E-values
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In statistical hypothesis testing, e-values quantify the evidence in the data against a
null hypothesis In scientific research, the null hypothesis (often denoted ''H''0) is the claim that no difference or relationship exists between two sets of data or variables being analyzed. The null hypothesis is that any experimentally observed difference is d ...
(e.g., "the coin is fair", or, in a medical context, "this new treatment has no effect"). They serve as a more robust alternative to p-values, addressing some shortcomings of the latter. In contrast to p-values, e-values can deal with optional continuation: e-values of subsequent experiments (e.g. clinical trials concerning the same treatment) may simply be multiplied to provide a new, "product" e-value that represents the evidence in the joint experiment. This works even if, as often happens in practice, the decision to perform later experiments may depend in vague, unknown ways on the data observed in earlier experiments, and it is not known beforehand how many trials will be conducted: the product e-value remains a meaningful quantity, leading to tests with Type-I error control. For this reason, e-values and their sequential extension, the ''e-process'', are the fundamental building blocks for anytime-valid statistical methods (e.g. confidence sequences). Another advantage over p-values is that any weighted average of e-values remains an e-value, even if the individual e-values are arbitrarily dependent. This is one of the reasons why e-values have also turned out to be useful tools in multiple testing. E-values can be interpreted in a number of different ways: first, the reciprocal of any e-value is itself a p-value, but a special, conservative one, quite different from p-values used in practice. Second, they are broad generalizations of likelihood ratios and are also related to, yet distinct from,
Bayes factors The Bayes factor is a ratio of two competing statistical models represented by their marginal likelihood, and is used to quantify the support for one model over the other. The models in questions can have a common set of parameters, such as a nul ...
. Third, they have an interpretation as bets. Finally, in a sequential context, they can also be interpreted as increments of nonnegative supermartingales. Interest in e-values has exploded since 2019, when the term 'e-value' was coined and a number of breakthrough results were achieved by several research groups. The first overview article appeared in 2023.


Definition and mathematical background

Let the
null hypothesis In scientific research, the null hypothesis (often denoted ''H''0) is the claim that no difference or relationship exists between two sets of data or variables being analyzed. The null hypothesis is that any experimentally observed difference is d ...
H_0 be given as a set of distributions for data Y. Usually Y= (X_1, \ldots, X_\tau ) with each X_i a single outcome and \tau a fixed sample size or some stopping time. We shall refer to such Y, which represent the full sequence of outcomes of a statistical experiment, as a ''sample'' or ''batch of outcomes.'' But in some cases Y may also be an unordered bag of outcomes or a single outcome. An e-variable or e-statistic is a ''nonnegative'' random variable E= E(Y) such that under all P \in H_0, its expected value is bounded by 1: _P \leq 1 . The value taken by e-variable E is called the e-value''.'' In practice, the term ''e-value'' (a number) is often used when one is really referring to the underlying e-variable (a random variable, that is, a measurable function of the data).


Interpretations


As conservative p-values

For any e-variable E and any 0< \alpha \leq 1 and all P \in H_0, it holds that P\left(E \geq \frac\right)= P(1/E \leq \alpha ) \ \overset\ \alpha In words: 1/E is a p-value, and the ''e-value based test with
significance level In statistical hypothesis testing, a result has statistical significance when it is very unlikely to have occurred given the null hypothesis (simply by chance alone). More precisely, a study's defined significance level, denoted by \alpha, is the p ...
\alpha ,'' which rejects P_0 if 1/E \leq \alpha , has Type-I error bounded by \alpha . But, whereas with standard p-values the inequality (*) above is usually an equality (with continuous-valued data) or near-equality (with discrete data), this is not the case with e-variables. This makes e-value-based tests more conservative (less power) than those based on standard p-values, and it is the price to pay for safety (i.e., retaining Type-I error guarantees) under optional continuation and averaging.


As generalizations of likelihood ratios

Let H_0 = \ be a simple null hypothesis. Let Q be any other distribution on Y , and let E:= \frac be their likelihood ratio. Then E is an e-variable. Conversely, any e-variable relative to a simple null H_0 = \ can be written as a likelihood ratio with respect to ''some'' distribution Q . Thus, when the null is simple, e-variables coincide with likelihood ratios. E-variables exist for general composite nulls as well though, and they may then be thought of as generalizations of likelihood ratios. The two main ways of constructing e-variables, UI and RIPr (see below) both lead to expressions that are variations of likelihood ratios as well. Two other standard generalizations of the likelihood ratio are (a) the generalized likelihood ratio as used in the standard, classical likelihood ratio test and (b) the
Bayes factor The Bayes factor is a ratio of two competing statistical models represented by their marginal likelihood, and is used to quantify the support for one model over the other. The models in questions can have a common set of parameters, such as a nul ...
. Importantly, neither (a) nor (b) are e-variables in general: generalized likelihood ratios in sense (a) are not e-variables unless the alternative is simple (see below under "universal inference"). Bayes factors ''are'' e-variables if the null is simple. To see this, note that, if = \ represents a statistical model, and w a prior density on \Theta, then we can set Q as above to be the Bayes marginal distribution with density q(Y) = \int q_(Y) w(\theta) d \theta and then E= q(Y)/p_0(Y) is also a Bayes factor of H_0 vs. H_1 := . If the null is composite, then some special e-variables can be written as Bayes factors with some very special priors, but most Bayes factors one encounters in practice are not e-variables and many e-variables one encounters in practice are not Bayes factors.


As bets

Suppose you can buy a ticket for 1 monetary unit, with nonnegative pay-off E=E(Y). The statements "E is an e-variable" and "if the null hypothesis is true, you do not expect to gain any money if you engage in this bet" are logically equivalent. This is because E being an e-variable means that the expected gain of buying the ticket is the pay-off minus the cost, i.e. E-1, which has expectation \leq 0. Based on this interpretation, the product e-value for a sequence of tests can be interpreted as the amount of money you have gained by sequentially betting with pay-offs given by the individual e-variables and always re-investing all your gains. The betting interpretation becomes particularly visible if we rewrite an e-variable as E := 1 + \lambda U where U has expectation \leq 0 under all P \in H_0 and \lambda\in is chosen so that E \geq 0 a.s. Any e-variable can be written in the 1 + \lambda U form although with parametric nulls, writing it as a likelihood ratio is usually mathematically more convenient. The 1 + \lambda U form on the other hand is often more convenient in
nonparametric Nonparametric statistics is the branch of statistics that is not based solely on Statistical parameter, parametrized families of probability distributions (common examples of parameters are the mean and variance). Nonparametric statistics is based ...
settings. As a prototypical example, consider the case that Y= (X_1, \ldots, X_n) with the X_i taking values in the bounded interval ,1/math>. According to H_0, the X_i are i.i.d. according to a distribution P with mean \mu; no other assumptions about P are made. Then we may first construct a family of e-variables for single outcomes, E_ := 1+ \lambda (X_i - \mu) , for any \lambda \in 1/(1-\mu),1/\mu (these are the \lambda for which E_ is guaranteed to be nonnegative). We may then define a new e-variable for the complete data vector Y by taking the product E:= \prod_^n E_ , where \breve, X^ is an estimate for , based only on past data X^= (X_1, \ldots,X_) , and designed to make E_ as large as possible in the "e-power" or "GRO" sense (see below). Waudby-Smith and Ramdas use this approach to construct "nonparametric" confidence intervals for the mean that tend to be significantly narrower than those based on more classical methods such as Chernoff, Hoeffding and Bernstein bounds.


A fundamental property: optional continuation

E-values are more suitable than p-value when one expects follow-up tests involving the same null hypothesis with different data or experimental set-ups. This includes, for example, combining individual results in a
meta-analysis A meta-analysis is a statistical analysis that combines the results of multiple scientific studies. Meta-analyses can be performed when there are multiple scientific studies addressing the same question, with each individual study reporting me ...
. The advantage of e-values in this setting is that they allow for ''optional continuation.'' Indeed, they have been employed in what may be the world's first fully 'online' meta-analysis with explicit Type-I error control. Informally, optional continuation implies that the product of any number of e-values, E_, E_,\ldots , defined on independent samples Y_, Y_,\ldots , is itself an e-value, even if the ''definition'' of each e-value is allowed to depend on all previous outcomes, and no matter what rule is used to decide when to stop gathering new samples (e.g. to perform new trials). It follows that, for any significance level 0 <\alpha < 1 , if the null is true, then the probability that a product of e-values will ''ever'' become larger than 1/\alpha , is bounded by \alpha . Thus if we decide to combine the samples observed so far and reject the null if the product e-value is larger than 1/\alpha , then our Type-I error probability remains bounded by \alpha . We say that testing based on e-values ''remains safe (Type-I valid) under optional continuation''. Mathematically, this is shown by first showing that the product e-variables form a nonnegative discrete-time martingale in the filtration generated by Y_, Y_,\ldots (the individual e-variables are then increments of this martingale). The results then follow as a consequence of Doob's optional stopping theorem and Ville's inequality. We already implicitly used product e-variables in the example above, where we defined e-variables on individual outcomes X_i and designed a new e-value by taking products. Thus, in the example the individual outcomes X_i play the role of 'batches' (full samples) Y_ above, and we can therefore even engage in ''optional stopping'' "within" the original batch Y : we may stop the data analysis at any individual ''outcome'' (not just "batch of outcomes") we like, for whatever reason, and reject if the product so far exceeds 1/\alpha . Not all e-variables defined for batches of outcomes Y can be decomposed as a product of per-outcome e-values in this way though. If this is not possible, we cannot use them for optional stopping (within a sample Y ) but only for optional continuation (from one sample Y_ to the next Y_ and so on).


Construction and optimality

If we set E:=1 independently of the data we get a ''trivial'' e-value: it is an e-variable by definition, but it will never allow us to reject the null hypothesis. This example shows that some e-variables may be better than others, in a sense to be defined below. Intuitively, a good e-variable is one that tends to be large (much larger than 1) if the alternative is true. This is analogous to the situation with p-values: both e-values and p-values can be defined without referring to an alternative, but ''if'' an alternative is available, we would like them to be small (p-values) or large (e-values) with high probability. In standard hypothesis tests, the quality of a valid test is formalized by the notion of '' statistical power'' but this notion has to be suitably modified in the context of e-values. The standard notion of quality of an e-variable relative to a given alternative H_1 , used by most authors in the field, is a generalization of the
Kelly criterion In probability theory, the Kelly criterion (or Kelly strategy or Kelly bet), is a formula that determines the optimal theoretical size for a bet. It is valid when the expected returns are known. The Kelly bet size is found by maximizing the expec ...
in economics and (since it does exhibit close relations to classical power) is sometimes called ''e-power''; the optimal e-variable in this sense is known as ''log-optimal'' or ''growth-rate optimal'' (often abbreviated to GRO). In the case of a simple alternative H_1 = \ , the e-power of a given e-variable S is simply defined as the expectation _Q log E ; in case of composite alternatives, there are various versions (e.g. worst-case absolute, worst-case relative) of e-power and GRO.


Simple alternative, simple null: likelihood ratio

Let H_0 = \ and H_1 = \ both be simple. Then the likelihood ratio e-variable E = q(Y)/p_0(Y) has maximal e-power in the sense above, i.e. it is GRO.


Simple alternative, composite null: reverse information projection (RIPr)

Let H_1 = \ be simple and H_0 = \ be composite, such that all elements of H_0 \cup H_1 have densities (denoted by lower-case letters) relative to the same underlying measure. Grünwald et al. show that under weak regularity conditions, the GRO e-variable exists, is essentially unique, and is given by E:= \frac where p_ is the Reverse Information Projection (RIPr) of Q unto the convex hull of H_0. Under further regularity conditions (and in all practically relevant cases encountered so far), p_ is given by a Bayes marginal density: there exists a specific, unique distribution W on \Theta_0 such that p_(Y) = \int_ p_(Y) dW(\theta) .


Simple alternative, composite null: universal inference (UI)

In the same setting as above, show that, under no regularity conditions at all, E= \frac \left( = \frac \right) is an e-variable (with the second equality holding if the MLE (
maximum likelihood estimator In statistics, maximum likelihood estimation (MLE) is a method of estimating the parameters of an assumed probability distribution, given some observed data. This is achieved by maximizing a likelihood function so that, under the assumed statis ...
) \hat\theta \mid Y based on data Y is always well-defined). This way of constructing e-variables has been called the universal inference (UI) method, "universal" referring to the fact that no regularity conditions are required.


Composite alternative, simple null

Now let H_0 = \ be simple and H_1 = \ be composite, such that all elements of H_0 \cup H_1 have densities relative to the same underlying measure. There are now two generic, closely related ways of obtaining e-variables that are close to growth-optimal (appropriately redefined for composite H_1 ): Robbins' method of mixtures and the plug-in method, originally due to Wald but, in essence, re-discovered by Philip Dawid as "prequential plug-in" and
Jorma Rissanen Jorma Johannes Rissanen (October 20, 1932 – May 9, 2020) was an information theorist, known for originating the minimum description length (MDL) principle and practical approaches to arithmetic coding for lossless data compression. His work in ...
as "predictive MDL". The method of mixtures essentially amounts to "being Bayesian about the numerator" (the reason it is not called "Bayesian method" is that, when both null and alternative are composite, the numerator may often not be a Bayes marginal): we posit any prior distribution W on \Theta_1 and set \bar_W(Y) := \int_ q_ (Y) dW(\theta) and use the e-variable \bar_W(Y)/p(Y) . To explicate the plug-in method, suppose that Y= (X_1, \ldots, X_n) where X_1, X_2, \ldots constitute a stochastic process and let \breve\theta \mid X^ be an estimator of \theta \in \Theta_1 based on data X^i=(X_1, \ldots, X_i) for i \geq 0 . In practice one usually takes a "smoothed"
maximum likelihood In statistics, maximum likelihood estimation (MLE) is a method of estimating the parameters of an assumed probability distribution, given some observed data. This is achieved by maximizing a likelihood function so that, under the assumed stat ...
estimator (such as, for example, the regression coefficients in
ridge regression Ridge regression is a method of estimating the coefficients of multiple- regression models in scenarios where the independent variables are highly correlated. It has been used in many fields including econometrics, chemistry, and engineering. Als ...
), initially set to some "default value" \breve\theta \mid X^:= \theta_0 . One now recursively constructs a density \bar_ for X^n by setting \bar_(X^n) = \prod_^n q_(X_i \mid X^) . Effectively, both the method of mixtures and the plug-in method can be thought of ''learning'' a specific instantiation of the alternative that explains the data well.


Composite null and alternative

In parametric settings, we can simply combine the main methods for the composite alternative (obtaining \bar_ or \bar_ ) with the main methods for the composite null (UI or RIPr, using the single distribution \bar_ or \bar_ as an alternative). Note in particular that when using the plug-in method together with the UI method, the resulting e-variable will look like \frac which resembles, but is still fundamentally different from, the generalized likelihood ratio as used in the classical likelihood ratio test. The advantage of the UI method compared to RIPr is that (a) it can be applied whenever the MLE can be efficiently computed - in many such cases, it is not known whether/how the reverse information projection can be calculated; and (b) that it 'automatically' gives not just an e-variable but a full e-process (see below): if we replace n in the formula above by a general stopping time \tau, the resulting ratio is still an e-variable; for the reverse information projection this automatic e-process generation only holds in special cases. Its main disadvantage compared to RIPr is that it can be substantially sub-optimal in terms of the e-power/GRO criterion, which means that it leads to tests which also have less classical statistical power than RIPr-based methods. Thus, for settings in which the RIPr-method is computationally feasible and leads to e-processes, it is to be preferred. These include the z-test, t-test and corresponding linear regressions, k-sample tests with Bernoulli, Gaussian and Poisson distributions and the logrank test
an R package
is available for a subset of these), as well as conditional independence testing under a ''model-X assumption''. However, in many other statistical testing problems, it is currently (2023) unknown whether fast implementations of the reverse information projection exist, and they may very well not exist (e.g. generalized linear models without the model-X assumption). In nonparametric settings (such as testing a mean as in the example above, or nonparametric 2-sample testing), it is often more natural to consider e-variables of the 1+ \lambda U type. However, while these superficially look very different from likelihood ratios, they can often still be interpreted as such and sometimes can even be re-interpreted as implementing a version of the RIPr-construction. Finally, in practice, one sometimes resorts to mathematically or computationally convenient combinations of RIPr, UI and other methods. For example, RIPr is applied to get optimal e-variables for small blocks of outcomes and these are then multiplied to obtain e-variables for larger samples - these e-variables work well in practice but cannot be considered optimal anymore.


A third construction method: p-to-e (and e-to-p) calibration

There exist functions that convert p-values into e-values. Such functions are called ''p-to-e calibrators''. Formally, a calibrator is a nonnegative decreasing function f :
, 1 The comma is a punctuation mark that appears in several variants in different languages. It has the same shape as an apostrophe or single closing quotation mark () in many typefaces, but it differs from them in being placed on the baseline o ...
\rightarrow , \infty/math> which, when applied to a p-variable (a random variable whose value is a p-value), yields an e-variable. A calibrator f is said to dominate another calibrator g if f \geq g, and this domination is strict if the inequality is strict. An admissible calibrator is one that is not strictly dominated by any other calibrator. One can show that for a function to be a calibrator, it must have an integral of at most 1 over the uniform probability measure. One family of admissible calibrators is given by the set of functions \ with f_\kappa(p) := \kappa p^. Another calibrator is given by integrating out \kappa: : \int_0^1 \kappa p^ d\kappa = \frac Conversely, an e-to-p calibrator transforms e-values back into p-variables. Interestingly, the following calibrator dominates all other e-to-p calibrators: : f(t) := \min(1, 1/t). While of theoretical importance, calibration is not much used in the practical design of e-variables since the resulting e-variables are often far from growth-optimal for any given H_1.


E-Processes


Definition

Now consider data X_1, X_2, \ldots arriving sequentially, constituting a
discrete-time stochastic process In probability theory and related fields, a stochastic () or random process is a mathematical object usually defined as a family of random variables. Stochastic processes are widely used as mathematical models of systems and phenomena that appea ...
. Let E_1, E_2, \ldots be another discrete-time process where for each n, E_n can be written as a (measurable) function of the first (X_1, \ldots, X_n) outcomes. We call E_1, E_2, \ldots an e-process if for any
stopping time In probability theory, in particular in the study of stochastic processes, a stopping time (also Markov time, Markov moment, optional stopping time or optional time ) is a specific type of “random time”: a random variable whose value is inter ...
\tau, E_ is an e-variable, i.e. for all P \in H_0: _P E_ \leq 1 . In basic cases, the stopping time can be defined by any rule that determines, at each sample size n , based only on the data observed so far, whether to stop collecting data or not. For example, this could be "stop when you have seen four consecutive outcomes larger than 1", "stop at n=100 ", or the level-\alpha -aggressive rule, "stop as soon as you can reject at level \alpha -level, i.e. at the smallest n such that E_n \geq 1/\alpha ", and so on. With e-processes, we obtain an e-variable with any such rule. Crucially, the data analyst may not know the rule used for stopping. For example, her boss may tell her to stop data collecting and she may not know exactly why - nevertheless, she gets a valid e-variable and Type-I error control. This is in sharp contrast to data analysis based on p-values (which becomes invalid if stopping rules are not determined in advance) or in classical Wald-style
sequential analysis In statistics, sequential analysis or sequential hypothesis testing is statistical analysis where the sample size is not fixed in advance. Instead data are evaluated as they are collected, and further sampling is stopped in accordance with a pre- ...
(which works with data of varying length but again, with stopping times that need to be determined in advance). In more complex cases, the stopping time has to be defined relative to some slightly reduced filtration, but this is not a big restriction in practice. In particular, the level-\alpha -aggressive rule is always allowed. Because of this validity under optional stopping, e-processes are the fundamental building block of confidence sequences, also known as anytime-valid confidence intervals. Technically, e-processes are generalizations of test supermartingales, which are nonnegative supermartingales with starting value 1: any test supermartingale constitutes an e-process but not vice versa.


Construction

E-processes can be constructed in a number of ways. Often, one starts with an e-value S_i for X_i whose definition is allowed to depend on previous data, i.e., for all P \in H_0: _P X_1, \ldots, X_ \leq 1 (again, in complex testing problems this definition needs to be modified a bit using reduced filtrations). Then the product process M_1, M_2, \ldots with M_n = E_1 \times E_2 \cdots \times E_n is a test supermartingale, and hence also an e-process (note that we already used this construction in the example described under "e-values as bets" above: for fixed \lambda , the e-values E_ were not dependent on past-data, but by using \lambda = \breve, X^ depending on the past, they became dependent on past data). Another way to construct an e-process is to use the universal inference construction described above for sample sizes 1, 2, \ldots The resulting sequence of e-values E_1, E_2, \ldots will then always be an e-process.


History

Historically, e-values implicitly appear as building blocks of nonnegative supermartingales in the pioneering work on anytime-valid confidence methods by well-known mathematician
Herbert Robbins Herbert Ellis Robbins (January 12, 1915 – February 12, 2001) was an American mathematician and statistician. He did research in topology, measure theory, statistics, and a variety of other fields. He was the co-author, with Richard Co ...
and some of his students. The first time e-values (or something very much like them) are treated as a quantity of independent interest is by another well-known mathematician,
Leonid Levin Leonid Anatolievich Levin ( ; russian: Леони́д Анато́льевич Ле́вин; uk, Леоні́д Анато́лійович Ле́він; born November 2, 1948) is a Soviet-American mathematician and computer scientist. He is kn ...
, in 1976, within the theory of algorithmic randomness. With the exception of contributions by pioneer V. Vovk in various papers with various collaborators (e.g.), and an independent re-invention of the concept in an entirely different field, the concept did not catch on at all until 2019, when, within just a few months, several pioneering papers by several research groups appeared on arXiv (the corresponding journal publications referenced below sometimes coming years later). In these, the concept was finally given a proper name ("S-Value" and "E-Value"; in later versions of their paper, also adapted "E-Value"); describing their general properties, two generic ways to construct them, and their intimate relation to betting). Since then, interest by researchers around the world has been surging. In 2023 the first overview paper on "safe, anytime-valid methods", in which e-values play a central role, appeared.


References

{{reflist Statistical hypothesis testing Statistical concepts Statistics Probability theory