaf of the projective scheme X in \mathbb_S(\mathcal).


Flat


Intuition

Flat morphisms have an algebraic definition but have a very concrete geometric interpretation: flat families correspond to families of varieties which vary "continuously". For example, :\operatorname\left(\frac \right) \to \operatorname(\Complex is a family of smooth affine quadric curves which degenerate to the normal crossing divisor :\operatorname\left(\frac \right) at the origin.


Properties

One important property that a flat morphism must satisfy is that the dimensions of the fibers should be the same. A simple non-example of a flat morphism then is a blowup since the fibers are either points or copies of some \mathbb^n.


Definition

Let f:X \to S be a morphism of schemes. We say that f is flat at a point x \in X if the induced morphism \mathcal_ \to \mathcal_x yields an exact functor -\otimes_ \mathcal_x. Then, f is flat if it is flat at every point of X. It is also faithfully flat if it is a surjective morphism.


Non-Example

Using our geometric intuition it obvious that :f:\operatorname(\Complex ,y(xy)) \to \operatorname(\Complex is not flat since the fiber over 0 is \mathbb^1 with the rest of the fibers are just a point. But, we can also check this using the definition with local algebra: Consider the ideal \mathfrak = (x) \in \operatorname(\Complex ,y(xy)). Since f(\mathfrak) = (x) \in \operatorname(\Complex we get a local algebra morphism :f_: \left( \Complex \right)_ \to \left(\Complex ,y(xy) \right)_ If we tensor :0 \to \Complex \overset \Complex with (\Complex ,y(xy))_, the map :(\Complex ,y(xy)))_ \xrightarrow (\Complex ,y(xy))_ has a non-zero kernel due the vanishing of xy. This shows that the morphism is not flat.


Unramified

A morphism f:X \to Y of affine schemes is
unramified In geometry, ramification is 'branching out', in the way that the square root function, for complex numbers, can be seen to have two ''branches'' differing in sign. The term is also used from the opposite perspective (branches coming together) ...
if \Omega_ = 0. We can use this for the general case of a morphism of schemes f:X\to Y. We say that f is unramified at x\in X if there is an affine open neighborhood x \in U and an affine open V\subseteq Y such that f(U)\subseteq V and \Omega_ = 0. Then, the morphism is unramified if it is unramified at every point in X.


Geometric Example

One example of a morphism which is flat and generically unramified, except for at a point, is : \operatorname\left( \frac \right) \to \operatorname(\Complex We can compute the relative differentials using the sequence :\frac\otimes_\Complex t \to \left(\fracdt \oplus \fracdx\right) / (nx^dx - dt) \to \Omega_ \to 0 showing :\Omega_ \cong \left(\fracdx\right)/(x^dx) \neq 0 if we take the fiber t = 0, then the morphism is ramified since :\Omega_ = \left(\fracdx\right)/(x^dx) otherwise we have :\Omega_ = \left(\fracdx\right)/(x^dx) \cong \fracdx \cong 0 showing that it is unramified everywhere else.


Etale

A morphism of schemes f:X \to Y is called étale if it is flat and unramfied. These are the algebro-geometric analogue of covering spaces. The two main examples to think of are covering spaces and finite separable field extensions. Examples in the first case can be constructed by looking at branched coverings and restricting to the unramified locus.


Morphisms as points

By definition, if ''X'', ''S'' are schemes (over some base scheme or ring ''B''), then a morphism from ''S'' to ''X'' (over ''B'') is an ''S''-point of ''X'' and one writes: :X(S) = \ for the set of all ''S''-points of ''X''. This notion generalizes the notion of solutions to a system of polynomial equations in classical algebraic geometry. Indeed, let ''X'' = Spec(''A'') with A =B _1, \dots, t_n(f_1, \dots, f_m). For a ''B''-algebra ''R'', to give an ''R''-point of ''X'' is to give an algebra homomorphism ''A'' →''R'', which in turn amounts to giving a homomorphism :B _1, \dots, t_n\to R, \, t_i \mapsto r_i that kills ''f''''i'''s. Thus, there is a natural identification: :X(\operatorname R) = \. Example: If ''X'' is an ''S''-scheme with structure map π: ''X'' → ''S'', then an ''S''-point of ''X'' (over ''S'') is the same thing as a section of π. In category theory, Yoneda's lemma says that, given a category ''C'', the contravariant functor :C \to \mathcal(C) = \operatorname(C^, \mathbf), \, X \mapsto \operatorname(-, X) is fully faithful (where \mathcal(C) means the category of
presheaves In mathematics, a sheaf is a tool for systematically tracking data (such as sets, abelian groups, rings) attached to the open sets of a topological space and defined locally with regard to them. For example, for each open set, the data could ...
on ''C''). Applying the lemma to ''C'' = the category of schemes over ''B'', this says that a scheme over ''B'' is determined by its various points. It turns out that in fact it is enough to consider ''S''-points with only affine schemes ''S'', precisely because schemes and morphisms between them are obtained by gluing affine schemes and morphisms between them. Because of this, one usually writes ''X''(''R'') = ''X''(Spec ''R'') and view ''X'' as a functor from the category of commutative ''B''-algebras to Sets. Example: Given ''S''-schemes ''X'', ''Y'' with structure maps ''p'', ''q'', :(X \times_S Y)(R) = X(R) \times_ Y(R) = \. Example: With ''B'' still denoting a ring or scheme, for each ''B''-scheme ''X'', there is a natural bijection :\mathbf^n_B(X) = ; in fact, the sections ''s''''i'' of ''L'' define a morphism X \to \mathbf^n_B, \, x \mapsto (s_0(x) : \dots : s_n(x)). (See also Proj construction#Global Proj.) Remark: The above point of view (which goes under the name functor of points and is due to Grothendieck) has had a significant impact on the foundations of algebraic geometry. For example, working with a category-valued (pseudo-)functor instead of a set-valued functor leads to the notion of a
stack Stack may refer to: Places * Stack Island, an island game reserve in Bass Strait, south-eastern Australia, in Tasmania’s Hunter Island Group * Blue Stack Mountains, in Co. Donegal, Ireland People * Stack (surname) (including a list of people ...
, which allows one to keep track of morphisms between points.


Rational map

A rational map of schemes is defined in the same way for varieties. Thus, a rational map from a reduced scheme ''X'' to a separated scheme ''Y'' is an equivalence class of a pair (U, f_U) consisting of an open dense subset ''U'' of ''X'' and a morphism f_U : U \to Y. If ''X'' is irreducible, a
rational function In mathematics, a rational function is any function that can be defined by a rational fraction, which is an algebraic fraction such that both the numerator and the denominator are polynomials. The coefficients of the polynomials need not be ...
on ''X'' is, by definition, a rational map from ''X'' to the affine line \mathbb^1 or the projective line \mathbb^1. A rational map is dominant if and only if it sends the generic point to the generic point. A ring homomorphism between function fields need not induce a dominant rational map (even just a rational map). For example, Spec ''k'' 'x''and Spec ''k''(''x'') and have the same function field (namely, ''k''(''x'')) but there is no rational map from the former to the latter. However, it is true that any inclusion of function fields of algebraic varieties induces a dominant rational map (see morphism of algebraic varieties#Properties.)


See also

*
Regular embedding In algebraic geometry, a closed immersion i: X \hookrightarrow Y of schemes is a regular embedding of codimension ''r'' if each point ''x'' in ''X'' has an open affine neighborhood ''U'' in ''Y'' such that the ideal of X \cap U is generated by a ...
* Constructible set (topology) * Universal homeomorphism


Notes


References

* *{{Hartshorne AG *Milne, Review of Algebraic Geometry a
Algebraic Groups: The theory of group schemes of finite type over a field.
*Vakil
Foundations of Algebraic Geometry
Algebraic geometry