Construction of the real numbers
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematics, there are several equivalent ways of defining the
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a ''continuous'' one-dimensional quantity such as a distance, duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that values can have arbitrarily small variations. Every ...
s. One of them is that they form a
complete ordered field In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a ''continuous'' one-dimensional quantity such as a distance, duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that values can have arbitrarily small variations. Every r ...
that does not contain any smaller complete ordered field. Such a definition does not prove that such a complete ordered field exists, and the existence proof consists of constructing a mathematical structure that satisfies the definition. The article presents several such constructions. They are equivalent in the sense that, given the result of any two such constructions, there is a unique
isomorphism In mathematics, an isomorphism is a structure-preserving mapping between two structures of the same type that can be reversed by an inverse mapping. Two mathematical structures are isomorphic if an isomorphism exists between them. The word i ...
of
ordered field In mathematics, an ordered field is a field together with a total ordering of its elements that is compatible with the field operations. The basic example of an ordered field is the field of real numbers, and every Dedekind-complete ordered fiel ...
between them. This results from the above definition and is independent of particular constructions. These isomorphisms allow identifying the results of the constructions, and, in practice, to forget which construction has been chosen.


Axiomatic definitions

An axiomatic definition of the real numbers consists of defining them as the elements of a complete ordered field. This means the following: The real numbers form a
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
, commonly denoted \mathbb, containing two distinguished elements denoted 0 and 1, and on which are defined two binary operations and one binary relation; the operations are called ''addition'' and ''multiplication'' of real numbers and denoted respectively with and ; the binary relation is ''inequality'', denoted \le. Moreover, the following properties called axioms must be satisfied. The existence of such a structure is a
theorem In mathematics, a theorem is a statement that has been proved, or can be proved. The ''proof'' of a theorem is a logical argument that uses the inference rules of a deductive system to establish that the theorem is a logical consequence of t ...
, which is proved by constructing such a structure. A consequence of the axioms is that this structure is unique up to an isomorphism, and thus, the real numbers can be used and manipulated, without referring to the method of construction.


Axioms

# \mathbb is a
field Field may refer to: Expanses of open ground * Field (agriculture), an area of land used for agricultural purposes * Airfield, an aerodrome that lacks the infrastructure of an airport * Battlefield * Lawn, an area of mowed grass * Meadow, a grass ...
under addition and multiplication. In other words, #* For all ''x'', ''y'', and ''z'' in \mathbb, ''x'' + (''y'' + ''z'') = (''x'' + ''y'') + ''z'' and ''x'' × (''y'' × ''z'') = (''x'' × ''y'') × ''z''. (
associativity In mathematics, the associative property is a property of some binary operations, which means that rearranging the parentheses in an expression will not change the result. In propositional logic, associativity is a valid rule of replacement ...
of addition and multiplication) #* For all ''x'' and ''y'' in \mathbb, ''x'' + ''y'' = ''y'' + ''x'' and ''x'' × ''y'' = ''y'' × ''x''. ( commutativity of addition and multiplication) #* For all ''x'', ''y'', and ''z'' in \mathbb, ''x'' × (''y'' + ''z'') = (''x'' × ''y'') + (''x'' × ''z''). (
distributivity In mathematics, the distributive property of binary operations generalizes the distributive law, which asserts that the equality x \cdot (y + z) = x \cdot y + x \cdot z is always true in elementary algebra. For example, in elementary arithmeti ...
of multiplication over addition) #* For all ''x'' in \mathbb, ''x'' + 0 = ''x''. (existence of additive
identity Identity may refer to: * Identity document * Identity (philosophy) * Identity (social science) * Identity (mathematics) Arts and entertainment Film and television * ''Identity'' (1987 film), an Iranian film * ''Identity'' (2003 film), ...
) #* 0 is not equal to 1, and for all ''x'' in \mathbb, ''x'' × 1 = ''x''. (existence of multiplicative identity) #* For every ''x'' in \mathbb, there exists an element −''x'' in \mathbb, such that ''x'' + (−''x'') = 0. (existence of additive inverses) #* For every ''x'' ≠ 0 in \mathbb, there exists an element ''x''−1 in \mathbb, such that ''x'' × ''x''−1 = 1. (existence of multiplicative inverses) # \mathbb is
totally ordered In mathematics, a total or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( reflexive ...
for \leq. In other words, #* For all ''x'' in \mathbb, ''x'' ≤ ''x''. ( reflexivity) #* For all ''x'' and ''y'' in \mathbb, if ''x'' ≤ ''y'' and ''y'' ≤ ''x'', then ''x'' = ''y''. (
antisymmetry In linguistics, antisymmetry is a syntactic theory presented in Richard S. Kayne's 1994 monograph ''The Antisymmetry of Syntax''. It asserts that grammatical hierarchies in natural language follow a universal order, namely specifier-head-comple ...
) #* For all ''x'', ''y'', and ''z'' in \mathbb, if ''x'' ≤ ''y'' and ''y'' ≤ ''z'', then ''x'' ≤ ''z''. ( transitivity) #* For all ''x'' and ''y'' in \mathbb, ''x'' ≤ ''y'' or ''y'' ≤ ''x''. ( totality) # Addition and multiplication are compatible with the order. In other words, #* For all ''x'', ''y'' and ''z'' in \mathbb, if ''x'' ≤ ''y'', then ''x'' + ''z'' ≤ ''y'' + ''z''. (preservation of order under addition) #* For all ''x'' and ''y'' in \mathbb, if 0 ≤ ''x'' and 0 ≤ ''y'', then 0 ≤ ''x'' × ''y'' (preservation of order under multiplication) # The order ≤ is ''complete'' in the following sense: every non-empty subset of \mathbb that is bounded above has a
least upper bound In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; plural infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is a greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. Consequently, the term ''greatest lo ...
. In other words, #* If ''A'' is a non-empty subset of \mathbb, and if ''A'' has an
upper bound In mathematics, particularly in order theory, an upper bound or majorant of a subset of some preordered set is an element of that is greater than or equal to every element of . Dually, a lower bound or minorant of is defined to be an eleme ...
in \R, then ''A'' has a least upper bound ''u'', such that for every upper bound ''v'' of ''A'', ''u'' ≤ ''v''.


On the least upper bound property

Axiom 4, which requires the order to be
Dedekind-complete In mathematics, the least-upper-bound property (sometimes called completeness or supremum property or l.u.b. property) is a fundamental property of the real numbers. More generally, a partially ordered set has the least-upper-bound property if eve ...
, implies the
Archimedean property In abstract algebra and analysis, the Archimedean property, named after the ancient Greek mathematician Archimedes of Syracuse, is a property held by some algebraic structures, such as ordered or normed groups, and fields. The property, typica ...
. The axiom is crucial in the characterization of the reals. For example, the totally
ordered field In mathematics, an ordered field is a field together with a total ordering of its elements that is compatible with the field operations. The basic example of an ordered field is the field of real numbers, and every Dedekind-complete ordered fiel ...
of the rational numbers Q satisfy the first three axioms, but not the fourth. In other words, models of the rational numbers are also models of the first three axioms. Note that the axiom is
nonfirstorderizable In formal logic, nonfirstorderizability is the inability of a natural-language statement to be adequately captured by a formula of first-order logic. Specifically, a statement is nonfirstorderizable if there is no formula of first-order logic which ...
, as it expresses a statement about collections of reals and not just individual such numbers. As such, the reals are not given by a first-order logic theory.


On models

A ''model of real numbers'' is a mathematical structure that satisfies the above axioms. Several models are given below. Any two models are isomorphic; so, the real numbers are unique up to isomorphisms. Saying that any two models are isomorphic means that for any two models (\mathbb, 0_\R, 1_\R, +_\R, \times_\R, \le_\R) and (S, 0_S, 1_S, +_S, \times_S, \le_S), there is a bijection f\colon\mathbb\to S that preserves both the field operations and the order. Explicitly, * is both injective and surjective. * and . * and , for all and in \mathbb. *
if and only if In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (shortened as "iff") is a biconditional logical connective between statements, where either both statements are true or both are false. The connective is b ...
, for all and in \mathbb.


Tarski's axiomatization of the reals

An alternative synthetic axiomatization of the real numbers and their arithmetic was given by
Alfred Tarski Alfred Tarski (, born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician a ...
, consisting of only the 8 axioms shown below and a mere four
primitive notion In mathematics, logic, philosophy, and formal systems, a primitive notion is a concept that is not defined in terms of previously-defined concepts. It is often motivated informally, usually by an appeal to intuition and everyday experience. In an ...
s: a
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
called ''the real numbers'', denoted \mathbb, a binary relation over \mathbb called ''order'', denoted by the
infix operator Infix notation is the notation commonly used in arithmetical and logical formulae and statements. It is characterized by the placement of operators between operands—" infixed operators"—such as the plus sign in . Usage Binary relations a ...
<, a binary operation over \mathbb called ''addition'', denoted by the infix operator +, and the constant 1. ''Axioms of order'' (primitives: \mathbb, <): Axiom 1. If ''x'' < ''y'', then not ''y'' < ''x''. That is, "<" is an
asymmetric relation In mathematics, an asymmetric relation is a binary relation R on a set X where for all a, b \in X, if a is related to b then b is ''not'' related to a. Formal definition A binary relation on X is any subset R of X \times X. Given a, b \in X, ...
. Axiom 2. If ''x'' < ''z'', there exists a ''y'' such that ''x'' < ''y'' and ''y'' < ''z''. In other words, "<" is
dense Density (volumetric mass density or specific mass) is the substance's mass per unit of volume. The symbol most often used for density is ''ρ'' (the lower case Greek letter rho), although the Latin letter ''D'' can also be used. Mathematically ...
in \mathbb. Axiom 3. "<" is
Dedekind-complete In mathematics, the least-upper-bound property (sometimes called completeness or supremum property or l.u.b. property) is a fundamental property of the real numbers. More generally, a partially ordered set has the least-upper-bound property if eve ...
. More formally, for all ''X'', ''Y'' ⊆ \mathbb, if for all ''x'' ∈ ''X'' and ''y'' ∈ ''Y'', ''x'' < ''y'', then there exists a ''z'' such that for all ''x'' ∈ ''X'' and ''y'' ∈ ''Y'', if ''z'' ≠ ''x'' and ''z'' ≠ ''y'', then ''x'' < ''z'' and ''z'' < ''y''. To clarify the above statement somewhat, let ''X'' ⊆ \mathbb and ''Y'' ⊆ \mathbb. We now define two common English verbs in a particular way that suits our purpose: :''X precedes Y'' if and only if for every ''x'' ∈ ''X'' and every ''y'' ∈ ''Y'', ''x'' < ''y''. :The real number ''z separates'' ''X'' and ''Y'' if and only if for every ''x'' ∈ ''X'' with ''x'' ≠ ''z'' and every ''y'' ∈ ''Y'' with ''y'' ≠ ''z'', ''x'' < ''z'' and ''z'' < ''y''. Axiom 3 can then be stated as: :"If a set of reals precedes another set of reals, then there exists at least one real number separating the two sets." ''Axioms of addition'' (primitives: \mathbb, <, +): Axiom 4. ''x'' + (''y'' + ''z'') = (''x'' + ''z'') + ''y''. Axiom 5. For all ''x'', ''y'', there exists a ''z'' such that ''x'' + ''z'' = ''y''. Axiom 6. If ''x'' + ''y'' < ''z'' + ''w'', then ''x'' < ''z'' or ''y'' < ''w''. ''Axioms for one'' (primitives: \mathbb, <, +, 1): Axiom 7. 1 ∈ \mathbb. Axiom 8. 1 < 1 + 1. These axioms imply that \mathbb is a
linearly ordered In mathematics, a total or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( reflexive) ...
abelian group In mathematics, an abelian group, also called a commutative group, is a group in which the result of applying the group operation to two group elements does not depend on the order in which they are written. That is, the group operation is comm ...
under addition with distinguished element 1. \mathbb is also
Dedekind-complete In mathematics, the least-upper-bound property (sometimes called completeness or supremum property or l.u.b. property) is a fundamental property of the real numbers. More generally, a partially ordered set has the least-upper-bound property if eve ...
and
divisible In mathematics, a divisor of an integer n, also called a factor of n, is an integer m that may be multiplied by some integer to produce n. In this case, one also says that n is a multiple of m. An integer n is divisible or evenly divisible by ...
.


Explicit constructions of models

We shall not prove that any models of the axioms are isomorphic. Such a proof can be found in any number of modern analysis or set theory textbooks. We will sketch the basic definitions and properties of a number of constructions, however, because each of these is important for both mathematical and historical reasons. The first three, due to
Georg Cantor Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( , ;  – January 6, 1918) was a German mathematician. He played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor established the importance of ...
/ Charles Méray, Richard Dedekind/
Joseph Bertrand Joseph Louis François Bertrand (; 11 March 1822 – 5 April 1900) was a French mathematician who worked in the fields of number theory, differential geometry, probability theory, economics and thermodynamics. Biography Joseph Bertrand was ...
and
Karl Weierstrass Karl Theodor Wilhelm Weierstrass (german: link=no, Weierstraß ; 31 October 1815 – 19 February 1897) was a German mathematician often cited as the "father of modern analysis". Despite leaving university without a degree, he studied mathematics ...
all occurred within a few years of each other. Each has advantages and disadvantages. A major motivation in all three cases was the instruction of mathematics students.


Construction from Cauchy sequences

A standard procedure to force all
Cauchy sequence In mathematics, a Cauchy sequence (; ), named after Augustin-Louis Cauchy, is a sequence whose elements become arbitrarily close to each other as the sequence progresses. More precisely, given any small positive distance, all but a finite numbe ...
s in a
metric space In mathematics, a metric space is a set together with a notion of '' distance'' between its elements, usually called points. The distance is measured by a function called a metric or distance function. Metric spaces are the most general set ...
to converge is adding new points to the metric space in a process called completion. \mathbb is defined as the completion of Q with respect to the metric , ''x''-''y'', , as will be detailed below (for completions of Q with respect to other metrics, see ''p''-adic numbers). Let ''R'' be the
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
of Cauchy sequences of rational numbers. That is, sequences : ''x''''1'', ''x''''2'', ''x''''3'',... of rational numbers such that for every rational , there exists an integer ''N'' such that for all natural numbers , . Here the vertical bars denote the absolute value. Cauchy sequences (''x''''n'') and (''y''''n'') can be added and multiplied as follows: : (''x''''n'') + (''y''''n'') = (''x''''n'' + ''y''''n'') : (''x''''n'') × (''y''''n'') = (''x''''n'' × ''y''''n''). Two Cauchy sequences are called ''equivalent'' if and only if the difference between them tends to zero. This defines an equivalence relation that is compatible with the operations defined above, and the set R of all equivalence classes can be shown to satisfy all axioms of the real numbers. We can
embed Embedded or embedding (alternatively imbedded or imbedding) may refer to: Science * Embedding, in mathematics, one instance of some mathematical object contained within another instance ** Graph embedding * Embedded generation, a distributed ge ...
Q into R by identifying the rational number ''r'' with the equivalence class of the sequence . Comparison between real numbers is obtained by defining the following comparison between Cauchy sequences: if and only if ''x'' is equivalent to ''y'' or there exists an integer ''N'' such that for all . By construction, every real number ''x'' is represented by a Cauchy sequence of rational numbers. This representation is far from unique; every rational sequence that converges to ''x'' is a representation of ''x''. This reflects the observation that one can often use different sequences to approximate the same real number. The only real number axiom that does not follow easily from the definitions is the completeness of ≤, i.e. the least upper bound property. It can be proved as follows: Let ''S'' be a non-empty subset of R and ''U'' be an upper bound for ''S''. Substituting a larger value if necessary, we may assume ''U'' is rational. Since ''S'' is non-empty, we can choose a rational number ''L'' such that for some ''s'' in ''S''. Now define sequences of rationals (''u''''n'') and (''l''''n'') as follows: :Set ''u''0 = ''U'' and ''l''0 = ''L''. For each ''n'' consider the number: :''m''''n'' = (''u''''n'' + ''l''''n'')/2 If ''m''''n'' is an upper bound for ''S'' set: : ''u''''n''+1 = ''m''''n'' and ''l''''n''+1 = ''l''''n'' Otherwise set: : ''l''''n''+1 = ''m''''n'' and ''u''''n''+1 = ''u''''n'' This defines two Cauchy sequences of rationals, and so we have real numbers and . It is easy to prove, by induction on ''n'' that: : ''u''''n'' is an upper bound for ''S'' for all ''n'' and: : ''l''''n'' is never an upper bound for ''S'' for any ''n'' Thus ''u'' is an upper bound for ''S''. To see that it is a least upper bound, notice that the limit of (''u''''n'' − ''l''''n'') is 0, and so ''l'' = ''u''. Now suppose is a smaller upper bound for ''S''. Since (''l''''n'') is monotonic increasing it is easy to see that for some ''n''. But ''l''''n'' is not an upper bound for S and so neither is ''b''. Hence ''u'' is a least upper bound for ''S'' and ≤ is complete. The usual
decimal notation The decimal numeral system (also called the base-ten positional numeral system and denary or decanary) is the standard system for denoting integer and non-integer numbers. It is the extension to non-integer numbers of the Hindu–Arabic numer ...
can be translated to Cauchy sequences in a natural way. For example, the notation π = 3.1415... means that π is the equivalence class of the Cauchy sequence (3, 3.1, 3.14, 3.141, 3.1415, ...). The equation 0.999... = 1 states that the sequences (0, 0.9, 0.99, 0.999,...) and (1, 1, 1, 1,...) are equivalent, i.e., their difference converges to 0. An advantage of constructing R as the completion of Q is that this construction is not specific to one example; it is used for other metric spaces as well.


Construction by Dedekind cuts

A
Dedekind cut In mathematics, Dedekind cuts, named after German mathematician Richard Dedekind but previously considered by Joseph Bertrand, are а method of construction of the real numbers from the rational numbers. A Dedekind cut is a partition of the r ...
in an ordered field is a partition of it, (''A'', ''B''), such that ''A'' is nonempty and closed downwards, ''B'' is nonempty and closed upwards, and ''A'' contains no
greatest element In mathematics, especially in order theory, the greatest element of a subset S of a partially ordered set (poset) is an element of S that is greater than every other element of S. The term least element is defined dually, that is, it is an elem ...
. Real numbers can be constructed as Dedekind cuts of rational numbers. For convenience we may take the lower set A\, as the representative of any given Dedekind cut (A, B)\,, since A completely determines B. By doing this we may think intuitively of a real number as being represented by the set of all smaller rational numbers. In more detail, a real number r is any subset of the set \textbf of rational numbers that fulfills the following conditions: # r is not empty # r \neq \textbf # r is closed downwards. In other words, for all x, y \in \textbf such that x < y, if y \in r then x \in r # r contains no greatest element. In other words, there is no x \in r such that for all y \in r, y \leq x * We form the set \textbf of real numbers as the set of all Dedekind cuts A of \textbf , and define a
total ordering In mathematics, a total or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( reflexive) ...
on the real numbers as follows: x \leq y\Leftrightarrow x \subseteq y * We
embed Embedded or embedding (alternatively imbedded or imbedding) may refer to: Science * Embedding, in mathematics, one instance of some mathematical object contained within another instance ** Graph embedding * Embedded generation, a distributed ge ...
the rational numbers into the reals by identifying the rational number q with the set of all smaller rational numbers \ . Since the rational numbers are
dense Density (volumetric mass density or specific mass) is the substance's mass per unit of volume. The symbol most often used for density is ''ρ'' (the lower case Greek letter rho), although the Latin letter ''D'' can also be used. Mathematically ...
, such a set can have no greatest element and thus fulfills the conditions for being a real number laid out above. * Addition. A + B := \ * Subtraction. A - B := \ where \textbf \setminus B denotes the
relative complement In set theory, the complement of a set , often denoted by (or ), is the set of elements not in . When all sets in the universe, i.e. all sets under consideration, are considered to be members of a given set , the absolute complement of is th ...
of B in \textbf, \ * Negation is a special case of subtraction: -B := \ * Defining multiplication is less straightforward. ** if A, B \geq 0 then A \times B := \ \cup \ ** if either A\, or B\, is negative, we use the identities A \times B = -(A \times -B) = -(-A \times B) = (-A \times -B) \, to convert A\, and/or B\, to positive numbers and then apply the definition above. * We define
division Division or divider may refer to: Mathematics *Division (mathematics), the inverse of multiplication *Division algorithm, a method for computing the result of mathematical division Military *Division (military), a formation typically consisting ...
in a similar manner: ** if A \geq 0 \mbox B > 0 then A / B := \ ** if either A\, or B\, is negative, we use the identities A / B = -(A / ) = -(-A / B)= -A / \, to convert A\, to a non-negative number and/or B\, to a positive number and then apply the definition above. * Supremum. If a nonempty set S of real numbers has any upper bound in \textbf, then it has a least upper bound in \textbf that is equal to \bigcup S. As an example of a Dedekind cut representing an
irrational number In mathematics, the irrational numbers (from in- prefix assimilated to ir- (negative prefix, privative) + rational) are all the real numbers that are not rational numbers. That is, irrational numbers cannot be expressed as the ratio of two inte ...
, we may take the positive square root of 2. This can be defined by the set A = \. It can be seen from the definitions above that A is a real number, and that A \times A = 2\,. However, neither claim is immediate. Showing that A\, is real requires showing that A has no greatest element, i.e. that for any positive rational x\, with x \times x < 2\,, there is a rational y\, with x and y \times y <2\,. The choice y=\frac\, works. Then A \times A \le 2 but to show equality requires showing that if r\, is any rational number with r < 2\,, then there is positive x\, in A with r. An advantage of this construction is that each real number corresponds to a unique cut. Furthermore, by relaxing the first two requirements of the definition of a cut, the
extended real number In mathematics, the affinely extended real number system is obtained from the real number system \R by adding two infinity elements: +\infty and -\infty, where the infinities are treated as actual numbers. It is useful in describing the algebra on ...
system may be obtained by associating -\infty with the empty set and \infty with all of \textbf.


Construction using hyperreal numbers

As in the
hyperreal number In mathematics, the system of hyperreal numbers is a way of treating infinite and infinitesimal (infinitely small but non-zero) quantities. The hyperreals, or nonstandard reals, *R, are an extension of the real numbers R that contains numbers ...
s, one constructs the *Q from the rational numbers by means of an
ultrafilter In the mathematical field of order theory, an ultrafilter on a given partially ordered set (or "poset") P is a certain subset of P, namely a maximal filter on P; that is, a proper filter on P that cannot be enlarged to a bigger proper filter o ...
. Here a hyperrational is by definition a ratio of two
hyperinteger In nonstandard analysis, a hyperinteger ''n'' is a hyperreal number that is equal to its own integer part. A hyperinteger may be either finite or infinite. A finite hyperinteger is an ordinary integer. An example of an infinite hyperinteger is g ...
s. Consider the
ring Ring may refer to: * Ring (jewellery), a round band, usually made of metal, worn as ornamental jewelry * To make a sound with a bell, and the sound made by a bell :(hence) to initiate a telephone connection Arts, entertainment and media Film and ...
''B'' of all limited (i.e. finite) elements in *Q. Then ''B'' has a unique
maximal ideal In mathematics, more specifically in ring theory, a maximal ideal is an ideal that is maximal (with respect to set inclusion) amongst all ''proper'' ideals. In other words, ''I'' is a maximal ideal of a ring ''R'' if there are no other ideals c ...
''I'', the infinitesimal numbers. The quotient ring ''B/I'' gives the
field Field may refer to: Expanses of open ground * Field (agriculture), an area of land used for agricultural purposes * Airfield, an aerodrome that lacks the infrastructure of an airport * Battlefield * Lawn, an area of mowed grass * Meadow, a grass ...
R of real numbers . Note that ''B'' is not an
internal set In mathematical logic, in particular in model theory and nonstandard analysis, an internal set is a set that is a member of a model. The concept of internal sets is a tool in formulating the transfer principle, which concerns the logical relation ...
in *Q. Note that this construction uses a non-principal ultrafilter over the set of natural numbers, the existence of which is guaranteed by the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
. It turns out that the maximal ideal respects the order on *Q. Hence the resulting field is an ordered field. Completeness can be proved in a similar way to the construction from the Cauchy sequences.


Construction from surreal numbers

Every ordered field can be embedded in the
surreal number In mathematics, the surreal number system is a totally ordered proper class containing the real numbers as well as infinite and infinitesimal numbers, respectively larger or smaller in absolute value than any positive real number. The surreals ...
s. The real numbers form a maximal subfield that is Archimedean (meaning that no real number is infinitely large or infinitely small). This embedding is not unique, though it can be chosen in a canonical way.


Construction from integers (Eudoxus reals)

A relatively less known construction allows to define real numbers using only the additive group of integers \mathbb with different versions. The construction has been formally verified by the IsarMathLib project. and refer to this construction as the ''Eudoxus reals'', named after an ancient Greek astronomer and mathematician Eudoxus of Cnidus. Let an almost homomorphism be a map f:\mathbb\to\mathbb such that the set \ is finite. (Note that f(n) = \lfloor \alpha n\rfloor is an almost homomorphism for every \alpha \in \mathbb .) Almost homomorphisms form an abelian group under pointwise addition. We say that two almost homomorphisms f,g are almost equal if the set \ is finite. This defines an equivalence relation on the set of almost homomorphisms. Real numbers are defined as the equivalence classes of this relation. Alternatively, the almost homomorphisms taking only finitely many values form a subgroup, and the underlying additive group of the real number is the quotient group. To add real numbers defined this way we add the almost homomorphisms that represent them. Multiplication of real numbers corresponds to functional composition of almost homomorphisms. If /math> denotes the real number represented by an almost homomorphism f we say that 0\leq /math> if f is bounded or f takes an infinite number of positive values on \mathbb^+. This defines the
linear order In mathematics, a total or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( reflexive) ...
relation on the set of real numbers constructed this way.


Other constructions

write: "Few mathematical structures have undergone as many revisions or have been presented in as many guises as the real numbers. Every generation reexamines the reals in the light of its values and mathematical objectives." A number of other constructions have been given, by: * , * * , For an overview, see . As a reviewer of one noted: "The details are all included, but as usual they are tedious and not too instructive." (84j:26002) review of .


See also

* *


References


Bibliography

* * * also at http://alexandria.tue.nl/repository/freearticles/597556.pdf * * * * * * * * * * * * {{DEFAULTSORT:Construction Of The Real Numbers Real numbers Constructivism (mathematics)