HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Fair division of a single homogeneous resource is one of the simplest settings in
fair division Fair division is the problem in game theory of dividing a set of resources among several people who have an entitlement to them so that each person receives their due share. That problem arises in various real-world settings such as division of inh ...
problems. There is a single resource that should be divided between several people. The challenge is that each person derives a different utility from each amount of the resource. Hence, there are several conflicting principles for deciding how the resource should be divided. A primary conflict is between efficiency and equality. Efficiency is represented by the ''utilitarian'' rule, which maximizes the sum of utilities; equality is represented by the ''egalitarian'' rule, which maximizes the minimum utility.


Setting

In a certain society, there are: * t units of some divisible resource. * n agents with different "utilities". * The utility of agent i is represented by a function u_i; when agent i receives y_i units of resource, he derives from it a utility of u_i(y_i). This setting can have various interpretations. For example: * The resource is wood, the agents are builders, and the utility functions represent their productive power - u_i(y_i) is the number of buildings that agent i can build using y_i units of wood. * The resource is a medication, the agents are patients, and the utility functions represent their chance of recovery - u_i(y_i) is the probability of agent i to recover by getting y_i doses of the medication. In any case, the society has to decide how to divide the resource among the agents: it has to find a vector y_1,\dots,y_n such that: y_1+\cdots+y_n = t


Allocation rules


Envy-free

The
Envy-freeness Envy-freeness, also known as no-envy, is a criterion for fair division. It says that, when resources are allocated among people with equal rights, each person should receive a share that is, in their eyes, at least as good as the share received by a ...
rule says that the resource should be allocated such that no agent envies another agent. In the case of a single homogeneous resource, it always selects the allocation that gives each agent the same amount of the resource, regardless of their utility function: ::\forall i: y_i = t/n


Utilitarian

The utilitarian rule says that the sum of utilities should be maximized. Therefore, the utilitarian allocation is: ::y = \arg\max_y \sum_i u_i(y_i)


Egalitarian

The egalitarian rule says that the utilities of all agents should be equal. Therefore, we would like to select an allocation that satisfies: ::\forall i,j: u_i(y_i) = u_j(y_j) However, such allocation may not exist, since the ranges of the utility functions might not overlap (see example below). To ensure that a solution exists, we allow different utility levels, but require that agents with utility levels above the minimum receive no resources: ::y_i>0 \implies u_i(y_i) = \min_j u_j(y_j) Equivalently, the egalitarian allocation maximizes the minimum utility: ::y = \arg\max_y \min_i u_i(y_i) The utilitarian and egalitarian rules may lead to the same allocation or to different allocations, depending on the utility functions. Some examples are illustrated below.


Examples


Common utility and unequal endowments

Suppose all agents have the same utility function, u, but each agent i has a different initial endowment, x_i. So the utility of each agent i is given by: ::u_i(y_i) = u(x_i + y_i) If u is a concave function, representing
diminishing returns In economics, diminishing returns are the decrease in marginal (incremental) output of a production process as the amount of a single factor of production is incrementally increased, holding all other factors of production equal ( ceteris parib ...
, then the utilitarian and egalitarian allocations are the same - trying to equalize the endowments of the agents. For example, if there are 3 agents with initial endowments x=2,4,9 and the total amount is t=8, then both rules recommend the allocation y=5,3,0, since it both pushes towards equal utilities (as much as possible) and maximizes the sum of utilities. In contrast, if u is a convex function, representing
increasing returns In economics, diminishing returns are the decrease in marginal (incremental) output of a production process as the amount of a single factor of production is incrementally increased, holding all other factors of production equal (ceteris paribu ...
, then the egalitarian allocation still pushes towards equality, but the utilitarian allocation now gives all the endowment to the richest agent: y=0,0,9. This makes sense, for example, when the resource is a scarce medication: it may be socially best to give all medication to the patient with the highest chances of curing.


Constant utility ratios

Suppose there is a common utility function u, but each agent has a different coefficient a_i representing this agent's productivity. So the utility of each agent i is given by: ::u_i(y_i) = a_i\cdot u(y_i) Here, the utilitarian and egalitarian approaches are diametrically opposed. * The egalitarian allocation gives more resources to the less productive agents, in order to compensate them and let them reach a high utility level: *::a_i>a_j \implies y_j>y_i * The utilitarian allocation gives more resources to the more productive agents, since they will use the resources better: *::a_i>a_j \implies y_i>y_j


Properties of allocation rules

* Resource-monotonicity: the envy-free rule and the egalitarian rule are always resource-monotonic. The utilitarian rule is resource-monotonic when all utility functions are concave functions, representing
diminishing returns In economics, diminishing returns are the decrease in marginal (incremental) output of a production process as the amount of a single factor of production is incrementally increased, holding all other factors of production equal ( ceteris parib ...
; but, when some utility functions are convex functions, representing
increasing returns In economics, diminishing returns are the decrease in marginal (incremental) output of a production process as the amount of a single factor of production is incrementally increased, holding all other factors of production equal (ceteris paribu ...
, the utilitarian rule might be not resource-monotonic.


See also

*
Utilitarianism In ethical philosophy, utilitarianism is a family of normative ethical theories that prescribe actions that maximize happiness and well-being for all affected individuals. Although different varieties of utilitarianism admit different chara ...
*
Egalitarianism Egalitarianism (), or equalitarianism, is a school of thought within political philosophy that builds from the concept of social equality, prioritizing it for all people. Egalitarian doctrines are generally characterized by the idea that all hu ...


References

{{reflist Fair division