HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
first-order logic First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
, a first-order theory is given by a
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
of axioms in some language. This entry lists some of the more common examples used in
model theory In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between theory (mathematical logic), formal theories (a collection of Sentence (mathematical logic), sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a Structure (mat ...
and some of their properties.


Preliminaries

For every natural mathematical structure there is a
signature A signature (; from , "to sign") is a depiction of someone's name, nickname, or even a simple "X" or other mark that a person writes on documents as a proof of identity and intent. Signatures are often, but not always, Handwriting, handwritt ...
σ listing the constants, functions, and relations of the theory together with their arities, so that the object is naturally a σ-structure. Given a signature σ there is a unique first-order language ''L''σ that can be used to capture the first-order expressible facts about the σ-structure. There are two common ways to specify theories: #List or describe a set of
sentences The ''Sentences'' (. ) is a compendium of Christian theology written by Peter Lombard around 1150. It was the most important religious textbook of the Middle Ages. Background The sentence genre emerged from works like Prosper of Aquitaine's ...
in the language ''L''σ, called the axioms of the theory. #Give a set of σ-structures, and define a theory to be the set of sentences in ''L''σ holding in all these models. For example, the "theory of finite fields" consists of all sentences in the language of fields that are true in all finite fields. An Lσ theory may: *be consistent: no proof of contradiction exists; * be satisfiable: there exists a σ-structure for which the sentences of the theory are all true (by the
completeness theorem Complete may refer to: Logic * Completeness (logic) * Completeness of a theory, the property of a theory that every formula in the theory's language or its negation is provable Mathematics * The completeness of the real numbers, which implies ...
, satisfiability is equivalent to consistency); *be complete: for any statement, either it or its negation is provable; *have
quantifier elimination Quantifier elimination is a concept of simplification used in mathematical logic, model theory, and theoretical computer science. Informally, a quantified statement "\exists x such that ..." can be viewed as a question "When is there an x such ...
; * eliminate imaginaries; * be finitely axiomatizable; *be decidable: There is an algorithm to decide which statements are provable; *be recursively axiomatizable; *be model complete or sub-model complete; *be κ-categorical: All models of
cardinality The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
κ are isomorphic; *be
stable A stable is a building in which working animals are kept, especially horses or oxen. The building is usually divided into stalls, and may include storage for equipment and feed. Styles There are many different types of stables in use tod ...
or unstable; *be ω-stable (same as totally transcendental for
countable In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
theories); *be superstable *have an atomic model; *have a
prime model In mathematics, and in particular model theory, a prime model is a model that is as simple as possible. Specifically, a model P is prime if it admits an elementary embedding into any model M to which it is elementarily equivalent (that is, into a ...
; *have a
saturated model In mathematical logic, and particularly in its subfield model theory, a saturated model ''M'' is one that realizes as many complete types as may be "reasonably expected" given its size. For example, an ultrapower model of the hyperreals is \al ...
.


Pure identity theories

The signature of the pure identity theory is empty, with no functions, constants, or relations. Pure identity theory has no (non-logical) axioms. It is decidable. One of the few interesting properties that can be stated in the language of pure identity theory is that of being infinite. This is given by an infinite set of axioms stating there are at least 2 elements, there are at least 3 elements, and so on: *∃''x''1 ∃''x''2 ¬''x''1 = ''x''2,    ∃''x''1 ∃''x''2 ∃''x''3 ¬''x''1 = ''x''2 ∧ ¬''x''1 = ''x''3 ∧ ¬''x''2 = ''x''3,... These axioms define the theory of an infinite set. The opposite property of being finite cannot be stated in
first-order logic First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
for any theory that has arbitrarily large finite models: in fact any such theory has infinite models by the
compactness theorem In mathematical logic, the compactness theorem states that a set of first-order sentences has a model if and only if every finite subset of it has a model. This theorem is an important tool in model theory, as it provides a useful (but generall ...
. In general if a property can be stated by a finite number of sentences of first-order logic then the opposite property can also be stated in first-order logic, but if a property needs an infinite number of sentences then its opposite property cannot be stated in first-order logic. Any statement of pure identity theory is equivalent to either σ(''N'') or to ¬σ(''N'') for some finite
subset In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they a ...
''N'' of the
non-negative integer In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positiv ...
s, where σ(''N'') is the statement that the number of elements is in ''N''. It is even possible to describe all possible theories in this language as follows. Any theory is either the theory of all sets of cardinality in ''N'' for some ''finite'' subset ''N'' of the non-negative integers, or the theory of all sets whose cardinality is not in ''N'', for some ''finite or infinite'' subset ''N'' of the non-negative integers. (There are no theories whose models are exactly sets of cardinality ''N'' if ''N'' is an infinite subset of the integers.) The complete theories are the theories of sets of cardinality ''n'' for some finite ''n'', and the theory of infinite sets. One special case of this is the inconsistent theory defined by the axiom ∃''x'' ¬''x'' = ''x''. It is a perfectly good theory with many good properties: it is complete, decidable, finitely axiomatizable, and so on. The only problem is that it has no models at all. By Gödel's completeness theorem, it is the only theory (for any given language) with no models. It is not the same as the theory of the
empty set In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
(in versions of first-order logic that allow a model to be empty): the theory of the empty set has exactly one model, which has no elements.


Unary relations

A set of unary relations ''P''''i'' for ''i'' in some set ''I'' is called independent if for every two disjoint finite subsets ''A'' and ''B'' of ''I'' there is some element ''x'' such that ''P''''i''(''x'') is true for ''i'' in ''A'' and false for ''i'' in ''B''. Independence can be expressed by a set of first-order statements. The theory of a countable number of independent unary relations is complete, but has no atomic models. It is also an example of a theory that is superstable but not totally transcendental.


Equivalence relations

The signature of
equivalence relation In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation. A simpler example is equ ...
s has one binary infix relation symbol ~, no constants, and no functions. Equivalence relations satisfy the axioms: * Reflexive ∀''x'' ''x''~''x''; *
Symmetric Symmetry () in everyday life refers to a sense of harmonious and beautiful proportion and balance. In mathematics, the term has a more precise definition and is usually used to refer to an object that is invariant under some transformations ...
∀''x'' ∀''y'' ''x''~''y'' → ''y''~''x''; * Transitive: ∀''x'' ∀''y'' ∀''z'' (''x''~''y'' ∧ ''y''~''z'') → ''x''~''z''. Some first-order properties of equivalence relations are: *~ has an infinite number of
equivalence classes In mathematics, when the elements of some set S have a notion of equivalence (formalized as an equivalence relation), then one may naturally split the set S into equivalence classes. These equivalence classes are constructed so that elements a ...
; *~ has exactly ''n'' equivalence classes (for any fixed positive integer ''n''); *All equivalence classes are infinite; *All equivalence classes have size exactly ''n'' (for any fixed positive integer ''n''). The theory of an equivalence relation with exactly 2 infinite
equivalence class In mathematics, when the elements of some set S have a notion of equivalence (formalized as an equivalence relation), then one may naturally split the set S into equivalence classes. These equivalence classes are constructed so that elements ...
es is an easy example of a theory which is ω-categorical but not categorical for any larger
cardinal Cardinal or The Cardinal most commonly refers to * Cardinalidae, a family of North and South American birds **''Cardinalis'', genus of three species in the family Cardinalidae ***Northern cardinal, ''Cardinalis cardinalis'', the common cardinal of ...
. The equivalence relation ~ should not be confused with the identity symbol '=': if ''x''=''y'' then ''x''~''y'', but the converse is not necessarily true. Theories of equivalence relations are not all that difficult or interesting, but often give easy examples or counterexamples for various statements. The following constructions are sometimes used to produce examples of theories with certain spectra; in fact by applying them to a small number of explicit theories ''T'' one gets examples of complete countable theories with all possible uncountable spectra. If ''T'' is a theory in some language, we define a new theory 2''T'' by adding a new binary relation to the language, and adding axioms stating that it is an equivalence relation, such that there are an infinite number of equivalence classes all of which are
model A model is an informative representation of an object, person, or system. The term originally denoted the plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin , . Models can be divided in ...
s of ''T''. It is possible to iterate this construction transfinitely: given an ordinal α, define a new theory by adding an equivalence relation ''Eβ'' for each β<α, together with axioms stating that whenever β<γ then each ''Eγ'' equivalence class is the union of infinitely many ''Eβ'' equivalence classes, and each ''E0'' equivalence class is a model of ''T''. Informally, one can visualize models of this theory as infinitely branching trees of height α with models of ''T'' attached to all leaves.


Orders

The signature of
orders Order, ORDER or Orders may refer to: * A socio-political or established or existing order, e.g. World order, Ancien Regime, Pax Britannica * Categorization, the process in which ideas and objects are recognized, differentiated, and understood * H ...
has no constants or functions, and one binary relation symbols ≤. (It is of course possible to use ≥, < or > instead as the basic relation, with the obvious minor changes to the axioms.) We define ''x'' ≥ ''y'', ''x'' < ''y'', ''x'' > ''y'' as abbreviations for ''y'' ≤ ''x'', ''x'' ≤ ''y'' ∧¬''y'' ≤ ''x'', ''y'' < ''x'', Some first-order properties of orders: *Transitive: ∀''x'' ∀''y'' ∀''z'' (''x'' ≤ ''y)'' ∧ (''y'' ≤ ''z)'' → ''x'' ≤ ''z'' *Reflexive: ∀''x'' ''x'' ≤ ''x'' * Antisymmetric: ∀''x'' ∀''y'' (''x'' ≤ ''y)'' ∧ (''y'' ≤ ''x)'' → ''x'' = ''y'' *
Partial Partial may refer to: Mathematics *Partial derivative, derivative with respect to one of several variables of a function, with the other variables held constant ** ∂, a symbol that can denote a partial derivative, sometimes pronounced "partial d ...
: Transitive ∧ Reflexive ∧ Antisymmetric; *
Linear In mathematics, the term ''linear'' is used in two distinct senses for two different properties: * linearity of a '' function'' (or '' mapping''); * linearity of a '' polynomial''. An example of a linear function is the function defined by f(x) ...
(or total): Partial ∧ ∀''x'' ∀''y'' (''x'' ≤ ''y)'' ∨ (''y'' ≤ ''x)'' *
Dense Density (volumetric mass density or specific mass) is the ratio of a substance's mass to its volume. The symbol most often used for density is ''ρ'' (the lower case Greek letter rho), although the Latin letter ''D'' (or ''d'') can also be use ...
("Between any 2 distinct elements there is another element"): ∀''x'' ∀''z'' (''x'' < ''z)'' → ∃''y'' (''x'' < ''y)'' ∧ (''y'' < ''z)'' *There is a smallest element: ∃''x'' ∀''y'' (''x'' ≤ ''y)'' *There is a largest element: ∃''x'' ∀''y'' (''y'' ≤ ''x)'' *Every element has an immediate successor: ∀''x'' ∃''y'' ∀''z'' (''x'' < ''z)'' ↔ (''y'' ≤ ''z)'' The theory DLO of ''dense linear orders without endpoints'' (i.e. no smallest or largest element) is complete, ω-categorical, but not categorical for any uncountable cardinal. There are three other very similar theories: the theory of dense linear orders with a: * Smallest but no largest element; * Largest but no smallest element; * Largest and smallest element. Being well ordered ("any non-empty subset has a minimal element") is not a first-order property; the usual definition involves quantifying over all ''subsets''.


Lattices

Lattices can be considered either as special sorts of partially ordered sets, with a signature consisting of one binary relation symbol ≤, or as
algebraic structure In mathematics, an algebraic structure or algebraic system consists of a nonempty set ''A'' (called the underlying set, carrier set or domain), a collection of operations on ''A'' (typically binary operations such as addition and multiplicatio ...
s with a signature consisting of two binary operations ∧ and ∨. The two approaches can be related by defining ''a'' ≤ ''b'' to mean ''a''∧''b'' = ''a''. For two binary operations the axioms for a lattice are: For one relation ≤ the axioms are: *Axioms stating ≤ is a partial order, as above. *\forall a \forall b \exist c\; c \le a \wedge c \le b \wedge \forall d\;d \le a \wedge d \le b \rightarrow d \le c (existence of c = a∧b) *\forall a \forall b \exist c\; a \le c \wedge b \le c \wedge \forall d\;a \le d \wedge b \le d \rightarrow c \le d (existence of c = a∨b) First-order properties include: * \forall x \forall y\forall z\;x \vee (y \wedge z) = (x \vee y) \wedge (x \vee z) (
distributive lattice In mathematics, a distributive lattice is a lattice (order), lattice in which the operations of join and meet distributivity, distribute over each other. The prototypical examples of such structures are collections of sets for which the lattice o ...
s) * \forall x \forall y\forall z\;x \vee (y \wedge (x \vee z)) = (x \vee y) \wedge (x \vee z) ( modular lattices)
Heyting algebra In mathematics, a Heyting algebra (also known as pseudo-Boolean algebra) is a bounded lattice (with join and meet operations written ∨ and ∧ and with least element 0 and greatest element 1) equipped with a binary operation ''a'' → ''b'' call ...
s can be defined as lattices with certain extra first-order properties. Completeness is not a first-order property of lattices.


Graphs

The signature of graphs has no constants or functions, and one binary relation symbol ''R'', where ''R''(''x'',''y'') is read as "there is an edge from ''x'' to ''y''". The axioms for the theory of graphs are *Symmetric: ∀''x'' ∀''y'' ''R''(''x'',''y'')→ ''R''(''y'',''x'') * Anti-reflexive: ∀''x'' ¬''R''(''x'',''x'') ("no loops") The ''theory of random graphs'' has the following extra axioms for each positive integer ''n'': * For any two disjoint finite sets of size ''n'', there is a point joined to all points of the first set and to no points of the second set. (For each fixed ''n'', it is easy to write this statement in the language of graphs.) The theory of random graphs is ω categorical, complete, and decidable, and its countable model is called the
Rado graph In the mathematics, mathematical field of graph theory, the Rado graph, Erdős–Rényi graph, or random graph is a Countable set, countably infinite graph that can be constructed (with probability one) by choosing independently at random for eac ...
. A statement in the language of graphs is true in this theory if and only if the probability that an ''n''-vertex
random graph In mathematics, random graph is the general term to refer to probability distributions over graphs. Random graphs may be described simply by a probability distribution, or by a random process which generates them. The theory of random graphs l ...
models the statement tends to 1 in the limit as ''n'' goes to infinity.


Boolean algebras

There are several different signatures and conventions used for Boolean algebras: #The signature has two constants, 0 and 1, and two binary functions ∧ and ∨ ("and" and "or"), and one unary function ¬ ("not"). This can be confusing as the functions use the same symbols as the
propositional function In propositional calculus, a propositional function or a predicate is a sentence expressed in a way that would assume the value of true or false, except that within the sentence there is a variable (''x'') that is not defined or specified (thus be ...
s of first-order logic. #In
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, a common convention is that the language has two constants, 0 and 1, and two binary functions · and +, and one unary function −. The three functions have the same interpretation as the functions in the first convention. Unfortunately, this convention clashes badly with the next convention: #In
algebra Algebra is a branch of mathematics that deals with abstract systems, known as algebraic structures, and the manipulation of expressions within those systems. It is a generalization of arithmetic that introduces variables and algebraic ope ...
, the usual convention is that the language has two constants, 0 and 1, and two binary functions · and +. The function · has the same meaning as ∧, but ''a''+''b'' means ''a''∨''b''∧¬(''a''∧''b''). The reason for this is that the axioms for a Boolean algebra are then just the axioms for a ring with 1 plus ∀''x'' ''x''2 = ''x''. Unfortunately this clashes with the standard convention in set theory given above. The axioms are: *The axioms for a distributive lattice (see above) *∀a ''a''∧¬''a'' = 0, ∀a ''a''∨¬''a'' = 1 (properties of negation) *Some authors add the extra axiom ¬0 = 1, to exclude the trivial algebra with one element. Tarski proved that the theory of Boolean algebras is decidable. We write ''x'' ≤ ''y'' as an abbreviation for ''x''∧''y'' = ''x'', and atom(''x'') as an abbreviation for ¬''x'' = 0 ∧ ∀''y'' ''y'' ≤ ''x'' → ''y'' = 0 ∨ ''y'' = ''x'', read as "''x'' is an atom", in other words a non-zero element with nothing between it and 0. Here are some first-order properties of Boolean algebras: *Atomic: ∀''x'' ''x'' = 0 ∨ ∃''y'' ''y'' ≤ ''x'' ∧ atom(''y'') *Atomless: ∀''x'' ¬atom(''x'') The theory of atomless Boolean algebras is ω-categorical and complete. For any Boolean algebra ''B'', there are several invariants defined as follows. *the ideal ''I''(''B'') consists of elements that are the sum of an atomic and an atomless element (an element with no atoms below it). *The quotient algebras ''B''''i'' of ''B'' are defined inductively by ''B''0=''B'', ''B''''k''+1 = ''B''''k''/''I''(''B''''k''). *The invariant ''m''(''B'') is the smallest integer such that ''B''''m''+1 is trivial, or ∞ if no such integer exists. *If ''m''(''B'') is finite, the invariant ''n''(''B'') is the number of atoms of ''B''''m''(''B'') if this number is finite, or ∞ if this number is infinite. *The invariant ''l''(''B'') is 0 if ''B''''m''(''B'') is atomic or if ''m''(''B'') is ∞, and 1 otherwise. Then two Boolean algebras are elementarily equivalent if and only if their invariants ''l'', ''m'', and ''n'' are the same. In other words, the values of these invariants classify the possible completions of the theory of Boolean algebras. So the possible complete theories are: *The trivial algebra (if this is allowed; sometimes 0≠1 is included as an axiom.) *The theory with ''m'' = ∞ *The theories with ''m'' a natural number, ''n'' a natural number or ∞, and ''l'' = 0 or 1 (with ''l'' = 0 if ''n'' = 0).


Groups

The signature of
group theory In abstract algebra, group theory studies the algebraic structures known as group (mathematics), groups. The concept of a group is central to abstract algebra: other well-known algebraic structures, such as ring (mathematics), rings, field ( ...
has one constant 1 (the identity), one function of arity 1 (the inverse) whose value on ''t'' is denoted by ''t''−1, and one function of arity 2, which is usually omitted from terms. For any integer ''n'', ''t''''n'' is an abbreviation for the obvious term for the ''n''th power of ''t''.
Group A group is a number of persons or things that are located, gathered, or classed together. Groups of people * Cultural group, a group whose members share the same cultural identity * Ethnic group, a group whose members share the same ethnic iden ...
s are defined by the axioms *''Identity'': ∀''x'' 1''x'' = ''x'' ∧ ''x''1 = ''x'' *''Inverse'': ∀''x'' ''x''−1''x'' = ''1'' ∧ ''xx''−1 = ''1'' *''Associativity'': ∀''x''∀''y''∀''z'' (''xy'')''z'' = ''x''(''yz'') Some properties of groups that can be defined in the first-order language of groups are: * Abelian: ∀''x'' ∀''y'' ''xy'' = ''yx''. * Torsion free: ∀''x'' ''x''2 = 1→''x'' = 1, ∀''x'' ''x''3 = 1 → ''x'' = 1, ∀''x'' ''x''4 = 1 → ''x'' = 1, ... *
Divisible In mathematics, a divisor of an integer n, also called a factor of n, is an integer m that may be multiplied by some integer to produce n. In this case, one also says that n is a '' multiple'' of m. An integer n is divisible or evenly divisibl ...
: ∀''x'' ∃''y'' ''y''2 = ''x'', ∀''x'' ∃''y'' ''y''3 = ''x'', ∀''x'' ∃''y'' ''y''4 = ''x'', ... *Infinite (as in identity theory) *
Exponent In mathematics, exponentiation, denoted , is an operation involving two numbers: the ''base'', , and the ''exponent'' or ''power'', . When is a positive integer, exponentiation corresponds to repeated multiplication of the base: that is, i ...
''n'' (for any fixed positive integer ''n''): ∀''x'' ''x''''n'' = 1 *
Nilpotent In mathematics, an element x of a ring (mathematics), ring R is called nilpotent if there exists some positive integer n, called the index (or sometimes the degree), such that x^n=0. The term, along with its sister Idempotent (ring theory), idem ...
of class ''n'' (for any fixed positive integer ''n'') * Solvable of class ''n'' (for any fixed positive integer ''n'') The theory of abelian groups is decidable. The theory of infinite divisible torsion-free abelian groups is complete, as is the theory of infinite abelian groups of exponent p (for ''p''
prime A prime number (or a prime) is a natural number greater than 1 that is not a product of two smaller natural numbers. A natural number greater than 1 that is not prime is called a composite number. For example, 5 is prime because the only ways ...
). The theory of finite groups is the set of first-order statements in the language of groups that are true in all finite groups (there are plenty of infinite models of this theory). It is not completely trivial to find any such statement that is not true for all groups: one example is "given two elements of order 2, either they are conjugate or there is a non-trivial element commuting with both of them". The properties of being finite, or free, or
simple Simple or SIMPLE may refer to: *Simplicity, the state or quality of being simple Arts and entertainment * ''Simple'' (album), by Andy Yorke, 2008, and its title track * "Simple" (Florida Georgia Line song), 2018 * "Simple", a song by John ...
, or torsion are not first-order. More precisely, the first-order theory of all groups with one of these properties has models that do not have this property.


Rings and fields

The signature of (unital) rings has two constants 0 and 1, two binary functions + and ×, and, optionally, one unary negation function −. Rings Axioms: Addition makes the ring into an abelian group, multiplication is associative and has an identity 1, and multiplication is left and right distributive.
Commutative ring In mathematics, a commutative ring is a Ring (mathematics), ring in which the multiplication operation is commutative. The study of commutative rings is called commutative algebra. Complementarily, noncommutative algebra is the study of ring prope ...
s The axioms for rings plus ∀''x'' ∀''y'' ''xy'' = ''yx''. Fields The axioms for commutative rings plus ∀''x'' (¬ ''x'' = 0 → ∃''y'' ''xy'' = 1) and ¬ 1 = 0. Many of the examples given here have only universal, or ''algebraic'' axioms. The
class Class, Classes, or The Class may refer to: Common uses not otherwise categorized * Class (biology), a taxonomic rank * Class (knowledge representation), a collection of individuals or objects * Class (philosophy), an analytical concept used d ...
of structures satisfying such a theory has the property of being closed under substructure. For example, a subset of a group closed under the group actions of multiplication and inverse is again a group. Since the signature of fields does not usually include multiplicative and additive inverse, the axioms for inverses are not universal, and therefore a substructure of a field closed under addition and multiplication is not always a field. This can be remedied by adding unary inverse functions to the language. For any positive integer ''n'' the property that all equations of degree ''n'' have a root can be expressed by a single first-order sentence: *∀ ''a''1 ∀ ''a''2... ∀ ''a''''n'' ∃''x'' (...((''x''+''a''1)''x'' +''a''2)''x''+...)''x''+''a''''n'' = 0
Perfect field In algebra, a field ''k'' is perfect if any one of the following equivalent conditions holds: * Every irreducible polynomial over ''k'' has no multiple roots in any field extension ''F/k''. * Every irreducible polynomial over ''k'' has non-zero f ...
s The axioms for fields, plus axioms for each prime number ''p'' stating that if ''p'' 1 = 0 (i.e. the field has characteristic ''p''), then every field element has a ''p''th root. Algebraically closed fields of characteristic ''p'' The axioms for fields, plus for every positive ''n'' the axiom that all polynomials of degree ''n'' have a root, plus axioms fixing the characteristic. The classical examples of complete theories. Categorical in all uncountable cardinals. The theory ''ACF''p has a ''universal domain property'', in the sense that every structure ''N'' satisfying the universal axioms of ''ACF''p is a substructure of a sufficiently large algebraically closed field M \models ACF_0 , and additionally any two such embeddings ''N'' → ''M'' induce an
automorphism In mathematics, an automorphism is an isomorphism from a mathematical object to itself. It is, in some sense, a symmetry of the object, and a way of mapping the object to itself while preserving all of its structure. The set of all automorphism ...
of ''M''.
Finite field In mathematics, a finite field or Galois field (so-named in honor of Évariste Galois) is a field (mathematics), field that contains a finite number of Element (mathematics), elements. As with any field, a finite field is a Set (mathematics), s ...
s The theory of finite fields is the set of all first-order statements that are true in all finite fields. Significant examples of such statements can, for example, be given by applying the Chevalley–Warning theorem, over the
prime field In mathematics, a field is a set on which addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division are defined and behave as the corresponding operations on rational and real numbers. A field is thus a fundamental algebraic structure which is wid ...
s. The name is a little misleading as the theory has plenty of infinite models. Ax proved that the theory is decidable.
Formally real field In mathematics, in particular in field theory and real algebra, a formally real field is a field that can be equipped with a (not necessarily unique) ordering that makes it an ordered field. Alternative definitions The definition given above ...
s The axioms for fields plus, for every positive integer ''n'', the axiom: * ∀ ''a''1 ∀ ''a''2... ∀ ''a''''n'' ''a''1''a''1+''a''2''a''2+ ...+''a''''n''''a''''n''=0 → ''a''''1''=0∧''a''''2''=0∧ ... ∧''a''''n''=0. That is, 0 is not a non-trivial sum of squares.
Real closed field In mathematics, a real closed field is a field F that has the same first-order properties as the field of real numbers. Some examples are the field of real numbers, the field of real algebraic numbers, and the field of hyperreal numbers. Def ...
s The axioms for formally real fields plus the axioms: *∀''x'' ∃''y'' (''x''=''yy'' ∨ ''x''+''yy''= 0); *for every odd positive integer ''n'', the axiom stating that every polynomial of degree ''n'' has a root. The theory of real closed fields is effective and complete and therefore decidable (the Tarski–Seidenberg theorem). The addition of further function symbols (e.g., the exponential function, the sine function) may change decidability. ''p''-adic fields showed that the theory of ''p''-adic fields is decidable and gave a set of axioms for it.


Geometry

Axioms for various systems of geometry usually use a typed language, with the different types corresponding to different geometric objects such as points, lines, circles, planes, and so on. The signature will often consist of binary incidence relations between objects of different types; for example, the relation that a point lies on a line. The signature may have more complicated relations; for example ordered geometry might have a ternary "betweenness" relation for 3 points, which says whether one lies between two others, or a "congruence" relation between 2 pairs of points. Some examples of axiomatized systems of geometry include
ordered geometry Ordered geometry is a form of geometry featuring the concept of intermediacy (or "betweenness") but, like projective geometry, omitting the basic notion of measurement. Ordered geometry is a fundamental geometry forming a common framework for affi ...
,
absolute geometry Absolute geometry is a geometry based on an axiom system for Euclidean geometry without the parallel postulate or any of its alternatives. Traditionally, this has meant using only the first four of Euclid's postulates. The term was introduced by ...
,
affine geometry In mathematics, affine geometry is what remains of Euclidean geometry when ignoring (mathematicians often say "forgetting") the metric notions of distance and angle. As the notion of '' parallel lines'' is one of the main properties that is i ...
,
Euclidean geometry Euclidean geometry is a mathematical system attributed to ancient Greek mathematics, Greek mathematician Euclid, which he described in his textbook on geometry, ''Euclid's Elements, Elements''. Euclid's approach consists in assuming a small set ...
,
projective geometry In mathematics, projective geometry is the study of geometric properties that are invariant with respect to projective transformations. This means that, compared to elementary Euclidean geometry, projective geometry has a different setting (''p ...
, and
hyperbolic geometry In mathematics, hyperbolic geometry (also called Lobachevskian geometry or János Bolyai, Bolyai–Nikolai Lobachevsky, Lobachevskian geometry) is a non-Euclidean geometry. The parallel postulate of Euclidean geometry is replaced with: :For a ...
. For each of these geometries there are many different and inequivalent systems of axioms for various dimensions. Some of these axiom systems include "completeness" axioms that are not first order. As a typical example, the axioms for projective geometry use 2 types, points and lines, and a binary incidence relation between points and lines. If point and line variables are indicated by small and capital letter, and ''a'' incident to ''A'' is written as ''aA'', then one set of axioms is *\forall a\forall b\;\lnot a=b\rightarrow \exists C\; aC\land bC (There is a line through any 2 distinct points ''a'',''b'' ...) *\forall a\forall b\forall C\forall D\; \lnot a=b\land aC\land bC \land aD\land bD\rightarrow C=D (... which is unique) *\forall a\forall b\forall c\forall d\forall e\forall G\forall H \;aH\land bH\land eH\land cG\land dG\land eG\rightarrow\exists f\exists I\exists J\; aI\land cI\land fI\land bJ\land dJ\land fJ (Veblen's axiom: if ''ab'' and ''cd'' lie on intersecting lines, then so do ''ac'' and ''bd''.) *\forall A\exists b\exists c\exists d\; bA\land cA\land dA\land \lnot b=c\land \lnot b=d\land \lnot c=d (Every line has at least 3 points) Euclid did not state all the axioms for Euclidean geometry explicitly, and the first complete list was given by Hilbert in
Hilbert's axioms Hilbert's axioms are a set of 20 assumptions proposed by David Hilbert in 1899 in his book ''Grundlagen der Geometrie'' (tr. ''The Foundations of Geometry'') as the foundation for a modern treatment of Euclidean geometry. Other well-known modern ax ...
. This is not a first-order axiomatization as one of Hilbert's axioms is a second order completeness axiom.
Tarski's axioms Tarski's axioms are an axiom system for Euclidean geometry, specifically for that portion of Euclidean geometry that is formulable in first-order logic with identity (i.e. is formulable as an elementary theory). As such, it does not require an u ...
are a first-order axiomatization of Euclidean geometry. Tarski showed this axiom system is complete and decidable by relating it to the complete and decidable theory of real closed fields.


Differential algebra

* The theory DF of
differential field In mathematics, differential algebra is, broadly speaking, the area of mathematics consisting in the study of differential equations and differential operators as algebra, algebraic objects in view of deriving properties of differential equations ...
s. The signature is that of fields (0, 1, +, −, ×) together with a unary function ∂, the derivation. The axioms are those for fields together with :\forall u\forall v\,\partial(uv) = u \,\partial v + v\, \partial u :\forall u\forall v\,\partial (u + v) = \partial u + \partial v\ . For this theory one can add the condition that the characteristic is ''p'', a prime or zero, to get the theory DF''p'' of differential fields of characteristic ''p'' (and similarly with the other theories below). If ''K'' is a differential field then the field of constants k = \. The theory of differentially perfect fields is the theory of differential fields together with the condition that the field of constants is perfect; in other words, for each prime ''p'' it has the axiom: :\forall u \,\partial(u)=0 \land p 1 = 0\rightarrow \exists v\, v^p=u (There is little point in demanding that the whole field should be a
perfect field In algebra, a field ''k'' is perfect if any one of the following equivalent conditions holds: * Every irreducible polynomial over ''k'' has no multiple roots in any field extension ''F/k''. * Every irreducible polynomial over ''k'' has non-zero f ...
, because in non-zero characteristic this implies the differential is 0.) For technical reasons to do with
quantifier elimination Quantifier elimination is a concept of simplification used in mathematical logic, model theory, and theoretical computer science. Informally, a quantified statement "\exists x such that ..." can be viewed as a question "When is there an x such ...
, it is sometimes more convenient to force the constant field to be perfect by adding a new symbol ''r'' to the signature with the axioms :\forall u \,\partial(u)=0 \land p 1 = 0 \rightarrow r(u)^p=u :\forall u \,\lnot \partial(u)=0\rightarrow r(u)=0. * The theory of differentially closed fields (DCF) is the theory of differentially perfect fields with axioms saying that if ''f'' and ''g'' are differential polynomials and the separant of ''f'' is nonzero and ''g''≠0 and ''f'' has order greater than that of ''g'', then there is some ''x'' in the field with ''f''(''x'')=0 and ''g''(''x'')≠0.


Addition

The theory of the natural numbers with a successor function has signature consisting of a constant 0 and a unary function ''S'' ("successor": ''S''(''x'') is interpreted as ''x''+1), and has axioms: # ∀x ¬ Sx = 0 # ∀x∀y Sx = Sy → x = y #Let ''P''(''x'') be a first-order formula with a single
free variable In mathematics, and in other disciplines involving formal languages, including mathematical logic and computer science, a variable may be said to be either free or bound. Some older books use the terms real variable and apparent variable for f ...
''x''. Then the following formula is an axiom: :(''P''(0) ∧ ∀''x''(''P''(''x'')→''P''(''Sx''))) → ∀''y'' ''P''(''y''). The last axiom (induction) can be replaced by the axioms *For each integer ''n''>0, the axiom ∀x SSS...Sx ≠ x (with ''n'' copies of ''S'') * ∀x ¬ x = 0 → ∃y Sy = x The theory of the natural numbers with a successor function is complete and decidable, and is κ-categorical for uncountable κ but not for countable κ. Presburger arithmetic is the theory of the natural numbers under addition, with signature consisting of a constant 0, a unary function ''S'', and a binary function +. It is complete and decidable. The axioms are # ∀x ¬ Sx = 0 # ∀x∀y Sx = Sy → x = y # ∀x x + 0 = x # ∀x∀y x + Sy = S(x + y) #Let ''P''(''x'') be a first-order formula with a single free variable ''x''. Then the following formula is an axiom: :(''P''(0) ∧ ∀''x''(''P''(''x'')→''P''(''Sx''))) → ∀''y'' ''P''(''y'').


Arithmetic

Many of the first-order theories described above can be extended to complete recursively enumerable consistent theories. This is no longer true for most of the following theories; they can usually encode both multiplication and addition of natural numbers, and this gives them enough power to encode themselves, which implies that Gödel's incompleteness theorem applies and the theories can no longer be both complete and recursively enumerable (unless they are inconsistent). The signature of a theory of arithmetic has: *The constant 0; *The unary function, the successor function, here denoted by prefix ''S'', or by prefix σ or postfix ′ elsewhere; *Two binary functions, denoted by infix + and ×, called "addition" and "multiplication." Some authors take the signature to contain a constant 1 instead of the function ''S'', then define ''S'' in the obvious way as ''St'' = 1 + ''t''. Robinson arithmetic (also called Q). Axioms (1) and (2) govern the distinguished element 0. (3) assures that ''S'' is an Injective function, injection. Axioms (4) and (5) are the standard recursive definition of addition; (6) and (7) do the same for multiplication. Robinson arithmetic can be thought of as Peano arithmetic without induction. Q is a weak theory for which Gödel's incompleteness theorems, Gödel's incompleteness theorem holds. Axioms: # ∀''x'' ¬ S''x'' = 0 # ∀''x'' ¬ ''x'' = 0 → ∃''y'' S''y'' = ''x'' # ∀''x''∀''y'' S''x'' = S''y'' → ''x'' = ''y'' # ∀''x'' ''x'' + 0 = ''x'' # ∀''x''∀''y'' ''x'' + S''y'' = S(''x'' + ''y'') # ∀''x'' ''x'' × 0 = 0 # ∀''x''∀''y'' ''x'' × S''y'' = (''x'' × ''y'') + ''x''. IΣn is first-order Peano arithmetic with induction restricted to Arithmetical hierarchy, Σn formulas (for ''n'' = 0, 1, 2, ...). The theory IΣ0 is often denoted by IΔ0. This is a series of more and more powerful fragments of Peano arithmetic. The case ''n'' = 1 has about the same strength as primitive recursive arithmetic (PRA). Exponential function arithmetic (EFA) is IΣ0 with an axiom stating that ''x''''y'' exists for all ''x'' and ''y'' (with the usual properties). First-order Peano arithmetic, PA. The "standard" theory of arithmetic. The axioms are the axioms of Robinson arithmetic above, together with the axiom scheme of induction: * \phi(0) \wedge (\forall x \phi(x) \rightarrow \phi(Sx)) \rightarrow (\forall x \phi(x)) for any formula φ in the language of PA. φ may contain free variables other than ''x''. Kurt Gödel's 1931 paper proved that PA is incomplete, and has no consistent recursively enumerable completions. Complete arithmetic (also known as true arithmetic) is the theory of the standard model of arithmetic, the natural numbers N. It is complete but does not have a recursively enumerable set of axioms. For the real numbers, the situation is slightly different: The case that includes just addition and multiplication cannot encode the integers, and hence Gödel's incompleteness theorem Tarski–Seidenberg theorem, does not apply. Decidability of first-order theories of the real numbers, Complications arise when adding further function symbols (e.g., exponentiation).


Second order arithmetic

Second-order arithmetic can refer to a first-order theory (in spite of the name) with two types of variables, thought of as varying over integers and subsets of the integers. (There is also a theory of arithmetic in second order logic that is called second order arithmetic. It has only one model, unlike the corresponding theory in first-order logic, which is incomplete.) The signature will typically be the signature 0, ''S'', +, × of arithmetic, together with a membership relation ∈ between integers and subsets (though there are numerous minor variations). The axioms are those of Robinson arithmetic, together with axiom schemes of Mathematical induction, induction and Axiom schema of specification, comprehension. There are many different subtheories of second order arithmetic that differ in which formulas are allowed in the induction and comprehension schemes. In order of increasing strength, five of the most common systems are *\mathsf_0, Recursive Comprehension *\mathsf_0, Weak Kőnig's lemma *\mathsf_0, Arithmetical comprehension *\mathsf_0, Arithmetical Transfinite Recursion *\Pi^1_1\mbox\mathsf_0, \Pi^1_1 comprehension These are defined in detail in the articles on second order arithmetic and reverse mathematics.


Set theories

The usual signature of set theory has one binary relation ∈, no constants, and no functions. Some of the theories below are "class theories" which have two sorts of object, sets and classes. There are three common ways of handling this in first-order logic: #Use first-order logic with two types. #Use ordinary first-order logic, but add a new unary predicate "Set", where "Set(''t'')" means informally "''t'' is a set". #Use ordinary first-order logic, and instead of adding a new predicate to the language, treat "Set(''t'')" as an abbreviation for "∃''y'' ''t''∈''y''" Some first-order set theories include: *Weak theories lacking powersets: **General set theory, S' (Tarski, Mostowski, and Robinson, 1953); (finitely axiomatizable) **Kripke–Platek set theory; KP; **Pocket set theory **General set theory, GST **Constructive set theory, CZF *Mac Lane set theory and Elementary topos theory *Zermelo set theory; Z *Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory; ZF, ZFC; *Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory; NBG; (finitely axiomatizable) *Ackermann set theory; *Scott–Potter set theory *New Foundations; NF (finitely axiomatizable) *Positive set theory *Morse–Kelley set theory; MK; *Tarski–Grothendieck set theory; TG; Some extra first-order axioms that can be added to one of these (usually ZF) include: *Axiom of choice, axiom of dependent choice *Generalized continuum hypothesis *Martin's axiom (usually together with the negation of the continuum hypothesis), Martin's maximum *diamondsuit, ◊ and clubsuit, ♣ *Axiom of constructibility (V=L) *Proper forcing axiom *Analytic determinacy, projective determinacy, Axiom of determinacy *Many list of large cardinal properties, large cardinal axioms


See also

* *


References


Further reading

* * * {{Mathematical logic Model theory, First-order theories, List of Mathematical logic, First-order theories, List of Mathematics-related lists, First-order theories