Fischer–Trendelenburg Debate
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg (30 November 1802 – 24 January 1872) was a
German German(s) may refer to: * Germany (of or related to) **Germania (historical use) * Germans, citizens of Germany, people of German ancestry, or native speakers of the German language ** For citizens of Germany, see also German nationality law **Ger ...
philosopher A philosopher is a person who practices or investigates philosophy. The term ''philosopher'' comes from the grc, φιλόσοφος, , translit=philosophos, meaning 'lover of wisdom'. The coining of the term has been attributed to the Greek th ...
and philologist.


Life

He was born at
Eutin Eutin () is the district capital of Ostholstein, Eastern Holstein county located in the northern German state of Schleswig-Holstein. As of 2020, the town had some 17,000 inhabitants. History The name Eutin (originally Utin) is of Slavic origin. I ...
, near Lübeck. He was placed in a gymnasium in
Eutin Eutin () is the district capital of Ostholstein, Eastern Holstein county located in the northern German state of Schleswig-Holstein. As of 2020, the town had some 17,000 inhabitants. History The name Eutin (originally Utin) is of Slavic origin. I ...
, which was under the direction of , a philologist influenced by Immanuel Kant. He was educated at the universities of Kiel, Leipzig, Berlin. He became more and more attracted to the study of Plato and Aristotle, and his 1826 doctoral dissertation, ''Platonis de ideis et numeris doctrina ex Aristotele illustrata'' (''On Plato's Doctrine of Ideas and Numbers as Illustrated by Aristotle''), was an attempt to reach through Aristotle's criticisms a more accurate knowledge of the Platonic philosophy. He declined the offer of a classical chair at Kiel, and accepted a post as tutor to the son of an intimate friend of
Karl vom Stein zum Altenstein Karl Sigmund Franz Freiherr vom Stein zum Altenstein (1 October 1770, in Schalkhausen near Ansbach – 14 May 1840, in Berlin) was a Prussian politician and the first Prussian education minister. His most lasting impact was the reform of the Pru ...
, the Prussian minister of education. He held this position for seven years (1826–1833), occupying his leisure time with the preparation of a critical edition of Aristotle's '' De anima'' (1833; 2nd ed. by Christian Belger, 1877). In 1833 Altenstein appointed Trendelenburg extraordinary professor in Berlin, and four years later he was advanced to an ordinary professorship.


Teaching

For nearly 40 years, he proved himself markedly successful as a teacher, during the greater part of which time he had to examine in
philosophy Philosophy (from , ) is the systematized study of general and fundamental questions, such as those about existence, reason, knowledge, values, mind, and language. Such questions are often posed as problems to be studied or resolved. Some ...
and pedagogics all candidates for the scholastic profession in Prussia. His teaching method was highly regarded by
Søren Kierkegaard Søren Aabye Kierkegaard ( , , ; 5 May 1813 – 11 November 1855) was a Danish theologian, philosopher, poet, social critic, and religious author who is widely considered to be the first existentialist philosopher. He wrote critical texts on ...
who called him "one of the most sober philosophical philologists I know." He was elected a Foreign Honorary Member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in 1861. Two of his prominent students were Franz Brentano and
Wilhelm Dilthey Wilhelm Dilthey (; ; 19 November 1833 – 1 October 1911) was a German historian, psychologist, sociologist, and hermeneutic philosopher, who held G. W. F. Hegel's Chair in Philosophy at the University of Berlin. As a polymathic philosopher, w ...
.


Philosophical work


Defense of teleology

Trendelenburg's philosophizing is conditioned throughout by his loving study of Plato and Aristotle, whom he regards not as opponents but as building jointly on the broad basis of idealism. His own standpoint may be called a modern version of Aristotelianism. While denying the possibility of an absolute method and an absolute philosophy, as contended for by
Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (; ; 27 August 1770 – 14 November 1831) was a German philosopher. He is one of the most important figures in German idealism and one of the founding figures of modern Western philosophy. His influence extends a ...
and others, Trendelenburg was emphatically an idealist in the ancient or Platonic sense; his whole work was devoted to the demonstration of the ideal in the real. But he maintained that the procedure of philosophy must be analytic, rising from the particular facts to the universal in which we find them explained. We divine the system of the whole from the part we know, but the process of reconstruction must remain approximative. Our position forbids the possibility of a final system. Instead, therefore, of constantly beginning afresh in speculation, it should be our duty to attach ourselves to what may be considered the permanent results of historic developments. The classical expression of these results Trendelenburg finds mainly in the Platonico-Aristotelian system. The philosophical question is stated thus: How are thought and being united in knowledge? How does thought get at being? And how does being enter into thought? Proceeding on the principle that like can only be known by like, Trendelenburg next reaches a doctrine peculiar to himself (though based upon Aristotle) that plays a central part in his speculations. Motion is the fundamental fact common to being and thought; the ''actual motion'' of the external world has its counterpart in the ''constructive motion'' involved in every instance of perception or thought. From motion he proceeds to deduce time, space and the categories of mechanics and natural science. These, being thus derived, are at once subjective and objective in their scope. It is true that matter can never be completely resolved into motion, but the irreducible remainder may be treated, like Aristotle, as an abstraction we asymptotically approach but never reach. The facts of existence, however, are not adequately explained by the mechanical categories. The ultimate interpretation of the universe can only be found in the higher category of End or final cause. Here Trendelenburg finds the dividing line, between philosophical systems. On the one side stand those that acknowledge none but efficient causes, which make force prior to thought, and explain the universe, as it were, ''a tergo'' ("from the back"). This may be called, typically, Democritism. On the other side stands the organic or teleological view of the world, which interprets the parts through the idea of the whole, and sees in the efficient causes only the vehicle of ideal ends. This may be called in a wide sense Platonism. Systems like Spinozism, which seem to form a third class, neither sacrificing
force In physics, a force is an influence that can change the motion of an object. A force can cause an object with mass to change its velocity (e.g. moving from a state of rest), i.e., to accelerate. Force can also be described intuitively as a p ...
to
thought In their most common sense, the terms thought and thinking refer to conscious cognitive processes that can happen independently of sensory stimulation. Their most paradigmatic forms are judging, reasoning, concept formation, problem solving, a ...
nor thought to force, yet by their denial of final causes inevitably fall back into the Democritic or essentially materialistic standpoint, leaving us with the great antagonism of the mechanical and the organic systems of philosophy. The latter view, which receives its first support in the facts of life, or organic nature as such, finds its culmination and ultimate verification in the ethical world, which essentially consists in the realization of ends. Trendelenburg's ''Naturrecht'' he right of naturemay, therefore, be taken as in a manner the completion of his system, his working out of the ideal as present in the real. The ethical end is taken to be the idea of humanity, not in the abstract as formulated by Immanuel Kant, but in the context of the state and of history. Law is treated throughout as the vehicle of ethical requirements. In Trendelenburg's treatment of the state, as the ethical organism in which the individual (the potential man) may be said first to emerge into actuality, we may trace his nurture on the best ideas of Hellenic antiquity.


Fischer–Trendelenburg debate

In 1865 he became involved in an acrimonious controversy on the interpretation of Kant's doctrine of space with Kuno Fischer, whom he attacked in ''Kuno Fischer und sein Kant'' (1869), which drew forth the reply ''Anti-Trendelenburg'' (1870). The controversy became known in the history of philosophy as the Fischer–Trendelenburg debate. Trendelenburg's position on the debate (the position that "Kant may establish that space and time are '' a priori'' and intuitive conditions for experience in the " Transcendental Aesthetic," but this in no way entails that space and time have nothing to do with the objects outside of possible experience") has been variously dubbed as "Neglected Alternative," "Trendelenburg's gap" 'die trendelenburgische Lücke'' "Pistorius's gap 'die pistorische Lücke'' (named after
Hermann Andreas Pistorius Hermann Andreas Pistorius (8 April 1730 – 10 November 1798) was a German Protestant-Lutheran theologian and clergyman, philosopher, reviewer, translator and writer. During his lifetime he was regarded as "the most learned man on Rügen". Early l ...
), or "third possibility" 'die dritte Möglichkeit''Andrew F. Specht
"Kant and the Neglected Alternative"
December 2014, p. 4.


Family

His son,
Friedrich Trendelenburg Friedrich Trendelenburg (; 24 May 184415 December 1924) was a German surgeon. He was son of the philosophy, philosopher Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg, father of the pharmacology, pharmacologist Paul Trendelenburg and grandfather of the pharmaco ...
, was a prominent surgeon; several medical techniques and matters are named for him.


Works (selection)

Trendelenburg was also the author of the following: *''Elementa Logices Aristotelicae'' (1836; 9th ed., 1892; Eng. trans. 1881), a selection of passages from the '' Organon'' with Latin translation and notes, containing the substance of Aristotle's logical doctrine, supplemented by ''Erlauterungen zu den Elementen der Aristotelischen Logik'' (1842; 3rd ed., 1876). *''Logische Untersuchungen (Logical Investigations)'', 2 vols. (1840; 3rd ed. 1870), and ''Die logische Frage in Hegels System'' (1843), important factors in the reaction against Hegel. *''Historische Beitrage zur Philosophie'' (1846–1867), in three volumes, the first of which (''Geschichte der Kategorienlehre'') contains a history of the doctrine of the Categories. *''Geschichte der Kategorienlehre'' I: Aristotle Kategorienlehre; II: Die Kategorienlehre in der Geschichte der Philosophie (1846, reprint: Hildesheim, Olms, 1979). *''Des Naturrecht aufdem Grunde der Ethik'' (1860). *''Lücken im Völkerrecht'' (1870), a treatise on the defects of international law, occasioned by the war of 1870. *'' Kleine Schriften'' (1871), papers dealing with non-philosophical, chiefly national and educational subjects.
''Zur Geschichte des Wortes Person''
Kant-Studien, Bd. 13, Berlin 1908 *''Ethische Untersuchungen: Genetisch-kritische Fragmentedition''. Edited by Christian Biehl. ''Exempla critica'' 5. De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston 2022


Translations


''A Contribution to the History of the Word Person: A Posthumous Treatise''
Open Court Pub. Co., 1910.
''Outlines of Logic: An English Translation of Trendelenburg's Elementa''
1898.


Notes

Attribution: *


References

* Frederick Beiser
''Late German Idealism: Trendelenburg and Lotze''
Oxford University Press, 2013 urrently the most complete discussion of Trendelenburg's philosophy.* Graham Bird
''A Companion to Kant''
John Wiley and Sons, 2009 p. 486ff has an article about Trendelenburg's dispute with Fisher over Kant's definition of space * Hermann Bonitz, ''Zur Erinnering an Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg'' (Berlin, 1872) * * Ernst Bratuschek, ''Adolf Trendelenburg'' (Berlin, 1873)
he first complete intellectual biography of Trendelenburg. He or HE may refer to: Language * He (pronoun), an English pronoun * He (kana), the romanization of the Japanese kana へ * He (letter), the fifth letter of many Semitic alphabets * He (Cyrillic), a letter of the Cyrillic script called ''He'' in ...
*
George Sylvester Morris George Sylvester Morris (November 15, 1840 – March 23, 1889) was a 19th-century American educator and philosophical writer. Biography Morris was born in Norwich, Vermont. He was the son of a well known abolitionist and temperance man. In 1861, ...
, ''Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg'' (1874). * Paul Kleinert, ''Grabrede'' (Berlin, 1872) *
Carl von Prantl Karl von Prantl (aka Carl von Prantl) (28 January 1820 – 14 September 1888) (after 1872: Karl, Ritter von Prantl) was a Germans, German Philosophy, philosopher and Philology, philologist. Biography He was born at Landsberg am Lech, Landsber ...
, ''Gedächtnisrede'' (Munich, 1873)


External links

* {{DEFAULTSORT:Trendelenburg, Friedrich Adolf 1802 births 1872 deaths 19th-century German male writers 19th-century German non-fiction writers 19th-century German people 19th-century German philosophers 19th-century essayists 19th-century philologists 19th-century philosophers Aristotelian philosophers Continental philosophers Epistemologists Fellows of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences German essayists German ethicists German logicians German male non-fiction writers German philologists Hegel scholars Humboldt University of Berlin alumni Humboldt University of Berlin faculty Idealists Kant scholars Lecturers Leipzig University alumni Metaphysicians Moral philosophers Ontologists People from Eutin People from Oldenburg (state) Philosophers of culture Philosophers of education Philosophers of ethics and morality Philosophers of history Philosophers of language Philosophers of law Philosophers of logic Philosophers of mind Philosophers of social science Philosophers of war Philosophy academics Philosophy teachers Philosophy writers Recipients of the Pour le Mérite (civil class) Spinoza scholars University of Kiel alumni